BIOCENTRISM

Home > Other > BIOCENTRISM > Page 7
BIOCENTRISM Page 7

by Robert Lanza


  limit is not being violated because nobody can use EPR correlations

  to send information because the behavior of the sending particle is

  always random. Current research is directed toward practical rather

  than philosophical concerns: the aim is to harness this bizarre

  behavior to create new ultra-powerful quantum computers that, as

  Wineland put it, “carry all the weird baggage that comes with quan-

  tum mechanics.”

  Through it all, the experiments of the past decade truly seem to

  prove that Einstein’s insistence on “locality”—meaning that nothing

  w H e N T o m o r r o w C o m e s b e f o r e y e s T e r d a y 5 3

  can influence anything else at superluminal speeds—is wrong.

  Rather, the entities we observe are floating in a field—a field of

  mind, biocentrism maintains—that is not limited by the external

  space-time Einstein theorized a century ago.

  No one should imagine that when biocentrism points to quan-

  tum theory as one major area of support, it is just a single aspect of

  quantum phenomena. Bell’s Theorem of 1964, shown experimen-

  tally to be true over and over in the intervening years, does more

  than merely demolish all vestiges of Einstein’s (and others’) hopes

  that locality can be maintained.

  Before Bell, it was still considered possible (though increas-

  ingly iffy) that local realism—an objective independent universe—

  could be the truth. Before Bell, many still clung to the millennia-old

  assumption that physical states exist before they are measured. Before Bell, it was still widely believed that particles have definite attributes and values independent of the act of measuring. And, finally,

  thanks to Einstein’s demonstrations that no information can travel

  faster than light, it was assumed that if observers are sufficiently far

  apart, a measurement by one has no effect on the measurement by

  the other.

  All of the above are now finished, for keeps.

  In addition to the above, three separate major areas of quantum

  theory make sense biocentrically but are bewildering otherwise.

  We’ll discuss much of this at greater length in a moment, but let’s

  begin simply by listing them. The first is the entanglement just cited,

  which is a connectedness between two objects so intimate that they

  behave as one, instantaneously and forever, even if they are sepa-

  rated by the width of galaxies. Its spookiness becomes clearer in the

  classical two-slit experiment.

  The second is complementarity. This means that small objects

  can display themselves in one way or another but not both, depend-

  ing on what the observer does; indeed, the object doesn’t have an

  existence in a specific location and with a particular motion. Only

  the observer’s knowledge and actions cause it to come into existence

  in some place or with some particular animation. Many pairs of such

  5 4

  b i o C e N T r i s m

  complementary attributes exist. An object can be a wave or a particle

  but not both, it can inhabit a specific position or display motion but

  not both, and so on. Its reality depends solely on the observer and

  his experiment.

  The third quantum theory attribute that supports biocentrism

  is wave-function collapse, that is, the idea that a physical particle or

  bit of light only exists in a blurry state of possibility until its wave-

  function collapses at the time of observation, and only then actu-

  ally assumes a definite existence. This is the standard understanding

  of what goes on in quantum theory experiments according to the

  Copenhagen interpretation, although competing ideas still exist, as

  we’ll see shortly.

  The experiments of Heisenberg, Bell, Gisin, and Wineland, for-

  tunately, call us back to experience itself, the immediacy of the here

  and now. Before matter can peep forth—as a pebble, a snowflake, or

  even a subatomic particle—it has to be observed by a living creature.

  This “act of observation” becomes vivid in the famous two-hole

  experiment, which in turn goes straight to the core of quantum phys-

  ics. It’s been performed so many times, with so many variations, it’s

  conclusively proven that if one watches a subatomic particle or a bit

  of light pass through slits on a barrier, it behaves like a particle, and

  creates solid-looking bam-bam-bam hits behind the individual slits

  on the final barrier that measures the impacts. Like a tiny bullet, it

  logically passes through one or the other hole. But if the scientists

  do not observe the particle, then it exhibits the behavior of waves

  that retain the right to exhibit all possibilities, including somehow passing through both holes at the same time (even though it cannot split

  itself up)—and then creating the kind of rippling pattern that only

  waves produce.

  Dubbed quantum weirdness, this wave–particle duality has befud-

  dled scientists for decades. Some of the greatest physicists have

  described it as impossible to intuit, impossible to formulate into

  words, impossible to visualize, and as invalidating common sense

  and ordinary perception. Science has essentially conceded that quan-

  tum physics is incomprehensible outside of complex mathematics.

  w H e N T o m o r r o w C o m e s b e f o r e y e s T e r d a y 5 5

  How can quantum physics be so impervious to metaphor, visualiza-

  tion, and language?

  Amazingly, if we accept a life-created reality at face value, it all

  becomes simple and straightforward to understand. The key ques-

  tion is “waves of what?” Back in 1926, German physicist Max Born

  demonstrated that quantum waves are waves of probability, not waves

  of material, as his colleague Schrödinger had theorized . They are

  statistical predictions. Thus, a wave of probability is nothing but a

  likely outcome. In fact, outside of that idea, the wave is not there!

  It’s intangible. As Nobel physicist John Wheeler once said, “No phe-

  nomenon is a real phenomenon until it is an observed phenomenon.”

  Note that we are talking about discrete objects like photons or

  electrons, rather than collections of myriad objects, such as, say, a

  train. Obviously, we can get a schedule and arrive to pick up a friend

  at a station and be fairly confident that his train actually existed

  during our absence, even if we did not personally observe it. (One

  reason for this is that as the considered object gets bigger, its wave-

  length gets smaller. Once we get into the macroscopic realm, the

  waves are too close together to be noticed or measured. They are still

  there, however.)

  With small discrete particles, however, if they are not being

  observed, they cannot be thought of as having any real existence—

  either duration or a position in space. Until the mind sets the scaf-

  folding of an object in place, until it actually lays down the threads

  (somewhere in the haze of probabilities that represent the object’s

  range of possible values), it cannot be thought of as being either here

  or there. Thus, quantum waves merely define the potential location a particle can occupy. When a scientist observe
s a particle, it will

  be found within the statistical probability for that event to occur.

  That’s what the wave defines. A wave of probability isn’t an event

  or a phenomenon, it is a description of the likelihood of an event or phenomenon occurring. Nothing happens until the event is actually

  observed.

  In our double-slit experiment, it is easy to insist that each pho-

  ton or electron—because both these objects are indivisible—must

  5 6

  b i o C e N T r i s m

  go through one slit or the other and ask, which way does a particu-

  lar photon really go? Many brilliant physicists have devised experi-

  ments that proposed to measure the “which-way” information of a

  particle’s path on its route to contributing to an interference pattern.

  They all arrived at the astonishing conclusion, however, that it is not

  possible to observe both which-way information and the interference

  pattern. One can set up a measurement to watch which slit a photon

  goes through, and find that the photon goes through one slit and

  not the other. However, once this is kind of measurement is set up,

  the photons instead strike the screen in one spot, and totally lack

  the ripple-interference design; in short, they will demonstrate them-

  selves to be particles, not waves. The entire double-slit experiment

  and all its true amazing weirdness will be laid out with illustrations

  in the next chapter.

  Apparently, watching it go through the barrier makes the wave-

  function collapse then and there, and the particle loses its freedom

  to probabilistically take both choices available to it instead of having

  to choose one or the other.

  And it still gets screwier. Once we accept that it is not possible to gain both the which-way information and the interference pattern,

  we might take it even further. Let’s say we now work with sets of

  photons that are entangled. They can travel far from each other, but

  their behavior will never lose their correlation.

  So now we let the two photons, call them y and z, go off in

  two different directions, and we’ll set up the double-slit experi-

  ment again. We already know that photon y will mysteriously pass

  through both slits and create an interference pattern if we measure

  nothing about it before it reaches the detection screen. Except, in

  our new setup, we’ve created an apparatus that lets us measure the

  which-way path of its twin, photon z, miles away. Bingo: As soon as

  we activate this apparatus for measuring its twin, photon y instantly

  “knows” that we can deduce its own path (because it will always do

  the opposite or complementary thing as its twin). Photon y suddenly

  stops showing an interference pattern the instant we turn on the

  measuring apparatus for far-away photon z, even though we didn’t

  w H e N T o m o r r o w C o m e s b e f o r e y e s T e r d a y 5 7

  bother y in the least. And this would be true—instantly, in real

  time—even if y and z lay on opposite sides of the galaxy.

  And, though it doesn’t seem possible, it gets spookier still. If we

  now let photon y hit the slits and the measuring screen first, and a split second later measure its twin far away, we should have fooled

  the quantum laws. The first photon already ran its course before

  we troubled its distant twin. We should therefore be able to learn

  both photons’ polarization and been treated to an interference pat-

  tern. Right? Wrong. When this experiment is performed, we get a

  non-interference pattern. The y-photon stops taking paths through

  both slits retroactively; the interference is gone. Apparently, photon y somehow knew that we would eventually find out its polarization, even though its twin had not yet encountered our polarization-detection apparatus.

  What gives? What does this say about time, about any real exis-

  tence of sequence, about present and future? What does it say about

  space and separation? What must we conclude about our own roles

  and how our knowledge influences actual events miles away, with-

  out any passage of time? How can these bits of light know what will

  happen in their future? How can they communicate instantaneously,

  faster than light? Obviously, the twins are connected in a special

  way that doesn’t break no matter how far apart they are, and in a

  way that is independent of time, space, or even causality. And, more

  to our point, what does this say about observation and the “field of

  mind” in which all these experiments occur?

  meaning . . . ?

  The Copenhagen interpretation, born in the 1920s in the fever-

  ish minds of Heisenberg and Bohr, bravely set out to explain the

  bizarre results of the quantum theory experiments, sort of. But, for

  most, it was too unsettling a shift in worldview to accept in full.

  In a nutshell, the Copenhagen interpretation was the first to claim

  what John Bell and others substantiated some forty years later: that

  before a measurement is made, a subatomic particle doesn’t really

  5 8

  b i o C e N T r i s m

  exist in a definite place or have an actual motion. Instead, it dwells

  in a strange nether realm without actually being anywhere in partic-

  ular. This blurry indeterminate existence ends only when its wave-

  function collapses. It took only a few years before Copenhagen adher-

  ents were realizing that nothing is real unless it’s perceived. Copenhagen makes perfect sense if biocentrism is reality; otherwise, it’s a

  total enigma.

  If we want some sort of alternative to the idea of an object’s wave-

  function collapsing just because someone looked at it, and avoid that

  kind of spooky action at a distance, we might jump aboard Copen-

  hagen’s competitor, the “Many Worlds Interpretation” (MWI), which

  says that everything that can happen, does happen. The universe

  continually branches out like budding yeast into an infinitude of

  universes that contain every possibility, no matter how remote. You

  now occupy one of the universes. But there are innumerable other

  universes in which another “you,” who once studied photography

  instead of accounting, did indeed move to Paris and marry that girl

  you once met while hitchhiking. According to this view, embraced

  by such modern theorists as Stephen Hawking, our universe has no

  superpositions or contradictions at all, no spooky action, and no

  non-locality: seemingly contradictory quantum phenomena, along

  with all the personal choices you think you didn’t make, exist today

  in countless parallel universes.

  Which is true? All the entangled experiments of the past decades

  point increasingly toward confirming Copenhagen more than any-

  thing else. And this, as we’ve said, strongly supports biocentrism.

  Some physicists, like Einstein, have suggested that “hidden vari-

  ables” (that is, things not yet discovered or understood) might ulti-

  mately explain the strange counterlogical quantum behavior. Maybe

  the experimental apparatus itself contaminates the behavior of the

  objects being observed, in ways no one has yet conceived. Obviously,

  there’s no possible rebuttal to a suggestion that an u
nknown variable

  is producing some result because the phrase itself is as unhelpful as

  a politician’s election promise.

  w H e N T o m o r r o w C o m e s b e f o r e y e s T e r d a y 5 9

  At present, the implications of these experiments are conve-

  niently downplayed in the public mind because, until recently,

  quantum behavior was limited to the microscopic world. However,

  this has no basis in reason, and more importantly, it is starting to

  be challenged in laboratories around the world. New experiments

  carried out with huge molecules called buckyballs show that quan-

  tum reality extends into the macroscopic world we live in. In 2005,

  KHCO crystals exhibited quantum entanglement ridges one-half

  3

  inch high—visible signs of behavior nudging into everyday levels

  of discernment. In fact, an exciting new experiment has just been

  proposed (so-called scaled-up superposition) that would furnish the

  most powerful evidence to date that the biocentric view of the world

  is correct at the level of living organisms.

  To which we would say—of course.

  And so we add a third principle of Biocentrism:

  First Principle of Biocentrism: What we perceive as reality is a

  process that involves our consciousness.

  Second Principle of Biocentrism: Our external and internal per-

  ceptions are inextricably intertwined. They are different sides of the

  same coin and cannot be separated.

  Third Principle of Biocentrism: The behavior of subatomic

  particles—indeed all particles and objects—is inextricably

  linked to the presence of an observer. Without the presence of a

  conscious observer, they at best exist in an undetermined state

  of probability waves.

  the most AmAzIng

  8

  experIment

  Quantum theory has unfortunately become a catch-all phrase

  for trying to prove various kinds of New Age nonsense. It’s

  unlikely that the authors of the many books making wacky

  claims of time travel or mind control, and who use quantum theory

  as “proof” have the slightest knowledge of physics or could explain

  even the rudiments of quantum theory. The popular 2004 film, What

  the Bleep Do We Know? is a good case in point. The movie starts out claiming quantum theory has revolutionized our thinking—which

 

‹ Prev