Lovers of Sophia

Home > Other > Lovers of Sophia > Page 3
Lovers of Sophia Page 3

by Jason Reza Jorjani


  anything, indulge any lust, maneuver oneself into any position of

  power that commands respect? Suppose one could become invisible

  while secretly committing every manner of criminal and unethical

  deed and that doing so allowed one to publicly command ever more

  respect, and even to be praised as virtuous by the masses. Imagine

  also that persecution and even a torture worse than death were

  the reward for actual y being virtuous, rather than merely seeming

  so while raping and plundering in stealth. Who would prefer to

  actual y be virtuous rather than seem so while being wicked? Even if

  we grant that being ethical requires habituation from childhood and

  the mirror of personal relationships throughout life to sustain, could the god-like virtue required to be this ethical be a matter of habit or having the right kind of friends?

  If there are individuals who seem to have a transcendent virtue,

  people who are ethical y exemplary, it also seems that for any one

  of them there are many others who are at the opposite extreme:

  people who no amount of proper habituation can render ethical and

  who are incapable of entering into any but the crassest and most

  convenient friendships. We are going to contemplate whether, as

  Plato and Aristotle think, sometimes entire societies are dominated

  by such people – societies so viciously oppressive that the cultivation 23

  lovers of sophia

  of virtue is impossible in them. If a society needs exemplary

  individuals even in order to cultivate ethical habits in others, doesn’t it make a very great difference whether the political system is one

  that encourages exemplary leadership or one where the most vicious

  elements in a society are allowed to harness the vilest impulses in

  the masses to create conditions that make life impossible for ethical

  paragons. Can a true democracy ever be ethical?

  The United States of America is often mistakenly considered a

  democracy. Even some of our recent Presidents have spoken as if

  this is a democracy and one of them called for spreading the fire

  of democracy around the world. Wel , we have seen what kind of

  fire that policy has spread in the Middle East. In fact, the United

  States is not a true democracy and most of the founding fathers

  of America considered “democracy” a dirty word. They were

  students of classical Greek and Roman thinkers like Plato, Aristotle,

  Xenophon, and Cicero who reasoned that democracy was pretty

  near to the worst form of government there is. Only tyranny is

  more vicious than democracy from a classical perspective, and the

  founding fathers viewed democracy as a “tyranny of the majority.”

  Those with a poor education in history think that democracy was

  some shining accomplishment of the Greeks, when in fact almost all

  Greek intellectuals were harsh critics of democracy.

  Analysis of the Declaration of Independence, the Bill of Rights, and the various writings (including the private letters) of the founding

  fathers make it clear that rather than being a democracy, this nation

  is grounded on the concept of Natural Right – sometimes also

  known as the Rights of Man. This has been more recently reframed

  by the United Nations as Universal Human Rights but in a way that

  is less clear and coherent than the Natural Right conception of the

  founders. The founders of the American constitutional Republic,

  and by the way also some of their French revolutionary colleagues,

  saw Natural Right as a universal ethical standard. In his book The Rights of Man, Thomas Paine, who set off the American Revolution with his more widely read pamphlet Common Sense, explicitly and publicly states what others of the founders privately believed: Natural 24

  jason reza jorjani

  Right is so universal that it applies even to all of the other intelligent beings throughout the Universe, so that the bell of liberty rung by

  the American Revolution is not even limited to all of the oppressed

  individuals on the planet Earth – it reverberates throughout the

  Cosmos.

  For Deists and Freemasons such as Benjamin Franklin, Thomas

  Jefferson, George Washington, and other key founders, the “Creator”

  in the Declaration of Independence was not the God of the Bible

  but the macrocosmic rational order reflected in the microcosm

  of reason that allows us to perfect ourselves. This relationship

  between a reason inherent in Nature at large and the rational faculty

  characteristic of human nature is at the core of the idea that we have certain rights that are “inalienable” – in other words, not given by

  any government and therefore not justly ignored, withdrawn, or

  violated by any government. Even if a 99% majority of people in this

  country were to vote through their elected representatives to strip

  individuals of their natural rights, their votes would be null and void.

  Military officers who have sworn to uphold the constitution could

  legitimately disempower a congress or President that acknowledged

  such a majority vote. So, again, the United States is very far from

  a democracy. It is a constitutional government dedicated to the

  protection of the Natural Rights of Man, where “man” means not

  just men and women but each and every intelligent being in the

  Universe.

  This basic conception of Natural Right or a universal Ethics was

  most careful y crystalized by Immanuel Kant in his argument for a

  Categorical Imperative. In the third unit, we will look at how Kant

  thinks that his universal ethics would be truly universal, namely

  that it would apply to every form of extraterrestrial intelligence

  regardless of their biological differences from Homo sapiens. How

  tenable is this claim considering what we now know about evolution?

  Couldn’t there be forms of extraterrestrial intelligence that are much more similar to terrestrial insects with a hive mind than they are to

  humans on Earth, and given the horrifying amorality of interactions

  within insect colonies wouldn’t it be absurd to claim that the beings

  25

  lovers of sophia

  constituting them would be bound by the ethical standards of

  anything like the Bill of Rights or the Universal Declaration of Human Rights?

  Furthermore, aren’t emergent biotechnologies giving us the

  power to so radical y alter the human genome that a speciation of

  our own race could present us with beings of a common ancestry

  that are as alien to us as any extraterrestrials? In the second half of the third unit we will look together with Francis Fukuyama at how

  the technologies of embryo selection, cloning, genetic engineering,

  and genetic hybridization call into question whether there is any

  essence or metaphysical nature that we all share as humans in the

  first place – the kind of nature that would ground Natural Right or

  Human Rights. If our so-called ‘nature’ is only an evolutionarily

  contingent and technological y malleable biological nature, what

  legitimacy do such conceptions of universal ethics have in the first

  place? We may be able to use legislation to keep these technologies

  at bay (although that is unlikely), but even so, such legislation only covers over the power of such technologies to reve
al something

  much more fundamental to us about ourselves – something with

  profound ethical implications. Emergent biotechnologies even

  give us the power to create new forms of intelligent life, to be the

  designers of new species of sentient beings. What if we were to find

  out that we ourselves are the artifacts of more advanced beings? Is

  there something about each of us that is uncreated and a bearer of

  pre-political ethical rights, irrespective of whether or not the human race was someone else’s pet project? Prometheus created the human

  race in his own image; what are the ethics of a Promethean, of a

  superman alien to the human condition?

  26

  THE PHARMAKON ARTIST

  “The safest general characterization of the European

  philosophical tradition is that it consists of a series of footnotes

  to Plato.”

  – Alfred North Whitehead

  For too long now has this quote from Whitehead sounded

  as if it were a cliché. Historical y, doctrinal y, and

  temperamental y, there are many branches in the tree

  of Philosophia –between Neo-Pythagorean Platonists

  and Aristotelian Neo-Platonists before Descartes, between

  analytic and continental thought after Kant, between Marxist and

  Existentialist thinkers after Hegel. Nevertheless, they all recognize

  their common heritage in the solid trunk of the dramatic dialogues

  of Plato before disappearing into subterranean Pre-Socratic roots.

  A radical reinterpretation of Plato, then, has an obvious bearing on

  any attempt to revolutionize the philosophical tradition as a whole.

  If it could be shown that the dialectical development from out of

  Platonic idealism and into other forms of rationalism and intuitive

  understanding was in some way anticipated by Plato himself, even

  designed by him as a vast social conditioning mechanism, the whole

  of intellectual history would have to be rethought. I do not claim to

  attain this aim in the present essay, but I do paint in broad strokes

  some indispensable path marks to that end.

  27

  lovers of sophia

  The essay is divided into five sections. The first three sections

  are closely related and form the initial phase of my argument. In

  them I interpret Plato’s development of the Theory of Forms in

  terms of the metaphysics of the two foremost Pre-Socratic Greek

  thinkers, Heraclitus and Parmenides. The first section offers a

  concise sketch of the life-affirming worldview of Heraclitus and of

  the Eleatic school’s transcendentalist reaction against it, beginning

  with Parmenides. In the interests of a point made later in the essay,

  I preface this with an even briefer evocative glimpse at the Greek

  mind in the Homeric age.

  Since this essay is already ambitious in the scope of its treatment

  of Plato, to give more attention to the Pre-Socratics than I do here

  would seriously compromise its coherence. For the reader who is

  basical y unfamiliar with this background to Plato’s thought, and

  who needs more than the refreshers that I offer in the first section of this paper, I recommend Friedrich Nietzsche’s lectures on The Pre-Platonic Philosophers1 as well as his Philosophy in the Tragic Age of the Greeks 2 – a very short posthumously published book that he wrote contemporaneously with his famous study of Greek drama. My own

  understanding of the Pre-Socratics, or as Nietzsche called them the

  ‘Pre-Platonic’ philosophers, has been profoundly influenced by these

  two works, especial y his view therein of the relationship between

  Heraclitus and the Eleatic school of Parmenides.

  The second section argues that the Platonic “form” or “idea”

  ( eidos) was something devised with a view to Parmenidean notions of enduring unity, and on the basis of a tacit acceptance of a

  Heraclitean view of the world of sensuous experience as a perpetual

  flux. In itself, this is no great revelation, but what I suggest is

  something more. Namely, that Plato deliberately misinterprets the

  ontology of Heraclitus, privileging Becoming to the total exclusion

  of Being whereas for Heraclitus Becoming is a concealing or

  1 Friedrich Nietzsche, The Pre-Platonic Philosophers (Chicago: University of Illinois Press, 2001).

  2 Friedrich Nietzsche, Philosophy in the Tragic Age of the Greeks (Washington DC: Regnery Publishing, 1998).

  28

  jason reza jorjani

  sheltering aspect of Existence. Likewise, he perversely distorts the

  meaning of Non-Being in Parmenides from a negatively infinite

  ontological Nothingness to a finite cipher in the context of indexical reference (i.e. as that which is not being presently referred to, but

  which nonetheless exists as a counterfactual referent).

  Following clues in certain remarks made by Aristotle concerning

  Plato’s Heraclitean pedigree, I excavate the Heraclitean world-view

  tacitly accepted by Plato from between the lines of the dialogues

  Theaetetus, Cratylus, and Phaedo. I then turn to the dialogues Parmenides and The Sophist to see how Plato appears to respond to this vision of a world in perpetual flux, a world where certain

  knowledge of definite objects is impossible, by taking recourse to

  a rational y apprehensible transcendental realm that endows each

  object with its distinctive cohesive unity. The reader unfamiliar with academic philosophy will be duly forewarned that this exposition

  is by far the most abstract and abstruse section of the essay, and

  may seem – to those who even invest the effort in following it – to

  consists of platitudes concerning the relationship between the One

  and the Many and other fundamental points of Logic. The simplicity

  is, however, a deceptive one and careful y following Plato on these

  points is important for appreciating the more substantive claim of

  the next section.

  That claim is the following. The Theory of Forms can be seen as

  arising out of an attempt to find a middle way between uprooted and

  straw-man versions of Heraclitean and Parmenidean ontology, one

  which acknowledges the Heraclitean realm of sensuous experience,

  which Parmenides rejected as sheer il usion, while also securing the

  Parmenidean unity and simplicity indispensable to the definitions

  required for rational knowledge of objects. To this end, as we see

  perhaps most clearly in Timaeus, Plato develops the concept of a plurality of perfect unities – “forms” or “ideas” – that formatively

  define pure matter, which would otherwise be in an ungraspable

  state of perpetual flux. The soul on a quest for knowledge is at the

  crux of the mixture of form and matter, and is consequently impure.

  Nevertheless, she may seek purification through the rational

  29

  lovers of sophia

  element within her. However, Plato admits that perfect knowledge

  – which is the indispensable standard or sine qua non of any inferior

  ‘knowledge’ as such – cannot be attained insofar as intellection

  remains mediated by sensuous experience. I show how at one point

  in Phaedo, Plato makes the bold claim that knowledge by means of the pure intellect apart from anything bodily or sensory is possible

  after death, but he quickly contradicts this claim by consoling his

&n
bsp; disciples with a sensory account of the afterlife.

  I then insist that the metaphysics implicit in the latter statement

  cannot simply be dismissed – apart from its consoling moralistic

  content – because it is on a continuum with the tale of Er, which

  plays a key role in Republic, with its Pythagorean account of the unambiguously sensory state between death and (even the highest)

  rebirth (as a philosophical Guardian). Remaining in Republic, two key sets of passages on “the Good” are then examined toward the

  end of showing how Plato actual y conceived of the “forms” as

  constructs or postulates akin to those employed by geometers,

  and that these cannot even be viewed as leading one to a rational

  comprehension of the form of the Good. This “form of forms” is

  itself incomprehensible and inexplicable. So, briefly put, the forms

  are not only inescapably contaminated by matter where it counts,

  namely in the soul, but rational knowledge of that which the forms

  are postulated in order to apprehend is itself basical y impossible.

  The third section concludes with significant citations from two

  of Plato’s private Letters, which suggest that the upshot of his entire method of dialectical inquiry in terms of the forms is actual y a

  moment when mystical insight flashes upon the mind confronted

  with paradoxes that are bound to seem irresolvable within the limits

  of conceptual understanding or rational analysis. This requires

  as a prerequisite, not only a fine-tuning of intellect, through

  contemplation of the postulated forms and dialectical discourse with

  others, but also an intimately communal life among devoted seekers.

  That is the point of departure for the second part of the essay,

  which consists of its fourth and fifth sections. Together they forward the proposal that this irrational intuition that Plato is trying to

  30

  jason reza jorjani

  provoke is essential y an aesthetic intuition. The fourth section explores this in terms of the account of the pursuit of the form of the Beautiful in Symposium, with a focus on the relationship between that dialogue and another text named after Alcibiades – who is the most significant character in Symposium besides Socrates himself. It is argued that through Alcibiades’ eulogy, amidst an unprecedented

  honesty of intoxication, Plato offers us an insight into the profoundly Dionysian character of Socrates. We also have a shocking admission

 

‹ Prev