Book Read Free

Lovers of Sophia

Page 14

by Jason Reza Jorjani


  2 Ibid., 269.

  3 Ibid., 269.

  108

  jason reza jorjani

  estimate the strength of Sina’s thought by comparison to a mind like

  that of Hegel. In the Kitab al-shifa Sina claims that evil is always only a privation, that there is no positive force of evil, and that necessary evils are incidental to the overall rational design of the almighty

  creator of man and the Cosmos. This argument, which is too twisted

  to rehash in detail for our purposes here, runs counter to the very

  core of ancient Iranian thought and it is also illogical on its own

  terms.

  It does not help Sina that at the end of his life he admits that

  this was one of the many lies out of which he wove his philosophy,

  because without the Mantiq al-mashriqiyyin we do not know what he truly thought about such matters. In Fi Maqaamaat al-aarifin

  Sina destroys any hope we have of attributing a serious political

  philosophy to him, because he claims that the legitimacy of the

  legislator whose law and order are needed for social stability comes

  from divine signs that the Lord gives in order to manifest his power

  and demand our obedience to his prophet and vice-regent.4 Sina

  legitimates the very Islamic rule that he, in the end, admits oppressed and victimized him.

  Of the major thinkers from the period of the zenith of science

  and knowledge in Iran after the Islamic conquest, Zakariya Razi

  and Omar Khayyam are the two who rejected Islam. Consequently,

  one might be inclined to see them as the true “philosophers” of

  the period. However, Razi and Khayyam do not develop any new

  philosophical concepts or express any unprecedented insights into

  the nature of reality or the structure of society. Their philosophical thought is on the level of followers of the Stoic or Epicurean schools in the Roman Empire, both in terms of form and in terms of content.

  It is true that both men contributed significantly to the advancement

  of scientific knowledge, but this is not the same thing as being a

  philosopher.

  Most of the work produced by professional so-called

  ‘philosophers’ in academia today is not philosophy at al . Philosophy

  is a kind of thinking that upholds the unity of the sciences, including 4 Ibid., 252.

  109

  lovers of sophia

  political science and aesthetics. Scientific theories and discoveries

  may be the product of philosophical thought, insofar as that thought

  establishes new fundamental frameworks for seeking and organizing

  knowledge, but the philosopher must question basic assumptions in

  a way that is not necessary for scientists and inventors. Philosophy

  is fundamental thinking on the nature of Truth, Beauty, and Justice.

  The person who actual y comes closest to being a genuine

  philosopher in Iran during the period in question is Abu Nasr

  Farabi (257 Hejri, 870 Miladi). Like Plato and Aristotle, and also like Hegel, Farabi’s thought extends from ontology and epistemology to

  ethics, political theory, and aesthetics. However, the work of Farabi

  also clearly demonstrates how far Iran remained from producing a

  thinker like Hegel and why that is the case. In his Kitab al-burhan (a commentary on Aristotle’s Analytica Posteriora) we see that Farabi has a first-rate logical mind, capable of the most hair-splitting analysis and careful reasoning.5 Yet in his Kitab al-jam ‘bayn ra’yay al-hakimayn, Aflatun al-ilahi wa Aristu he tries to assert that there are no significant differences between Plato and Aristotle, and that

  any merely apparent differences in their thinking have to do with

  their different ways of life and styles of writing.6 I do not say he

  makes an argument for this because no argument can ever be made

  for such a preposterous position. Then in Mabadi’ ara’ ahl al-madinat al-fadilah, which I believe was Ayatol ah Khomeini’s favorite book, Farabi adopts the political theory of the ideal state from Plato’s

  Republic and has the audacity to claim that Muhammad and the

  Imams are essential y what Plato meant by the ideal philosopher-

  kings.7

  The same problem lies at the basis of these two very

  embarrassing expositions. Farabi cannot tolerate intellectual tension

  on fundamental questions. For him, if Plato and Aristotle did not

  think the same things on the same matters of ultimate importance,

  this would be an indictment of human reason as such. The reality

  5 Ibid., 93–110.

  6 Ibid., 110–118.

  7 Ibid., 119–133.

  110

  jason reza jorjani

  is that not only does Aristotle argue against Plato repeatedly, on

  matters both metaphysical and political, but Plato uses the method

  of his dramatic dialogues to constantly argue against himself. He

  chooses Socrates as a mouthpiece because he understands that the

  philosophical life is a life of fundamental questioning, and only on

  account of this can it lead to discoveries. The most famous saying

  of Socrates is “Wisdom begins in wonder,” whereas regarding the

  attainment of knowledge Farabi says, “If he encounters this meaning,

  he rests at it, feels peace with it, and enjoys the removal in him of the harm of wonder and ignorance.”8

  Someone who considers wonder a harm does not understand the

  first thing about Philosophy. For Farabi knowledge is cumulative.

  Plato and Aristotle together attained it, and so they cannot be in

  any fundamental disagreement. If they were, it would mean that

  both ignorance and wonder persist in even the most powerful

  minds precisely because knowledge is not cumulative and discovery

  is an ongoing process. Since Farabi is well aware of the essential

  connection between ontology or epistemology and political theory,

  this incompleteness and mutability of knowledge would mean

  not only intellectual unrest but also a threat to the long-term

  peace and stability of society. Someone might arrive at a different

  understanding of nature, including human nature, that could

  for example be reflected in a new political theory that produces

  something like the French Revolution.

  That possibility unconsciously terrifies Farabi, whereas it was

  very clear to Plato (who he claims to revere so much). Socrates was

  martyred as a revolutionary political dissident, and Plato is almost

  killed himself for experimenting with an ideal state in Syracuse.

  Even Aristotle, who is relatively more conservative, had to exile

  himself from Athens because as he put it, he did not want to make

  the Athenians responsible for murdering two philosophers. Aristotle

  ran a think tank that would experiment with different constitutions

  for different city-states whose leaders would privately come to him

  for advisement. By contrast, Farabi has a mind like that of a Chinese

  8 Ibid., 118.

  111

  lovers of sophia

  Confucian. He treats Plato and Aristotle as if they are Confucius.

  This is also why he can so perversely equate the philosopher-king

  with an Imam.

  For Farabi knowledge is fixed and handed-down all tidied-up,

  like a divine revelation. As far as I am concerned, there is no native Chinese philosophy. There might be some Buddhist philosophy

  which took place in China after Iranian missionaries such as />
  Bodhidharma brought Mahayana Buddhism there through the Silk

  Route. But neither the Confucian nor even the Taoist sages or wise

  men can be considered philosophers. The Chinese have this saying,

  “May you live in interesting times,” which they consider a curse. It is for this reason that I worry if the Chinese are left as the only bulwark against Islam, the Caliphate may dominate the world because the

  Asian mentality – which the Turks and Mongols shared – is actual y

  very much in accord with Islam. Farabi has this mentality. He wants

  to sit at the foot of silk-robed sages and receive Wisdom. This is also similar to the mentality of guru-worship in India, but the analogy to

  Confucianism is more appropriate because Hindu gurus usual y did

  not speak on politics.

  The precondition for producing a Hegel or Nietzsche is centuries

  of dialectical tension, a conflict of fundamental standpoints that

  plays itself out in both scientific and political revolutions that

  are as productive as they are destructive. The closest conditions

  approximating this in the history of Iran were during the Sassanian

  period, where we witnessed a conflict between at least four different

  worldviews: Manichaeism, Orthodox Zoroastrianism, Mazdakism,

  and Sassanian Court Platonism (which had Zurvanite elements). I

  have noticed that the tendency in the Iranian Renaissance movement

  is to conflate the court Platonism of Khosrow Anushirawan with

  orthodox Zoroastrianism and then dismiss Mani and Mazdak’s

  revolutionary doctrines as total y degenerate. I imagine that if

  European thinkers of the New Right were to advance their own

  interpretation of Sassanian Iran they would arrive at the same

  conclusion, especial y those who are Traditionalist rather than

  Archeo-Futurist. But it is important to remember that Mani was

  112

  jason reza jorjani

  endorsed by Shapur the Great and that Mazdak received the support

  of Kavad I.

  We know that each of these movements had extensive scriptures

  produced over a very long period of time. Mazdakism survived

  past the Islamic conquest in the form of the Khorramdin and

  Qarmatian. Manichaeism spread all the way from northwestern

  China to Bulgaria and the South of France. In Europe, in its Bogomil

  and Cathar forms, it was such a potent social force that it catalyzed

  the Holy Inquisition of the Catholic Church in response to it. If we

  were to charitably suppose that the fragments of these movements

  that survived both Sassanian state persecution and the Islamic and

  Mongol conquests are a pale shadow of what they were in terms of

  their sophistication and depth of reflection, then we can postulate

  that if the culture of Sassanian Iran had continued for another

  century or two, it might have yielded a thinker like Hegel.

  Such a man could have analyzed the dynamics of the evolution

  of consciousness, in hindsight, understanding the Mazdakite

  revolution as a stage in the self-correcting development of reason,

  and he could have reflected on the metaphysical shift from

  Zoroastrian cosmology to a Manichean or Neo-Platonist cosmology.

  As far as I am aware, no other non-Western culture besides Iran ever

  had the kind of open conflict between fundamental intellectual and

  spiritual standpoints that we see in the late Sassanian period. These

  were the birth pangs of an Enlightenment.

  When one dismisses Mani and Mazdak as aberrations from

  some falsely idealized Khosravani wisdom and virtue, and then

  attributes Shapur and Khosrow’s eclectic interest in Neo-Platonism

  to the orthodox Zoroastrian Mobeds who were probably nervous

  on account of it, one is tidying-up the intellectual, spiritual, and

  social conditions of the Sassanian period in a way that denies that an Iranian Hegel was ever even a possibility. An example of this kind of

  tidying-up is the reconstruction of Sassanian so-called ‘Philosophy’

  that we see in two works by Ibn Miskawayh, a thinker from Rayy

  who was born in 320 Hijri or 932 Miladi into a family that had

  only recently converted from Zoroastrianism to Islam. His book

  113

  lovers of sophia

  Javidan-Kherad or “The Perennial Philosophy” claims to preserve a Sassanian book of wise sayings and judgments by Hushang Shah,

  as well as the sayings of Kasra Qobad, a letter from Bozorgmehr to

  Kasra, and “words of wisdom” from Anushiravan.9

  Indeed, there are many fine ( nikou) words of wisdom here, in

  the sense of sayings of a sage that the Chinese might neatly wrap

  up inside a fortune cookie. Some of them are more insightful than

  others that must be considered platitudes of the kind you would

  find in a 19th century European handbook on morals and proper

  etiquette. Even the most profound and penetrating of these sayings

  are not connected to each other by any systematic thought process

  that could, on account of its principles and logical structure, enter

  into a fundamental conflict with a rival system. One would be

  hard pressed to find anything in here that a person might die for

  or that might drive him to kill another. Compare this to the zeal of

  the Manicheans and the martyrdom of around a hundred thousand

  Mazdakites at the hands of Khosrow I. Whoever that Khosrow was,

  or for that matter whoever Kavad was that he had the audacity to

  back a revolutionary as radical as Mazdak, the intellectual force

  of these Sassanian period personages is not captured by Javidan

  Kherad.

  Actual y, the problem is not any specific error on the part of

  Ibn Miskawayh but the very idea of Javidan Kherad or “Perennial Philosophy”, which Mohammad Reza Shah resurrected and

  institutionalized in the Imperial Academy of Philosophy. This was

  the institute in Pahlavi period Iran where Henry Corbin col aborated

  with the likes of Seyyed Hossein Nasr. Its pariah was Peter Lamborn

  Wilson (a.k.a. Hakim Bey). If a society believes that there is an

  eternal, unchanging Wisdom that can be definitively attained by a

  person living within the present time, and that another intelligent

  person need only to study under such a sage to have this knowledge

  imparted to him, then that society will never see the kind of scientific and political revolutions that are catalyzed by genuine philosophers

  and that are also preconditions for a Hegel who tries to understand

  9 Ibid., 276–302.

  114

  jason reza jorjani

  what is at work in these revolutions. If I were to believe that Ibn

  Miskawayh’s Javidan Kherad adequately represents the intellectual life of Sassanian Iran, then an Iranian Hegel was never possible and

  I would even have to wonder whether the reason that Heraclitus did

  not accept Darius’ invitation to become the Court Philosopher of

  Iran is not for the reason I have repeatedly suggested in interviews

  with Iranian Renaissance leaders, but because Heraclitus knew that

  in the Court of Iran he would have to become Confucius.

  That is the last thing he could ever have become, since dialectical

  opposition and generative conflict is the very heart and soul of

  Heraclitus’ thought. Nietzsche and Heidegg
er idolize him for

  this, and without this mode of thinking on his part, there would

  never have been a Plato. Aristotle tel s us that Plato belonged

  to the school of Heraclitus in his youth and that what he learned

  there remained the foundation for all of his future work. What he

  learned was not some piece of information, it was not a cumulative

  addition to his knowledge. He learned how to think beneath and

  beyond any assumptions, whether cosmological or sociopolitical.

  This is extremely dangerous, not only because you might be killed

  for expressing what emerges from such thinking, but even more so

  because it brings you face to face with an abyss both within yourself

  and around you. The revolutionary transition from one framework

  of knowledge to another, and the revaluation of fundamental

  principles, requires an intellectual equivalent of Pahlavani (Heroism) and Javanmardi (Chivalry) that began with Zarathustra and that you do not see outside of the Āryan world.

  I have noticed that even within the Iranian Renaissance

  movement there are people who try to read the Gathas of Zarathustra as if they are the Analects of Confucius. This is to completely miss what it is about Zarathustra that makes him total y incomparable

  to Confucius. Nietzsche does far more justice to Zarathustra than

  those who try to use the Gathas to increase their knowledge, as if by increments. He fundamental y grasps the spirit of the man and

  claims that were that man alive today he would teach almost exactly

  the opposite of everything that he taught in his own time and place.

  115

  lovers of sophia

  This is an exaggeration on Nietzsche’s part, but his essential insight is absolutely right. Nietzsche grasps the form of Zarathustra’s thought

  and the ethos of this personality, an epitome of the “Promethean”

  or “Faustian” spirit characteristic of the Āryan genius long before

  Aeschylus’ Prometheus or Goethe’s Faust.

  Yet I do not mean to suggest in any way that Iran’s greatness lies

  only in the past. Islam is according to its own claim the third and

  final of the Abrahamic revelations. So if the fact that it cannot be

  reformed also means that once Iranians are fed up with it they will

  reject the religion in its entirety, then in a sense Iran has the potential to suddenly leap ahead of Europe. The Abrahamic religions are a

  three-stage project and Europe is only now being prepared to move

 

‹ Prev