Book Read Free

An Introduction to Madhva Vedan

Page 4

by Deepak Sarma


  eight svâmis, was ordained as head of the Sôde mañha. Madhvâcârya

  placed the mañhas of his disciples under his tutelage. The aùñamañhas

  still exist today and are loci for studying both doctrines and rituals

  and for the training of virtuosos.47 Madhvâcârya may have developed paryâya, a rotating system of leadership that would begin after his

  disappearance.48 It is not altogether clear that the paryâya system existed immediately after Madhvâcârya’s disappearance or if it was a later

  development. There is some inscriptional evidence, however, which

  indicates that it took effect immediately after he disappeared. In this

  system of governing, paryâya, the svâmis of each of the eight mañhas is proclaimed to be leader every two years.

  Although the community established by Madhvâcârya has spread to

  different parts of India, it is still centered in Karõâñaka state and, most

  importantly, in Uóupi. The Uttarâdi, Vyâsarâya, Râyara, Úrîpâdarâya,

  Râghavendra and Kukke-Subramanya mañhas among others, are also

  central to the contemporary Mâdhva saüpradâya.49

  The contemporary Mâdhva community

  The community and institutions that Madhvâcârya founded in the 13th

  and 14th centuries has grown far outside the boundaries of the southern

  Karõâñaka. Like many other communities in South Asia, British

  colonization and later diasporic migration has led Mâdhvas to move

  within India as well as to leave the subcontinent. The end result has been

  a wide dissemination of members of the Mâdhva community. In recent

  times, Mâdhvas have maintained their community by establishing a

  46 MV 15.128–129.

  47 For a brief analysis of contemporary issues facing Mâdhva mañhas, see Rao’s ‘The Udupi Madhva matha.’

  48 See Sharma, History, 192–194 for further details about this controversy.

  49 This list of mañhas is not comprehensive.

  28

  Madhvâcârya and the Mâdhva Tradition

  15

  directory of Mâdhvas in the United States and developing burgeoning

  Websites and automated mailing lists.50 Though such globalization is likely to conflict with traditional modes of instruction and transmission,

  it has been embraced by the svâmis of the aùñamatþas, some of whom

  are now even journeying outside of India. Only time will tell just how

  much the tradition will change given these new transformations and

  incarnations.

  Madhvâcârya’s works: the Sarvamûlagranthâþ, Compendium of

  All the Fundamentals

  Madhvâcârya wrote a total of 37 treatises, together known as the

  Sarvamûlagranthâþ, Compendium of All the Fundamentals.51 First, there are commentaries on the prasthânatraya, three-fold systems. The

  Bhagavad Gîtâ, the Brahma Sûtras and ten Upaniùads (the Aitareya, Bçhadâraõyaka, Chândogya, Îúâvâsya, Kena, Kañha, Mâõóûkya, Muõóaka, úañpraúna, Taittiriya), comprise the prasthânatraya and each has a commentary. The Brahma Sûtra Bhâùya, a commentary on Vyâsa’s

  Brahma Sûtras, is, perhaps, Madhvâcârya’s most important work and

  is, indirectly, a summary of the essence of the Mâdhva position.

  Madhvâcârya wrote three other commentaries on the Brahma Sûtras,

  including the Aõubhâùya, The Brief Commentary (also known as the

  Sarvaúâstrârthasaügrahaþ, Compendium of the Meaning of all the

  Úâstras), the Anuvyâkhyâna, An Explanation of the Sûtras, and, finally, the Nyâyavivaraõa, An Exposition on Logic. This large number of

  commentaries on the Brahma Sûtras is unusual in comparison to

  founders and followers of rival schools of Vedânta. Úaükarâcârya,

  for example, composed only one bhâùya, commentary, on the Brahma

  Sûtras.

  The second category consists of the daúaprakaraõa, ten-fold treatises

  on specific topics. In these short treatises, Madhvâcârya presents

  arguments concerning epistemology and ontology. His most well-

  known works in the area of ratiocination are his Viùõutattva(vi)nirõaya,

  The Complete Ascertainment of the Nature of Viùõu and his

  Khaõóanatraya, A Trio of Refutations. The Khaõóanatraya is composed

  50 See , , and Rao, Udupi and Dakshina Kannada Dravida Braahmans Directory [sic].

  51 For detailed analyses of the contents of each of these texts see Sharma, History, 90–187 and for a smaller number see Nagaraja Sarma’s Reign of Realism in Indian

  Philosophy.

  29

  16

  An Introduction to Mâdhva Vedânta

  of the Upâdhikhaõóana, The Refutation of the Upâdhi Position, the Mâyâvâdakhaõóana, The Refutation of the Mâyâ Position, and the Prapañcamithyâtvânumânakhaõóana, The Refutation of the Inference

  of the Illusoriness of Phenomenal Reality. The Mâyâvâdakhaõóana is, in part, a reaction to arguments found in Úrîharùa’s (the 12th-century ce

  Advaita scholar) Khaõóanakhaõóakhâdya.

  The third set, the purâõaprasthâna, systems of Purâõa texts,

  addresses philosophical matters exemplified in commentaries on myth-

  ological, epic and historical-literary works. Madhvâcârya has composed

  commentaries on the Mahâbhârata and the Bhâgavata Purâõa. His

  commentary on the Mahâbhârata, the Mahâbhâratatâtparyanirõaya,

  The Complete Ascertainment of the Meaning of the Mahâbhârata,

  is known among contemporary scholars as ‘ un passage étonnat de

  modernisme’ because it is an early text wherein the author mentions

  that he has critically edited a text on which he is commenting.52 In his commentary, Madhvâcârya mentions the problems with multiple,

  corrupt and conflicting manuscripts:

  In some places they put new [passages into the text. In some places]

  they deleted [texts] and in some places [there are] changes. In other

  cases they made changes by mistake. The texts that are not

  destroyed are entirely confused. For the most part, [there are only]

  corrupt texts. A fraction of the millions [of texts] is not even found.

  So the texts are corrupted. [In this way,] even for the gods the

  meaning is difficult to understand. So, in this perplexing time,

  ordered by Hari, by His grace, having studied all of the úâstra and

  the Vedânta, inspired by Hari, having seen the different copies of

  the text from different regions, I speak the correct purport [of the

  Mahâbhârata].53

  Madhvâcârya also includes commentary on the Mûlarâmâyâõa in his

  Mahâbhâratatâtparyanirõaya. Given that the main figures of the

  Mûlarâmâyâõa and the Mahâbhârata are both avatâras of Viùõu, and, therefore, inextricably linked with one another, the enclosure of

  the former in the latter is not unusual. The èg Veda and, therefore,

  52 Siauve, La Doctrine, 23.

  53 kvacid granthân prakùipanti kvacid antaritân api | kuryuþ kvacic ca vyatyâsaü pramâdât kvacid anyathâ | anutsannâ api granthâ vyâkulâ iti sarvaúaþ | utsannâþ prâyaúassarve koñyaüúo ‘pi na vartate | grantho ‘py evaü vilulitaþ kim vârtho devadurgamaþ | kalâvevaü vyâkulite nirõayâya pracoditaþ | hariõâ nirõayân vacmi vijânaüstatprasâdataþ | úâstrântarâõi sañjânan vedântâüú câsya prasâdataþ | deúe deúe tathâ granthân dçùñvâ caiva pçthagvidhân | Mahâbhâratatâtparyanirõaya, 2.3–2.8.

  (hereafter MBhTN).

  30

  Madhvâcârya and the Mâdhva Tradition

&nb
sp; 17

  Madhvâcârya’s èg Bhâùya, is also included among the purâõaprasthâna

  by contemporary scholars of Mâdhva Vedânta.

  The fourth set of Madhvâcârya’s works is minor treatises on practical

  doctrines. These works still play a role in the contemporary practice

  of Mâdhva Vedânta. The Tantrasârasaügraha, The Compendium of

  the Essential Parts of the Practical Doctrines, and Sadâcârasmçti,

  Tradition of Correct Practices, concerns Vaiùõava rituals and worship

  frameworks. This fourth set also includes poetic texts such as the

  Dvâdaúa Stotra, The Twelve Hymns, which can be set to music and may

  have helped to give rise to musical traditions in South Karõâñaka.54

  Other relevant Mâdhva works

  Although there are a large number of followers of Mâdhva Vedânta who

  composed commentaries on texts in Madhvâcârya’s Sarvamûlagranthâþ

  and independent treatises on Mâdhva doctrine, two are especially

  noteworthy. These two scholars are Jayatîrtha and Vyâsatîrtha, both of

  whom, along with Madhvâcârya, are known as the munitrayam, the

  three major thinkers, of Mâdhva Vedânta. The two commentators,

  Jayatîrtha and Vyâsatîrtha, composed works that changed the trajectory

  of Mâdhva Vedânta, both in terms of Mâdhva ratiocinative method

  and due to the sustained damage of their arguments against competing

  schools.

  Jayatîrtha (1365–88 ce) is best known for codifying the doctrines of

  Mâdhva Vedânta. Jayatîrtha earned the title ñîkâcârya, author of com-

  mentaries, with his two well-known commentaries on Madhvâcârya’s

  commentaries on the Brahma Sûtras. His Nyâya Sudhâ, Nectar of Logic, is a commentary on Madhvâcârya’s Anuvyakhyâna and primarily

  consists of refutations of the tenets of rival schools. His Tattvaprakaúika, Explanation of Reality, is a commentary on Madhvâcârya’s Brahma

  Sûtra Bhâùya. Jayatîrtha’s Pramâõapaddhati, Way of Proof, is one of his independent works and became a standard textbook on Mâdhva logic

  and epistemology.

  Vyâsatîrtha (1460–1539 ce) is best known for three of his works,

  called the Vyâsatrayam, The Trio of Vyâsatîrtha’s Works, by later

  Mâdhvas. His Nyâyâmçta, The Ambrosia of Logic, which presents

  arguments against Advaita metaphysics, inspired a lengthy series

  of debates between the two schools of Vedânta. For example,

  Madhusûdhana Sarasvatî, the 16th-century scholar of Advaita Vedânta,

  54 Sharma, History, 187–188. Vaiùõavacaran, v.

  31

  18

  An Introduction to Mâdhva Vedânta

  wrote his Advaitasiddhi in response to Vyâsatîrtha’s criticisms.

  Vyâsatîrtha’s Tâtparyacandrikâ was a further systematization of

  Madhvâcârya’s position on the Brahma Sûtras. The third member of the

  texts classified as Vyâsatrayam is Vyâsatîrtha’s Tarka Tâõóava, The Dance of Logic. The Tarka Tâõóava is a refutation of fundamental

  Navya Nyâya principles and, indirectly, of several Pûrva Mîmâüsâ

  positions.

  Theory and practice

  The life and history of Madhvâcârya and Mâdhva Vedânta offered here

  should help readers to view the tradition as a living one and not as

  simply a set of doctrines lacking practitioners. When one immerses

  oneself in epistemological and other more theoretical issues, one often

  forgets that the beliefs in question cannot, and do not, stand apart from

  their practice. It must not be forgotten that the ultimate goal of the

  Mâdhva tradition was to offer a convincing solution to the problem of

  birth and rebirth and an efficient and correct path to mokùa. Their

  solution, moreover, could not stand apart from the texts that they

  commented upon. This brief foray into the life and history of

  Madhvâcârya and Mâdhva Vedânta serves to remind readers of this link

  between theory and practice. With this context in mind, I now turn to the

  core of the Mâdhva position, namely epistemology.

  32

  CHAPTER TWO

  Mâdhva epistemology

  A means of valid knowledge is that which reveals an object [of

  knowledge] as it is.1

  Madhvâcârya begins his Pramâõalakùaõa, Characterization of the

  Means of Valid Knowledge, with this rather bold statement revealing

  the foundation of his philosophy of realism: that it is possible to have

  knowledge of an object that is free from sublation. Such a position is

  not surprising, given that Mâdhva philosophy is in part a reaction

  against Advaita Vedânta. Scholars of the Advaita School hold that

  objects that we see in vyâvahârika, our everyday experience, are not as

  they appear. Instead, objects are no more than superimpositions onto

  brahman, divinity.2 For this reason, in Advaita Vedânta anything that one perceives can be sublated, is not real and one’s perceptions are not

  entirely valid. It is not possible to know an object as it really is. For

  the Advaita School, means of valid knowledge are not yathârtha as

  Madhvâcârya defines it and, in fact, do not reveal the true nature of

  the objects of cognition. The status of all knowledge, perceptual and

  otherwise, is thus problematized in the Advaita epistemology.

  Madhvâcârya’s epistemology of realism is in direct opposition to

  Advaita Vedânta. Sat, real, objects for Madhvâcârya certainly are

  neither mere superimpositions, nor products of our imagination or of a

  Cartesian evil genius.3 In contrast to the Advaita position, valid and true knowledge is knowledge that is not superimposed and cannot be sublated.

  In order to justify his epistemology of realism, Madhvâcârya relies on

  a variety of cognitive apparatus and mechanisms. His account includes

  unavoidable presuppositions that also correlate with his ontology,

  soteriology and eschatology. In this chapter, I introduce readers to

  this system, which includes his theories about valid knowledge, the

  instruments of valid knowledge via logical discourse and the tools by

  which we construct cognitions.

  It is all too easy to forget that Mâdhva epistemological reflection

  was never an end in itself. Instead, it was always in the service of

  soteriology. A proper understanding of the mechanisms of the universe,

  1 yathârthaü pramâõam | Pramâõalakùaõa.

  2 See Chapter 3 for more on the term brahman.

  3 See Descartes’s Meditations on First Philosophy, Meditation 1.

  19

  33

  20

  An Introduction to Mâdhva Vedânta

  including epistemological ones and, most importantly, complete and

  correct knowledge of brahman, is essential to being granted mokùa. An incorrect understanding of brahman is the reason why sentient beings

  are reborn.4 Such knowledge combined with bhakti, devotion , and other practices eventually can break the cycle. Although I address these issues

  of practice in Chapter 4, it is vital that readers keep them in mind and do not artificially separate the theoretical from the practical.

  I am dependent upon several texts from the Mâdhva corpus for my

  analysis, including Madhvâcârya’s Pramâõalakùaõa, Characterization

  of the Means of Valid Knowledge (hereafter PL). The Pramâõalakùaõa,

  a prakaraõa, minor philoso
phical tract, is a handbook of his

  epistemology. It is comprised of fifty granthas, unmetered thirty-two-

  syllable verses. It also contains arguments against epistemological

  positions held by a number of schools including the Advaita School of

  Vedânta. Although this text has inspired many commentaries I rely only

  on Jayatîrtha’s Pramâõapaddhati, The Path Towards the Means of Valid

  Knowledge, (hereafter PP) an independent treatise of 750 granthas

  modeled after the PL. These two texts, combined with references to

  Mâdhva epistemology found in his Brahma Sûtra Bhâùya, Commentary

  on the Brahma Sûtras, Viùõutattva(vi)nirõaya (hereafter VTV), The Complete Ascertainment of the Nature of Viùõu, and Anuvyakhyâna

  (hereafter AV), An Explanation of the Sûtras, are sufficient for the

  purposes of this introduction. The Viùõutattva(vi)nirõaya, also a

  prakaraõa, is a detailed refutation of Advaita positions. It contains

  arguments against Advaita epistemology as well as criticisms of

  Advaita interpretations of controversial passages from úruti, the

  revealed texts of the Vedic canon, and is comprised of 540 granthas.

  Both the Brahma Sûtra Bhâùya and Anuvyakhyâna are commentaries on

  the Brahma Sûtras.

  Pramâõa, the means of valid knowledge

  One primary concern of the schools of South Asia philosophy is to

  characterize what constitutes a pramâõa, means of valid knowledge .

  There are debates among all of the schools concerning the definitions

  and components of pramâõa. Buddhists, for example, do not hold the

  sacred texts of the Hindus, such as the Vedas, to be unquestionably true.

  Their theories about what constitutes a pramâõa would surely conflict

  with the schools of Vedânta. Given the centrality of pramâõas and

  4 nâvedadinmanute taü bçhantaü sarvânubhûmâtmânaü sâmparâye | BSB 1.1.3.

  34

  Mâdhva Epistemology

  21

  epistemic theory, students of the schools of philosophy in South Asia

  were required to learn the intricacies of their own epistemologies and

  those of rivals. For this reason, I begin my characterization of the

  doctrines of Mâdhva Vedânta with epistemic theories.

  Pramâõas, according to Madhvâcârya, are of two varieties, kevala

  and anu.5 Kevala-pramâõa is direct knowledge of an object as it is, while anu-pramâõa, indirect knowledge, is the instrument that gives

 

‹ Prev