An Introduction to Madhva Vedan

Home > Other > An Introduction to Madhva Vedan > Page 8
An Introduction to Madhva Vedan Page 8

by Deepak Sarma


  nevertheless characterized as úâstra and, indirectly, can be classified

  as smçti! They are still given some status as important texts intended

  for tamo-yogyas, those who are fit only for darkness, despite being

  83 mohârthâny anyaúâstrâõi kçtâny evâjñayâ hareþ | atasteùûktam agrâhyam asurâõâü tamogataþ | yasmât kçtâni tânîha viùõunoktaiþ úivâdibhiþ | eùâü yan na virodhi syât tatroktaü tan na vâryate | MBhTN 1.34.

  84 eùa mohaü sçjâmyâúu yo janân mohyiùyati | tvaü ca rudra mahâbâho mohaúâstrâõi kâraya | atathyâõi vitathyâõi darúayasva mahâbhuja | prakâúaü kuru câtmânam aprakaúaü ca mâm kuru | iti vârâhavacanaü brahmâõóoktaü tathâ param |

  MBhTN 1.48–50. This same passage is found also in BSB 1.1.1.

  55

  42

  An Introduction to Mâdhva Vedânta

  confusing. Even texts that conflict with Mâdhva tenets, then, serve an

  important purpose in the Mâdhva theology.85 Not only were they

  ‘emitted’ by Viùõu, an inherently âpta, reliable, being, but they also help

  to confirm the unusual Mâdhva position regarding predestination and

  assume an important role in Mâdhva philosophy.

  Pratyakùa vs. âgama vs. anumâna

  As already mentioned, each school of Vedânta claims that its position

  is upheld by passages from the úruti and smçti. How relevant is úruti?

  What happens if it conflicts with pratyakùa? Are the three pramâõas

  also hierarchically arranged? Which pramâõa is upajîvya, foundational, and which is upajîvaka, dependent?86 It is crucial to the persuasiveness of his doctrine for Madhvâcârya to answer these questions and to offer a

  coherent interpretive strategy.

  Madhvâcârya gives greater importance to both pratyakùa, perception,

  and âgama, scriptural authority or verbal testimony, than to anumâna, logical inference. Not only are all constituents of anumâna dependent

  on either pratyakùa or âgama, but anumâna is a means to an end, not an end. Reasoning is not permitted outside of the úruti canon and is

  therefore subservient. This rule is found in sûtra 1.1.18 of the Brahma Sûtras itself: ‘And the requirement for an inference is not [simply] from

  the desire [to prove something].’87 Madhvâcârya’s commentary further clarifies this point:

  It is possible to make an inference [to prove whatever] one desires.

  Therefore, in connection with the truth, a distinct inference is not

  required. In the Skanda [ Purâõa, the following] is said: ‘As

  inference can be used to prove what is desired, therefore, consistent

  inferences are desired for the sake of [removing] contradiction in

  preceding and succeeding [passages] of the úruti. There is no other

  [use for inference].’88

  Madhvâcârya contends that anumâna itself is problematic when used

  for purposes other than interpreting úruti. It is upajîvaka, dependent, on

  85 amohâya guõâ viùõorâkâraú ciccrîratâ | nirdoúatvaü târatamyaü muktânâm api cocyate | etadvirudhaü yat sarvaü tanmohâyeti nirõayaþ | MBhTN 1.50–51.

  86 See Sharma’s Philosophy, Chapter 17, for more on this topic.

  87 kâmâc ca nânumânâpekùâ | BSB 1.1.18.

  88 yathâkâmaü hy anumâtuü úakyate | ato na tattve pçthaganumânam apekùyate |

  uktaü ca skânde | yathâkâmânumâ yasmât tasmât sânapagâ úruteþ | pûrvâparâvirodhâya ceùyate nânyathâ kvacit iti | BSB 1.1.18.

  56

  Mâdhva Epistemology

  43

  âgama-pramâõa. Madhvâcârya, for example, cites a passage from the

  Kûrma Purâõa in order to explain this emphasis on the supremacy of

  âgama:

  ‘And there is no definite authority of inference. Without the

  assistance of úruti, inference would certainly not accomplish [its]

  goal. The other pramâõa [perception] when accompanied by úruti

  and smçti is the best pramâõa and [therefore] gets the status of

  pramâõa. [In this way,] no [further] discussion ought to be

  undertaken. This [is an example of] reasoning [that] is [good] logic:

  “What meaning should be assented to here [given] the non-

  contradictions of the preceding and subsequent [in úâstra]?”

  Empty logic should be avoided.’ [This passage is from] the Kûrma

  Purâõa.89

  By giving a lower status to anumâna, Madhvâcârya directly contradicts

  the positions of the Advaita school of Vedânta. Úaükarâcârya, as I show

  below, purports that anumâna is more authoritative than pratyakùa,

  thereby permitting him to reject perceptual evidence that all is not

  brahman. Perception cannot be supplanted by reason alone. Placing a

  primacy on pratyakùa clashes with the foundations of the chief rivals

  of the Mâdhva school. Passages such as this one taken from the Kûrma

  Purâõa also remind readers that philosophical speculation is not an end

  in itself, that it always occurs in conjunction with properly interpreting

  the úâstra and that epistemic reflection is always in service of obtaining

  mokùa. Logic is a means to an end, not an end in and of itself.

  Given the centrality of hierarchy in Madhvâcârya’s philosophical

  theology, one might expect either pratyakùa or âgama to be supreme.

  Although both are held to have supremacy relative to their respective

  scope, it appears that pratyakùa has preeminence. That is, each has

  internal supremacy in a limited range, while âgama is supreme in

  matters of dharma and knowledge of Viùõu and pratyakùa is supreme

  in matters of mundane reality, the foundation of all pramâõas remains

  the sâkùî.90 Recall that the sâkùî is the final judge of the truth of the

  89 na ca anumânasya niyatapramâõyam | úrutisâhâyyarahitam anumânaü na kutra cit | niúcayât sâdhayed arthaü pramâõântaram eva ca | úrutismçtisahâyaü yat pramâõântaram uttamam | pramâõapadavîü gacchen nâtra kâryâ vicâraõâ |

  pûrvottarâvirodhena ko ‘trârtho ‘bhimato bhavet | ity âdyam ûhanaü tarkaþ úuùkatarkaü tu varjayet ity âdi kaurme | BSB 1.1.3.

  90 pratyakùam upajîvyaü syât prâyo yuktir api kvacit | âgamaikapramaõeùu tasyaiva hy upajîvyatâ | AV 2.1.19. Generally, perception would be the foundation and sometimes it is inference. In the case of testimonial evidence, it is the foundation.

  57

  44

  An Introduction to Mâdhva Vedânta

  pramâõas.91 The úruti that conflicts with pratyakùa must be reinterpreted such that they do not. The pramâõa that is upajîvaka, foundational, must not conflict with the upajîvya, dependent. If an âgama concerns anything experiential, then it must agree with pratyakùa. This

  hermeneutic allows Madhvâcârya to reinterpret and reevaluate úruti

  which, at first glance, seems to agree with the Advaita position. In this

  way, Madhvâcârya is able to establish his philosophy of realism.

  Khyâti-vâdas, theories of false cognition

  South Asian traditions are primarily concerned with khyâti-vâda,

  theories of false cognition. How does one account for false cognitions in

  one’s everyday activity? How could one mistakenly see an object when

  one is not present or see an abheda, identity, where there was none?

  Are the objects of one’s perception actually there? Each school of

  philosophy must offer satisfying answers to these questions. There are

  two standard examples for false cognitions that are commonly utilized

  as heuri
stic devices by the schools of South Asian thought. One is

  incorrectly seeing a rope as a snake. The other often plagues treasure

  seekers at the beach who see a moistened piece of shell and think that

  it is silver. How and why do these false cognitions occur? How is this

  epistemic conundrum connected to sat, real, entities?

  Madhvâcârya provides a different sort of account of error than his

  Advaita opponents and Nyâya predecessors. It will be useful to examine

  briefly both theories before explaining Madhvâcârya’s own.

  Anirvâcanîya-khyâti , the theory that the ontological status of the

  object of a false cognition is indescribable

  The Advaita theory is comprehensive, applying to the microcosmic as

  well as the macrocosmic level.92 The errors that we make in seeing individual things on the level of microcosm is the same kind of error

  that occurs when we see anything at all on the level of macrocosm. All

  perceptions, in some sense, can be sublated. The Advaita position

  has been compared to Berkeley, the English idealist philosopher.93

  91 sâkùîpratyakùato hy eva mânânâü mânateyate | AV 3.2.55.

  92 There are a number of excellent introductions to the epistemology of Advaita Vedânta. See Deutsch, Advaita Vedânta: and Potter, Advaita Vedânta. Many thanks to Vrajaprana Brahmaprana for reading this section.

  93 See Berkeley, Three Dialogues Between Hylas and Philonous.

  58

  Mâdhva Epistemology

  45

  According to the Advaita position, things are never what they seem.

  Such a global cognitive confusion requires that they posit several

  concepts and mechanisms.

  Perceiving a snake as a rope, for example, involves the mechanism of

  adhyâsa, superimposition. A careful householder circumambulating her

  house before retiring may superimpose a snake on a rope. A putatively

  sat, real, rope is thus mistaken for a snake. After a flashlight is obtained and shined on the snake, the superimposition is lifted and the sat, real,

  rope is perceived. But what is the ontological status of the snake? Is it

  sat, real? Or asat, unreal? It cannot be sat, real, as it was denied by the rope. According to the Advaita school, it also cannot be asat, unreal,

  as it was the object of a perceptual cognition. For this reason, it is held

  to be anirvâcanîya, indescribable, neither sat, real, or asat, unreal (see

  Fig. 2.9).94

  ROPE

  SNAKE

  asat

  anirvâcanîya

  2.9 Anirvâcanîya-khyâti-vâda

  According to the Advaita perspective, a parallel error occurs on the

  macrocosmic level as well. The rope in the above example, like the

  snake, is superimposed on something else. The rope and, in fact, all

  empirical perceptions in vyâvahârika, everyday experience, are

  superimposed on brahman. All conventional perceptions, this book,

  your thumb holding the page and the tea you are about to spill as you

  read, are superimposed on brahman. And why does this superimposition

  occur? Scholars of the Advaita school conjecture that avidyâ, ignorance,

  is responsible for false perceptions on the microcosmic level. On the

  macrocosmic level this cosmic ignorance is known as mâyâ, the means

  to illusion as is illustrated in Fig. 2.10.

  94 See the Brahmasiddhi of the 7th-century Advaita scholar, Maõóana Miúra.

  59

  46

  An Introduction to Mâdhva Vedânta

  brahman

  vyâvahârika

  mâyâ

  2.10 Superimposing vyâvahârika on brahman

  As with the snake, the ontological status of the objects in our illusory

  world is anirvâcanîya, indescribable, neither sat, real, or asat, unreal.

  This paradox inspires Úaükarâcârya’s theory to be called the

  anirvâcanîya-khyâti-vâda, The Theory that the Ontological Status of the

  Object of False Cognitions is Indescribable.

  This brief summary is not meant to be comprehensive but to provide

  a foil for the Madhvâcârya’s abhinava-anyathâkhyâti-vâda, the New

  Theory that the False Cognition is Knowing [Something] as Otherwise.

  I examine Madhvâcârya’s refutation of the Advaita position below in

  Chapter 5.

  Anyathâ-khyâti , the theory that false cognition is knowing

  [something] as otherwise

  Madhvâcârya’s theory is called abhinava, new, because it is a

  modification of an earlier one proposed by the Nyâya School, anyathâ-

  khyâti, The Theory that False Cognition is Knowing [Something] as

  Otherwise.95 The Nyâya School holds that, when one sees a shell as silver then one has contact with a sat, real, piece of silver perceived at an earlier time and in an earlier place, for example in a shop, and then

  confuses them. The error is seeing an abheda, identity, of the sat silver and the sat shell as sat, real, when it is asat. But how could such a connection between the silver and the shell occur in the first place? After

  all, it is the shell, not the silver, that is immediately in front of the

  cognizer! According to the Naiyâyikas, the connection occurs through

  alaukika, a super-normal sense relation, fostered by a recollection of the

  previously perceived silver that existed elsewhere (see Fig. 2.11). There is a connection with the earlier perception of the sat, real, silver despite it

  95 See Mohanty’s Classical Indian Philosophy and Dasgupta, A History of Indian Philosophy for more on this school.

  60

  Mâdhva Epistemology

  47

  not being present. There is confusion between the two, the sat, real, shell

  and the sat, real, silver from the shop or wherever it was originally

  perceived. The result is the cognition, ‘This is silver.’ The error is

  negated when the perceiver realizes that the abheda, identity, alone is

  asat, unreal.

  SILVER

  SHELL

  SILVER

  (in the shop)

  sat

  sat

  alaukika

  2.11 Anyathâ-khyâti

  Mâdhvas such as Jayatîrtha, were unhappy with the Nyâya position. If

  the realization that ‘this is not silver’ is founded on the negation of the

  abheda, identity, between the silver and the shell (that is, abheda is correctly perceived as asast rather than sat), then why cannot the same error apply to the silver. That is, cannot asat silver be incorrectly

  perceived as sat? Why is there a need to connect one’s perception to

  silver perceived elsewhere?96 Mâdhvas thus question the necessity to posit the connection that occurs through alaukika, a super-normal sense

  relation. It is for this reason that Madhvâcârya modifies the Nyâya

  theory and derives his abhinava-anyathâ-khyâti, the New Theory that

  False Cognition is Knowing [Something] as Otherwise.

  Madhvâcârya’s abhinava-anyathâ-khyâti , the new theory that false

  cognition is knowing [something] as otherwise

  Madhvâcârya believes that error is apprehending sat, real, as asat,

  unreal, and the asat, unreal, as sat, real.97 It is thus possible to cognize

  96 yathâhuþekadeúâpavâdena kalpyamâne ca bâdhake | na sarvabâdhanaü yuktim iti nyâyavidaþ sthitâþ iti | kiüca rajatasyâtyantâsattve pratibhâso nopapadyate | sthite caivaü sattve bâdhasamaye puro ‘darúanâd deúântare sattvamâsthîyate | doùaduùitaü cakùuþ úuktiúaktiúakalamâtrasannikçùñam api viprakçùñarajatâman
â tadâ darúayatitit ko doùa iti | Nyâya Sudhâ 1.1.1. Thanks to Professor Haridâsa Bhat for this reference.

  97 asataþ sattvapratîtaþ sato ‘sattvapratîtir ity anyathâpratîter eva bhrantitvâta |

  Madhvâcârya, VTV. I am indebted to Professor Haridâsa Bhat for this characterization.

  61

  48

  An Introduction to Mâdhva Vedânta

  the asat, unreal. Error, then, is apprehending something as different

  than itself, apprehending a shell, for example, as a piece of silver.

  Madhvâcârya does not believe that it is necessary to evoke silver in the

  shop in order to explain false cognitions as do his Nyâya predecessors.

  Madhvâcârya holds that the error occurs when one apprehends a sat,

  real, shell as asat, unreal, and the asat, unreal, silver, as sat, real, as illustrated in Fig. 2.12. There is a denial of the actual existence of the object of the illusion, the asat, unreal, silver, while there is an

  affirmation of the existence of the sat, real, shell which is the locus of the false cognition.

  ROPE

  SNAKE

  asat

  sat

  sat

  asat

  2.12 Abhinava-anyathâ-khyâti

  The cakùus, eye, for example comes into contact with the shell and

  then, due to some saüskâra, impression in the memory or defect in the

  cakùus, the sat, real, shell is incorrectly perceived as asat, unreal, silver.

  When the beachgoer realizes the error, the beachgoer experiences the

  realization ‘Silver, which was asat, unreal, appeared to be real, sat.’98

  There is no need to stipulate that there is a sat, real, silver in a shop

  that the cakùus, eye, contacts. But, how does this theory explain the

  confusion between two objects that are similar? According to

  Madhvâcârya, false cognition is a result of seeing a sat, real, abheda, identity, when it is, in fact, asat. For example, if one confuses George

  Bush senior with his son, George Bush junior, it is because the sat, real,

  bheda, difference between the two, is falsely cognized as asat, unreal and the asat, unreal, abheda, identity, is falsely cognized as sat, real.

  Madhvâcârya’s position is distinguished from others as he holds

  that asat, unreal, things can be cognized. It is for this reason that

  Madhvâcârya modifies the Nyâya theory and derives his abhinava-

  98 asad eva rajataü pratyabhâ | VTV.

  62

  Mâdhva Epistemology

 

‹ Prev