Book Read Free

The Big Picture

Page 62

by Carroll, Sean M.


  it also has three possible “colors,” and one times two times three is six. Pho-

  30

  tons have an electric charge fixed at zero, but they do have two possible spin

  31

  states, so they have two degrees of freedom just like electrons do.

  32

  We could interpret the supposed existence of mental properties in the

  33

  most direct way possible, as introducing new degrees of freedom for each

  34

  elementary particle. In addition to spinning clockwise or counterclockwise,

  35S

  a photon could be in one of (let’s say) two mental states. Call them “happy”

  36N

  and “sad,” although the labels are more poetic than authentic.

  364

  Big Picture - UK final proofs.indd 364

  20/07/2016 10:02:54

  A R E PhO t O n S C O n S C I Ou S ?

  This overly literal version of panpsychism cannot possibly be true. One

  01

  of the most basic things we know about the Core Theory is exactly how

  02

  many degrees of freedom each particle has. Recall the Feynman diagrams

  03

  from chapter 23, describing particles scattering off of one another by ex-

  04

  changing other particles. Each diagram corresponds to a number that we

  05

  can compute, the total contribution of that particular process to the end

  06

  result, such as two electrons scattering off of each other by exchanging pho-

  07

  tons. Those numbers have been experimentally tested to exquisite precision,

  08

  and the Core Theory has passed with flying colors.

  09

  A crucial ingredient in calculating these processes is the number of de-

  10

  grees of freedom associated with each particle. If photons had some hidden

  11

  degrees of freedom that we didn’t know about, they would alter all of the

  12

  predictions we make for any scattering experiment that involves such pho-

  13

  tons, and all of our predictions would be contradicted by the data. That

  14

  doesn’t happen. So we can state unambiguously that photons do not come

  15

  in “happy” and “sad” varieties, or any other manner of mental properties

  16

  that act like physical degrees of freedom.

  17

  Advocates of panpsychism would probably not go as far as to imagine

  18

  that mental properties play roles similar to true physical degrees of freedom,

  19

  so that the preceding argument wouldn’t dissuade them. Otherwise these

  20

  new properties would just be ordinary physical properties.

  21

  That leaves us in a position very similar to the zombie discussion: we

  22

  posit new mental properties, and then insist that they have no observable

  23

  physical effects. What would the world be like if we replaced “protocon-

  24

  scious photons” with “zombie photons” lacking such mental properties? As

  25

  far as the behavior of physical matter is concerned, including what you say

  26

  when you talk or write or communicate nonverbally with your romantic

  27

  partner, the zombie- photon world would be exactly the same as the world

  28

  where photons have mental properties.

  29

  A good Bayesian can therefore conclude that the zombie- photon world

  30

  is the one we actually live in. We simply don’t gain anything by attributing

  31

  the features of consciousness to individual particles. Doing so is not a useful

  32

  way of talking about the world; it buys us no new insight or predictive

  33

  power. All it does is add a layer of metaphysical complication onto a descrip-

  34

  tion that is already perfectly successful.

  S35

  Consciousness seems to be an intrinsically collective phenomenon, a

  N36

  365

  Big Picture - UK final proofs.indd 365

  20/07/2016 10:02:55

  T H E B IG PIC T U R E

  01

  way of talking about the behavior of complex systems with the capacity for

  02

  representing themselves and the world within their inner states. Just be-

  03

  cause it is here full- blown in our contemporary universe doesn’t mean that

  04

  there was always some trace of it from the very start. Some things just come

  05

  into being as the universe evolves and entropy and complexity grow: galax-

  06

  ies, planets, organisms, consciousness.

  07

  •

  08

  09

  Regardless of whether individual particles possess a form of protoconscious

  10

  awareness, there is a long history of attempts to link the mystery of con-

  11

  sciousness to another famous mystery, that of quantum mechanics. In part

  12

  these efforts can be attributed to what Chalmers has jokingly called the

  13

  “Law of Minimization of Mystery”: consciousness is confusing, and quan-

  14

  tum mechanics is confusing, so maybe they’re somehow related.

  15

  There is no doubt that there are real mysteries associated with quantum

  16

  mechanics, especially what precisely happens when an observer measures a

  17

  quantum system. In Everett’s Many- Worlds Interpretation, the answer is

  18

  simple: nothing special. Everything continues to smoothly evolve according

  19

  to a deterministic set of equations, but the interaction of the macroscopic

  20

  observer with a vast environment around them causes the way we talk

  21

  about the system to evolve from “one universe in a quantum superposition”

  22

  to “two separate universes.” The fact that observers happen to be con-

  23

  scious plays precisely zero role; measurements can be easily carried out by

  24

  nematodes, video cameras, or rocks.

  25

  Sadly, not everyone accepts the advantages of this approach. In the text-

  26

  book version of quantum mechanics, there is a moment during the observa-

  27

  tion process at which wave functions “collapse.” Before collapse, a particle

  28

  might have been in a superposition of two different states, like spinning

  29

  clockwise and spinning counterclockwise; after collapse, only one alterna-

  30

  tive remains. So what precisely leads to the collapse event? It is not com-

  31

  pletely crazy to speculate that it might have something to do with the

  32

  presence of a conscious observer, and a number of respectable physicists

  33

  have done so over the years.

  34

  The possibility that consciousness plays a role in understanding quan-

  35S

  tum mechanics has lost almost all of whatever support it may have on
ce

  36N

  366

  Big Picture - UK final proofs.indd 366

  20/07/2016 10:02:55

  A R E PhO t O n S C O n S C I Ou S ?

  enjoyed. These days we understand quantum mechanics a lot better than

  01

  the pioneers did; we have very specific and quantitative theories that can

  02

  plausibly explain exactly what happens during the process of measurement,

  03

  without any need to invoke consciousness. We don’t know which if any of

  04

  these theories is right, so mysteries remain— but even without having the

  05

  final answer, the very existence of respectable alternatives tends to make the

  06

  way- out ones seem less attractive.

  07

  Some people have an inordinate fondness for way- out possibilities, and

  08

  will grab on to their associated buzzwords and use them for their own ends.

  09

  Such is the situation with most of what goes by the label of “quantum con-

  10

  sciousness” in popular conversation. Quantum mechanics says that super-

  11

  positions evolve into definite outcomes during the process of measurement,

  12

  at least for any one observer; it’s not hard to twist that into the claim that

  13

  conscious observation literally brings reality into existence.

  14

  It’s the ultimate anti- Copernican move, a way of restoring the central

  15

  importance of humanity to our picture of the universe. Sure, you might feel

  16

  insignificant in the vastness of the cosmos, and perhaps you become alien-

  17

  ated by thinking that your atoms obey impersonal laws of physics, but hey,

  18

  don’t worry: you are personally creating the world at every moment, just by

  19

  looking at it. Advocates of this approach will sometimes throw in some-

  20

  thing about “entanglement”— which isn’t even a mystery, just an interesting

  21

  feature of quantum mechanics— to make you feel like you are connected to

  22

  everything else in the universe. As a final flourish, they might suggest that

  23

  quantum mechanics has discarded the physical world entirely, leaving us

  24

  with idealism, where everything is a projection of the mind.

  25

  There is nothing in anything we know about physics that suggests any

  26

  of that is true. Quantum mechanics may be mysterious, but it is still— in all

  27

  of its suggested formulations— an ordinary physical theory, governed by

  28

  impersonal laws expressed in the form of equations. In particular, even in

  29

  interpretations where wave functions really do collapse when systems are

  30

  observed, the person doing the observing has no influence whatsoever on

  31

  what the measurement outcome turns out to be. That just follows a rule, the

  32

  Born rule for quantum probabilities, which says the probability of each

  33

  outcome is given by the value of the wave function squared. Nothing

  34

  spooky, nothing personal, nothing intrinsically human. Just physics.

  S35

  N36

  367

  Big Picture - UK final proofs.indd 367

  20/07/2016 10:02:55

  T H E B IG PIC T U R E

  01

  •

  02

  03

  “Quantum consciousness” in this disreputable formulation is distinct from

  04

  an idea that is speculative, but at least physically sensible: that quantum

  05

  processes play an important role in the actual workings of the brain. At

  06

  some level this is trivially true. The brain is made of particles, which are

  07

  vibrations of quantum fields, which obey the rules of quantum mechanics.

  08

  But most neuroscience starts with the assumption that important processes

  09

  in the brain are well described by the approximation of classical physics. We

  10

  don’t need wave functions or entanglement to get a rocket to the moon, and

  11

  it seems reasonable to imagine that we don’t need them to understand the

  12

  brain either.

  13

  The brain is a warm, wet environment, not a cold, precise laboratory

  14

  setup. Every particle in your head is constantly being jostled by other par-

  15

  ticles, leading to an ongoing process of “collapse” (or branching of the wave

  16

  function, for fearless Everettians like me). There’s not much time for par-

  17

  ticles to linger in a superposition, become entangled with other particles,

  18

  and so on. Maintaining quantum coherence inside the brain would seem to

  19

  be analogous to building a house of cards outside during a hurricane.

  20

  Nevertheless, recent discoveries in biology have indicated that living

  21

  organisms do seem to take advantage of certain quantum effects that go

  22

  beyond what classical physics could do. Photosynthesis, in particular, in-

  23

  volves transfers of energy by particles in quantum superposition. (Darwin-

  24

  ian evolution stumbled across quantum mechanics long before human

  25

  beings discovered it.) So we can’t discard the possibility that quantum ef-

  26

  fects are important in the brain simply on the basis of pure thought— we

  27

  have to do the usual empiricist Bayesian procedure of inventing hypotheses

  28

  and testing them against the data.

  29

  Physicist Matthew Fisher has identified one very specific set of quantum

  30

  objects in the brain that could become entangled with one another, and

  31

  remain so for a relatively long time: the nuclei of certain phosphorous atoms

  32

  that are found in subgroups of ATP molecules and elsewhere. In Fisher’s

  33

  model, the rate at which chemical reactions involving these atoms will oc-

  34

  cur depends on whether their nuclei share quantum entanglement with

  35S

  other nearby phosphorous nuclei. As a result, quantum mechanics could

  36N

  play a very real role in brain processes, perhaps even allowing the brain to

  368

  Big Picture - UK final proofs.indd 368

  20/07/2016 10:02:55

  A R E PhO t O n S C O n S C I Ou S ?

  act as a “quantum computer.” Or not— these are all new and speculative

  01

  ideas. They do remind us not to jump to conclusions when we’re talking

  02

  about a system as subtle and complicated as a brain.

  03

  When most people think of quantum effects in the brain, however,

  04

  they’re not imagining something as prosaic as accounting for how the brain

  05


  performs computations. They want to invoke new physics to help us explain

  06

  consciousness.

  07

  The most famous proponent of this approach is Roger Penrose, the Brit-

  08

  ish physicist and mathematician renowned for his contributions to our

  09

  modern understanding of Einstein’s general relativity. Penrose is one of

  10

  those scientists who rattles off brilliant ideas like most of us brush bread

  11

  crumbs from our shirts. And he is convinced that human brains do things

  12

  that computers can’t do. But computers can simulate anything that could

  13

  happen according to the known laws of physics. So we need some genuinely

  14

  new physical phenomena at work in the brain— in particular, something

  15

  special about the collapse of the wave function.

  16

  Penrose’s argument is elaborate and ingenious, but ultimately uncon-

  17

  vincing to the vast majority of researchers studying physics, neuroscience,

  18

  or consciousness. He starts with Gödel’s Incompleteness Theorem, a cele-

  19

  brated result by Austrian logician Kurt Gödel. At the risk of dramatic over-

  20

  simplification, the gist of the Incompleteness Theorem is that within any

  21

  consistent mathematical formal system— a set of axioms, and rules for de-

  22

  riving consequences from them— there will be statements that are true but

  23

  cannot be proven within that system. (Gödel’s basic trick was to invent a

  24

  way of expressing “This statement cannot be proven” within any sufficiently

  25

  powerful formal system. Either you can prove it and it is therefore false,

  26

  showing that your system is inconsistent, or you can’t prove it and it’s true.)

  27

  A computer working with the appropriate set of formal rules wouldn’t be

  28

  able to prove such a statement.

  29

  But, Penrose says, human mathematicians have no trouble perceiving

  30

  the truth of statements like that. Therefore, what’s going on inside the brain

  31

  of a human mathematician must be something over and above a formal

  32

  mathematical system. The known laws of physics don’t grant us such

  33

  powers.

  34

  As we discussed in chapter 24, if there is going to be a loophole in the

  S35

  audacious claim that the laws of physics underlying everyday life are

  N36

  369

  Big Picture - UK final proofs.indd 369

  20/07/2016 10:02:55

  T H E B IG PIC T U R E

  01

  completely known, the leading candidate would be some alteration in how

 

‹ Prev