Book Read Free

The Big Picture

Page 64

by Carroll, Sean M.


  vironment in terms of its own molecular structure. The individual molecule

  11

  has no idea it’s part of a snowflake, and could not care less.

  12

  Something like downward causation is possible in principle, even if

  13

  there’s no evidence for it in the real universe. We could imagine a possible

  14

  world in which electrons and atoms obeyed the rules of the Core Theory in

  15

  situations of very low numbers of particles, but started obeying different

  16

  rules when the numbers became large (such as in a human being). Even

  17

  then, the right way to think about the situation would not be “the larger

  18

  structure is influencing the smaller particles”; it’s “the rules we thought

  19

  were obeyed by particles were wrong.” In other words, we could discover

  20

  that the domain of applicability of the Core Theory was smaller than we

  21

  thought it was. There is no evidence that anything along those lines is true,

  22

  and it would violate everything we know about effective quantum field

  23

  theories— but many things are possible.

  24

  The way we talk about human beings and their interactions is going to

  25

  end up being less crisp and precise than our theories of elementary particles.

  26

  It might be harmless, and even useful, to borrow terms from one story be-

  27

  cause they are useful in another one—“diseases are caused by microscopic

  28

  germs” being an obvious example. Drawing relations between different vo-

  29

  cabularies, such as when Boltzmann suggested that the entropy of a gas was

  30

  related to the number of indistinguishable arrangements of the molecules

  31

  of which it was composed, can be extremely valuable and add important

  32

  insights. But if a theory is any good, it has to be able to speak sensibly about

  33

  the phenomena it purports to describe all by itself, without leaning on

  34

  causes being exerted to or from theories at different levels of focus.

  35S

  Mental states are ways of talking about particular physical states. To say

  36N

  376

  Big Picture - UK final proofs.indd 376

  20/07/2016 10:02:55

  W h At AC t S O n W h A t ?

  that a mental state causes a physical effect is precisely as legitimate as saying

  01

  that any macroscopic physical situation is the cause of some macroscopic

  02

  physical event. There is nothing incorrect about attributing your scratching

  03

  to the existence of your itching; there’s simply more than one story we can

  04

  legitimately tell about what’s going on.

  05

  06

  07

  08

  09

  10

  11

  12

  13

  14

  15

  16

  17

  18

  19

  20

  21

  22

  23

  24

  25

  26

  27

  28

  29

  30

  31

  32

  33

  34

  S35

  N36

  377

  Big Picture - UK final proofs.indd 377

  20/07/2016 10:02:55

  01

  02

  03

  44

  04

  05

  Freedom to Choose

  06

  07

  08

  09

  10

  11

  12

  13

  14

  15

  16

  17

  Once we see how mental states can exert physical effects, it’s irresist-

  ible to ask, “Who is in charge of those mental states?” Am I, my

  emergent self, actually making choices? Or am I simply a puppet,

  pulled and pushed as my atoms jostle amongst themselves according to the

  18

  laws of physics? Do I, at the end of the day, have free will?

  19

  There’s a sense in which you do have free will. There’s also a sense in

  20

  which you don’t. Which sense is the “right” one is an issue you’re welcome

  21

  to decide for yourself (if you think you have the ability to make decisions).

  22

  The usual argument against free will is straightforward: We are made of

  23

  atoms, and those atoms follow the patterns we refer to as the laws of phys-

  24

  ics. These laws serve to completely describe the evolution of a system, with-

  25

  out any influences from outside the atomic description. If information

  26

  is conserved through time, the entire future of the universe is already writ-

  27

  ten, even if we don’t know it yet. Quantum mechanics predicts our future

  28

  in terms of probabilities rather than certainties, but those probabilities

  29

  themselves are absolutely fixed by the state of the universe right now. A

  30

  quantum version of Laplace’s Demon could say with confidence what the

  31

  probability of every future history will be, and no amount of human voli-

  32

  tion would be able to change it. There is no room for human choice, so there

  33

  is no such thing as free will. We are just material objects who obey the laws

  34

  of nature.

  35S

  It’s not hard to see where that argument violates our rules. Of course

  36N

  there is no such notion as free will when we are choosing to describe human

  378

  Big Picture - UK final proofs.indd 378

  20/07/2016 10:02:55

  F R E E d O M t O C h O O S E

  beings as collections of atoms or as a quantum wave function. But that says

  01

  nothing about whether the concept nevertheless plays a useful role when we

  02

  choose to describe human beings as people. Indeed, it pretty clearly does

  03

  play a useful role. Even the most diehard anti– free will partisans are con-

  04

  stantly speaking about choices that they and other people make in their

  05

  daily activities, even if they afterward try to make light of it by adding,

  06

  “Except of course the concept of choice doesn’t really exist.”

  07

  The concept of choice does exist, and it would be difficult indeed to

  08

  describe human beings without it. Imagine you’re a high school student

  09

  who wants to go to college, and you’ve been accepted into several universi-

  10

  ties. You look at their web pages, visit campuses, talk to students and fac-

  11

  ulty at each place. Then you say yes to one of them, no to the others. What

  12

  is th
e best way to describe what just happened, the most useful vocabulary

  13

  for talking about our human- scale world? It will inevitably involve some

  14

  statements along the lines of “you made a choice,” and the reasons for that

  15

  choice. If you had been a simplistic robot or a random- number generator,

  16

  there might have been a better way of talking. But it is artificial and coun-

  17

  terproductive to deny ourselves the vocabulary of choice when we talk

  18

  about human beings, regardless of how well we understand the laws of

  19

  physics. This stance is known in the philosophical literature as compatibil-

  20

  ism, and refers to the compatibility between an underlying deterministic

  21

  (or at least impersonal) scientific description and a macroscopic vocabulary

  22

  of choice and volition. Compatibilism, which traces its roots back as far as

  23

  John Locke in the seventeenth century, is the most popular way of thinking

  24

  about free will among professional philosophers.

  25

  From this perspective, the mistake made by free- will skeptics is to care-

  26

  lessly switch between incompatible vocabularies. You step out of the shower

  27

  in the morning, walk to your closet, and wonder whether you should put

  28

  on the black shirt or the blue shirt. That’s a decision that you have to make;

  29

  you can’t just say, “I’ll do whatever the atoms in my body were going to

  30

  deterministically do anyway.” The atoms are going to do whatever they were

  31

  going to do; but you don’t know what that is, and it’s irrelevant to the ques-

  32

  tion of which decision you should make. Once you frame the question in

  33

  terms of you and your choice, you can’t also start talking about your atoms

  34

  and the laws of physics. Either vocabulary is perfectly legitimate, but mix-

  S35

  ing them leads to nonsense.

  N36

  379

  Big Picture - UK final proofs.indd 379

  20/07/2016 10:02:55

  T H E B IG PIC T U R E

  01

  •

  02

  03

  You may be willing to accept that oceans and temperature are real, even

  04

  though they are nowhere to be found among the fundamental ingredients

  05

  of the Core Theory, but feel unwilling to apply the same logic to free will.

  06

  After all, the ability to make choices isn’t just a macroscopic collection of

  07

  many microscopic pieces; it’s an entirely different kind of thing. If it’s not

  08

  there in our best comprehensive description of nature, why is it helpful to

  09

  act like it’s there in our human- scale vocabulary?

  10

  The answer comes down to the arrow of time. In chapter 8 we talked

  11

  about how we have epistemic access to the past— memories— that we don’t

  12

  have when it comes to the future. That’s because there is a special boundary

  13

  condition, the Past Hypothesis, according to which entropy was very low

  14

  near the Big Bang. That’s a powerful bit of information about the past,

  15

  which enables us to pin it down in a way that we can’t pin down the future.

  16

  This temporal asymmetry arises only because of the distribution of matter

  17

  in the universe on macroscopic scales; there is no analogue of it in the Core

  18

  Theory itself.

  19

  There is a crucial role played by the leverage that features of our current

  20

  state exert over our knowledge of events in the past or future. When a fea-

  21

  ture of our current state implies (given the Past Hypothesis, and all else

  22

  being equal) something about the past, that’s a memory; when a feature of

  23

  our current state implies something about the future, that’s a cause of some

  24

  future effect. The small differences in a person’s brain state that correlate

  25

  with different bodily actions typically have negligible correlations with the

  26

  past state of the universe, but they can be correlated with substantially dif-

  27

  ferent future evolutions. That’s why our best human- sized conception of the

  28

  world treats the past and future so differently. We remember the past, and

  29

  our choices affect the future.

  30

  Laplace’s Demon discerns no such imbalance; he sees the whole history

  31

  of the world with perfect clarity. But none of us is Laplace’s Demon. None

  32

  of us knows the exact state of the universe, or has the calculational power

  33

  to predict the future even if we did. The unavoidable reality of our incom-

  34

  plete knowledge is responsible for why we find it useful to talk about the

  35S

  future using a language of choice and causation.

  36N

  One popular definition of free will is “the ability to have acted

  380

  Big Picture - UK final proofs.indd 380

  20/07/2016 10:02:55

  F R E E d O M t O C h O O S E

  differently.” In a world governed by impersonal laws, one can argue that

  01

  there is no such ability. Given the quantum state of the elementary particles

  02

  that make up me and my environment, the future is governed by the laws

  03

  of physics. But in the real world, we are not given that quantum state. We

  04

  have incomplete information; we know about the rough configuration of

  05

  our bodies and we have some idea of our mental states. Given only that

  06

  incomplete information— the information we actually have— it’s com-

  07

  pletely conceivable that we could have acted differently.

  08

  09

  •

  10

  This is the point at which free- will doubters will object that the stance

  11

  we’ve defended here isn’t really free will at all. All we’ve done is redefine the

  12

  notion to mean something completely different, presumably because we are

  13

  too cowardly to face up to the desolate reality of an impersonal cosmos.

  14

  I have no problem with the desolate reality of an impersonal cosmos.

  15

  But it’s important to explore the most accurate and useful ways of talking

  16

  about the world, on all relevant levels.

  17

  Admittedly, some formulations of “free will” go well beyond anything

  18

  that a poetic naturalist would be willing to countenance. There is what is

  19

  called libertarian freedom. This has nothing to do with the political free-r />
  20

  market idea of libertarianism. Rather, it’s the position that human agency

  21

  introduces an element of indeterminacy into the universe; people are not

  22

  governed by the impersonal laws of physics; they have a distinct ability to

  23

  shape their own futures. It’s a denial that there could be anything like La-

  24

  place’s Demon, who could know the future before it happened.

  25

  There’s no reason to accept libertarian freedom as part of the real world.

  26

  There is no direct evidence for it, and it violates everything we know about

  27

  the laws of nature. In order for libertarian freedom to exist, it would have

  28

  to be possible for human beings to overcome the laws of physics just by

  29

  thinking.

  30

  A poetic naturalist says that we can have two very different- sounding

  31

  ways of describing the world, a physics- level story and a human- level story,

  32

  which invoke separate sets of concepts and yet end up being compatible in

  33

  their predictions concerning what happens in the world. A libertarian

  34

  thinks that the right way to talk about human beings ends up making pre-

  S35

  dictions that are incompatible with the known laws of physics. We don’t

  N36

  381

  Big Picture - UK final proofs.indd 381

  20/07/2016 10:02:55

  T H E B IG PIC T U R E

  01

  need to do such dramatic violence to our understanding of reality just to

  02

  make peace with the fact that we make choices as we go through the day.

  03

  In a famous experiment in the 1980s, physiologist Benjamin Libet mea-

  04

  sured brain activity in subjects as they decided to move their hands. The

  05

  volunteers were also observing a clock, and could report precisely when they

  06

  made their decisions. Libet’s results seemed to indicate that there was a

  07

  telltale pulse of brain activity before the subjects became consciously aware

  08

  of their decision. To put it dramatically: part of their brain had seemingly

  09

  made the decision before the people themselves became aware of it.

  10

  Libet’s experiment, and various follow- ups, have become controversial.

  11

  Some claim that they are evidence against the existence of free will, since

  12

  obviously our consciousness is a bit behind the curve when it comes to

  13

  decision making. Others have raised technical concerns about whether the

  14

  signal Libet measured is truly a sign of a decision having been made, and

  15

  whether the subjects were reliable in reporting when their decisions oc-

 

‹ Prev