Various Works

Home > Nonfiction > Various Works > Page 118
Various Works Page 118

by Aristotle


  be just per accidens, in order that they may do us no harm. This

  last principle is the same as the one that precedes it, with, however,

  a different turn of expression. For we desire justice in our friends

  for itself, even though it will make no difference to us, and even

  though they be in India; whereas in our enemies we desire it for

  something else, in order that they may do us no harm.

  Also, that which is in itself the cause of good is more desirable

  than what is so per accidens, e.g. virtue than luck (for the former in

  itself, and the latter per accidens, the cause of good things), and so

  in other cases of the same kind. Likewise also in the case of the

  contrary; for what is in itself the cause of evil is more

  objectionable than what is so per accidens, e.g. vice and chance:

  for the one is bad in itself, whereas chance is so per accidens.

  Also, what is good absolutely is more desirable than what is good

  for a particular person, e.g. recovery of health than a surgical

  operation; for the former is good absolutely, the latter only for a

  particular person, viz. the man who needs an operation. So too what is

  good by nature is more desirable than the good that is not so by

  nature, e.g. justice than the just man; for the one is good by nature,

  whereas in the other case the goodness is acquired. Also the attribute

  is more desirable which belongs to the better and more honourable

  subject, e.g. to a god rather than to a man, and to the soul rather

  than to the body. So too the property of the better thing is better

  than the property of the worse; e.g. the property of God than the

  property of man: for whereas in respect of what is common in both of

  them they do not differ at all from each other, in respect of their

  properties the one surpasses the other. Also that is better which is

  inherent in things better or prior or more honourable: thus (e.g.)

  health is better than strength and beauty: for the former is

  inherent in the moist and the dry, and the hot and the cold, in fact

  in all the primary constituents of an animal, whereas the others are

  inherent in what is secondary, strength being a feature of the

  sinews and bones, while beauty is generally supposed to consist in a

  certain symmetry of the limbs. Also the end is generally supposed to

  be more desirable than the means, and of two means, that which lies

  nearer the end. In general, too, a means directed towards the end of

  life is more desirable than a means to anything else, e.g. that

  which contributes to happiness than that which contributes to

  prudence. Also the competent is more desirable than the incompetent.

  Moreover, of two productive agents that one is more desirable whose

  end is better; while between a productive agent and an end we can

  decide by a proportional sum whenever the excess of the one end over

  the other is greater than that of the latter over its own productive

  means: e.g. supposing the excess of happiness over health to be

  greater than that of health over what produces health, then what

  produces happiness is better than health. For what produces

  happiness exceeds what produces health just as much as happiness

  exceeds health. But health exceeds what produces health by a smaller

  amount; ergo, the excess of what produces happiness over what produces

  health is greater than that of health over what produces health.

  Clearly, therefore, what produces happiness is more desirable than

  health: for it exceeds the same standard by a greater amount.

  Moreover, what is in itself nobler and more precious and

  praiseworthy is more desirable than what is less so, e.g. friendship

  than wealth, and justice than strength. For the former belong in

  themselves to the class of things precious and praiseworthy, while the

  latter do so not in themselves but for something else: for no one

  prizes wealth for itself but always for something else, whereas we

  prize friendship for itself, even though nothing else is likely to

  come to us from it.

  2

  Moreover, whenever two things are very much like one another, and we

  cannot see any superiority in the one over the other of them, we

  should look at them from the standpoint of their consequences. For the

  one which is followed by the greater good is the more desirable: or,

  if the consequences be evil, that is more desirable which is

  followed by the less evil. For though both may be desirable, yet there

  may possibly be some unpleasant consequence involved to turn the

  scale. Our survey from the point of view of consequences lies in two

  directions, for there are prior consequences and later consequences:

  e.g. if a man learns, it follows that he was ignorant before and knows

  afterwards. As a rule, the later consequence is the better to

  consider. You should take, therefore, whichever of the consequences

  suits your purpose.

  Moreover, a greater number of good things is more desirable than a

  smaller, either absolutely or when the one is included in the other,

  viz. the smaller number in the greater. An objection may be raised

  suppose in some particular case the one is valued for the sake of

  the other; for then the two together are not more desirable than the

  one; e.g. recovery of health and health, than health alone, inasmuch

  as we desire recovery of health for the sake of health. Also it is

  quite possible for what is not good, together with what is, to be more

  desirable than a greater number of good things, e.g. the combination

  of happiness and something else which is not good may be more

  desirable than the combination of justice and courage. Also, the

  same things are more valuable if accompanied than if unaccompanied

  by pleasure, and likewise when free from pain than when attended

  with pain.

  Also, everything is more desirable at the season when it is of

  greater consequence; e.g. freedom from pain in old age more than in

  youth: for it is of greater consequence in old age. On the same

  principle also, prudence is more desirable in old age; for no man

  chooses the young to guide him, because he does not expect them to

  be prudent. With courage, the converse is the case, for it is in youth

  that the active exercise of courage is more imperatively required.

  Likewise also with temperance; for the young are more troubled by

  their passions than are their elders.

  Also, that is more desirable which is more useful at every season or

  at most seasons, e.g. justice and temperance rather than courage:

  for they are always useful, while courage is only useful at times.

  Also, that one of two things which if all possess, we do not need

  the other thing, is more desirable than that which all may possess and

  still we want the other one as well. Take the case of justice and

  courage; if everybody were just, there would be no use for courage,

  whereas all might be courageous, and still justice would be of use.

  Moreover, judge by the destructions and losses and generations and

  acquisitions and contraries of things: for things whose destruction is

  more objectionable are themselves mo
re desirable. Likewise also with

  the losses and contraries of things; for a thing whose loss or whose

  contrary is more objectionable is itself more desirable. With the

  generations or acquisitions of things the opposite is the case: for

  things whose acquisition or generation is more desirable are

  themselves also desirable. Another commonplace rule is that what is

  nearer to the good is better and more desirable, i.e. what more nearly

  resembles the good: thus justice is better than a just man. Also, that

  which is more like than another thing to something better than itself,

  as e.g. some say that Ajax was a better man than Odysseus because he

  was more like Achilles. An objection may be raised to this that it

  is not true: for it is quite possible that Ajax did not resemble

  Achilles more nearly than Odysseus in the points which made Achilles

  the best of them, and that Odysseus was a good man, though unlike

  Achilles. Look also to see whether the resemblance be that of a

  caricature, like the resemblance of a monkey to a man, whereas a horse

  bears none: for the monkey is not the more handsome creature,

  despite its nearer resemblance to a man. Again, in the case of two

  things, if one is more like the better thing while another is more

  like the worse, then that is likely to be better which is more like

  the better. This too, however, admits of an objection: for quite

  possibly the one only slightly resembles the better, while the other

  strongly resembles the worse, e.g. supposing the resemblance of Ajax

  to Achilles to be slight, while that of Odysseus to Nestor is

  strong. Also it may be that the one which is like the better type

  shows a degrading likeness, whereas the one which is like the worse

  type improves upon it: witness the likeness of a horse to a donkey,

  and that of a monkey to a man.

  Another rule is that the more conspicuous good is more desirable

  than the less conspicuous, and the more difficult than the easier: for

  we appreciate better the possession of things that cannot be easily

  acquired. Also the more personal possession is more desirable than the

  more widely shared. Also, that which is more free from connexion

  with evil: for what is not attended by any unpleasantness is more

  desirable than what is so attended.

  Moreover, if A be without qualification better than B, then also the

  best of the members of A is better than the best of the members of

  B; e.g. if Man be better than Horse, then also the best man is

  better than the best horse. Also, if the best in A be better than

  the best in B, then also A is better than B without qualification;

  e.g. if the best man be better than the best horse, then also Man is

  better than Horse without qualification.

  Moreover, things which our friends can share are more desirable than

  those they cannot. Also, things which we like rather to do to our

  friend are more desirable than those we like to do to the man in the

  street, e.g. just dealing and the doing of good rather than the

  semblance of them: for we would rather really do good to our friends

  than seem to do so, whereas towards the man in the street the converse

  is the case.

  Also, superfluities are better than necessities, and are sometimes

  more desirable as well: for the good life is better than mere life,

  and good life is a superfluity, whereas mere life itself is a

  necessity. Sometimes, though, what is better is not also more

  desirable: for there is no necessity that because it is better it

  should also be more desirable: at least to be a philosopher is

  better than to make money, but it is not more desirable for a man

  who lacks the necessities of life. The expression 'superfluity'

  applies whenever a man possesses the necessities of life and sets to

  work to secure as well other noble acquisitions. Roughly speaking,

  perhaps, necessities are more desirable, while superfluities are

  better.

  Also, what cannot be got from another is more desirable than what

  can be got from another as well, as (e.g.) is the case of justice

  compared with courage. Also, A is more desirable if A is desirable

  without B, but not B without A: power (e.g.) is not desirable

  without prudence, but prudence is desirable without power. Also, if of

  two things we repudiate the one in order to be thought to possess

  the other, then that one is more desirable which we wish to be thought

  to possess; thus (e.g.) we repudiate the love of hard work in order

  that people may think us geniuses.

  Moreover, that is more desirable in whose absence it is less

  blameworthy for people to be vexed; and that is more desirable in

  whose absence it is more blameworthy for a man not to be vexed.

  3

  Moreover, of things that belong to the same species one which

  possesses the peculiar virtue of the species is more desirable than

  one which does not. If both possess it, then the one which possesses

  it in a greater degree is more desirable.

  Moreover, if one thing makes good whatever it touches, while another

  does not, the former is more desirable, just as also what makes things

  warm is warmer than what does not. If both do so, then that one is

  more desirable which does so in a greater degree, or if it render good

  the better and more important object-if (e.g.), the one makes good the

  soul, and the other the body.

  Moreover, judge things by their inflexions and uses and actions

  and works, and judge these by them: for they go with each other:

  e.g. if 'justly' means something more desirable than 'courageously',

  then also justice means something more desirable than courage; and

  if justice be more desirable than courage, then also 'justly' means

  something more desirable than 'courageously'. Similarly also in the

  other cases.

  Moreover, if one thing exceeds while the other falls short of the

  same standard of good, the one which exceeds is the more desirable; or

  if the one exceeds an even higher standard. Nay more, if there be

  two things both preferable to something, the one which is more

  highly preferable to it is more desirable than the less highly

  preferable. Moreover, when the excess of a thing is more desirable

  than the excess of something else, that thing is itself also more

  desirable than the other, as (e.g.) friendship than money: for an

  excess of friendship is more desirable than an excess of money. So

  also that of which a man would rather that it were his by his own

  doing is more desirable than what he would rather get by another's

  doing, e.g. friends than money. Moreover, judge by means of an

  addition, and see if the addition of A to the same thing as B makes

  the whole more desirable than does the addition of B. You must,

  however, beware of adducing a case in which the common term uses, or

  in some other way helps the case of, one of the things added to it,

  but not the other, as (e.g.) if you took a saw and a sickle in

  combination with the art of carpentry: for in the combination the

  saw is a more desirable thing, but it is not a more desirable thing

  without qua
lification. Again, a thing is more desirable if, when added

  to a lesser good, it makes the whole greater good. Likewise, also, you

  should judge by means of subtraction: for the thing upon whose

  subtraction the remainder is a lesser good may be taken to be a

  greater good, whichever it be whose subtraction makes the remainder

  a lesser good.

  Also, if one thing be desirable for itself, and the other for the

  look of it, the former is more desirable, as (e.g.) health than

  beauty. A thing is defined as being desired for the look of it if,

  supposing no one knew of it, you would not care to have it. Also, it

  is more desirable both for itself and for the look of it, while the

  other thing is desirable on the one ground alone. Also, whichever is

  the more precious for itself, is also better and more desirable. A

  thing may be taken to be more precious in itself which we choose

  rather for itself, without anything else being likely to come of it.

  Moreover, you should distinguish in how many senses 'desirable' is

  used, and with a view to what ends, e.g. expediency or honour or

  pleasure. For what is useful for all or most of them may be taken to

  be more desirable than what is not useful in like manner. If the

  same characters belong to both things you should look and see which

  possesses them more markedly, i.e. which of the two is the more

  pleasant or more honourable or more expedient. Again, that is more

  desirable which serves the better purpose, e.g. that which serves to

  promote virtue more than that which serves to promote pleasure.

  Likewise also in the case of objectionable things; for that is more

  objectionable which stands more in the way of what is desirable,

  e.g. disease more than ugliness: for disease is a greater hindrance

  both to pleasure and to being good.

  Moreover, argue by showing that the thing in question is in like

  measure objectionable and desirable: for a thing of such a character

  that a man might well desire and object to it alike is less

  desirable than the other which is desirable only.

 

‹ Prev