Various Works

Home > Nonfiction > Various Works > Page 122
Various Works Page 122

by Aristotle


  are desirable, and therefore it is we say that even God and the good

  man possess them; for they are capable (we say) of doing evil. So then

  'capacity' can never be the genus of anything blameworthy. Else, the

  result will be that what is blameworthy is sometimes desirable: for

  there will be a certain form of capacity that is blameworthy.

  Also, see if he has put anything that is precious or desirable for

  its own sake into the class 'capacity' or 'capable' or 'productive' of

  anything. For capacity, and what is capable or productive of anything,

  is always desirable for the sake of something else.

  Or see if he has put anything that exists in two genera or more into

  one of them only. For some things it is impossible to place in a

  single genus, e.g. the 'cheat' and the 'slanderer': for neither he who

  has the will without the capacity, nor he who has the capacity without

  the will, is a slanderer or cheat, but he who has both of them.

  Hence he must be put not into one genus, but into both the aforesaid

  genera.

  Moreover, people sometimes in converse order render genus as

  differentia, and differentia as genus, defining (e.g.) astonishment as

  'excess of wonderment' and conviction as 'vehemence of conception'.

  For neither 'excess' nor 'vehemence' is the genus, but the

  differentia: for astonishment is usually taken to be an 'excessive

  wonderment', and conviction to be a 'vehement conception', so that

  'wonderment' and 'conception' are the genus, while 'excess' and

  'vehemence' are the differentia. Moreover, if any one renders 'excess'

  and 'vehemence' as genera, then inanimate things will be convinced and

  astonished. For 'vehemence' and 'excess' of a thing are found in a

  thing which is thus vehement and in excess. If, therefore,

  astonishment be excess of wonderment the astonishment will be found in

  the wonderment, so that 'wonderment' will be astonished! Likewise,

  also, conviction will be found in the conception, if it be

  'vehemence of conception', so that the conception will be convinced.

  Moreover, a man who renders an answer in this style will in

  consequence find himself calling vehemence vehement and excess

  excessive: for there is such a thing as a vehement conviction: if then

  conviction be 'vehemence', there would be a 'vehement vehemence'.

  Likewise, also, there is such a thing as excessive astonishment: if

  then astonishment be an excess, there would be an 'excessive

  excess'. Whereas neither of these things is generally believed, any

  more than that knowledge is a knower or motion a moving thing.

  Sometimes, too, people make the bad mistake of putting an

  affection into that which is affected, as its genus, e.g. those who

  say that immortality is everlasting life: for immortality seems to

  be a certain affection or accidental feature of life. That this saying

  is true would appear clear if any one were to admit that a man can

  pass from being mortal and become immortal: for no one will assert

  that he takes another life, but that a certain accidental feature or

  affection enters into this one as it is. So then 'life' is not the

  genus of immortality.

  Again, see if to an affection he has ascribed as genus the object of

  which it is an affection, by defining (e.g.) wind as 'air in

  motion'. Rather, wind is 'a movement of air': for the same air

  persists both when it is in motion and when it is still. Hence wind is

  not 'air' at all: for then there would also have been wind when the

  air was not in motion, seeing that the same air which formed the

  wind persists. Likewise, also, in other cases of the kind. Even, then,

  if we ought in this instance to admit the point that wind is 'air in

  motion', yet we should accept a definition of the kind, not about

  all those things of which the genus is not true, but only in cases

  where the genus rendered is a true predicate. For in some cases,

  e.g. 'mud' or 'snow', it is not generally held to be true. For

  people tell you that snow is 'frozen water' and mud is earth mixed

  with moisture', whereas snow is not water, nor mud earth, so that

  neither of the terms rendered could be the genus: for the genus should

  be true of all its species. Likewise neither is wine 'fermented

  water', as Empedocles speaks of 'water fermented in wood';' for it

  simply is not water at all.

  6

  Moreover, see whether the term rendered fail to be the genus of

  anything at all; for then clearly it also fails to be the genus of the

  species mentioned. Examine the point by seeing whether the objects

  that partake of the genus fail to be specifically different from one

  another, e.g. white objects: for these do not differ specifically from

  one another, whereas of a genus the species are always different, so

  that 'white' could not be the genus of anything.

  Again, see whether he has named as genus or differentia some feature

  that goes with everything: for the number of attributes that follow

  everything is comparatively large: thus (e.g.) 'Being' and 'Unity' are

  among the number of attributes that follow everything. If,

  therefore, he has rendered 'Being' as a genus, clearly it would be the

  genus of everything, seeing that it is predicated of everything; for

  the genus is never predicated of anything except of its species. Hence

  Unity, inter alia, will be a species of Being. The result,

  therefore, is that of all things of which the genus is predicated, the

  species is predicated as well, seeing that Being and Unity are

  predicates of absolutely everything, whereas the predication of the

  species ought to be of narrower range. If, on the other hand, he has

  named as differentia some attribute that follows everything, clearly

  the denotation of the differentia will be equal to, or wider than,

  that of the genus. For if the genus, too, be some attribute that

  follows everything, the denotation of the differentia will be equal to

  its denotation, while if the genus do not follow everything, it will

  be still wider.

  Moreover, see if the description 'inherent in S' be used of the

  genus rendered in relation to its species, as it is used of 'white' in

  the case of snow, thus showing clearly that it could not be the genus:

  for 'true of S' is the only description used of the genus in

  relation to its species. Look and see also if the genus fails to be

  synonymous with its species. For the genus is always predicated of its

  species synonymously.

  Moreover, beware, whenever both species and genus have a contrary,

  and he places the better of the contraries inside the worse genus: for

  the result will be that the remaining species will be found in the

  remaining genus, seeing that contraries are found in contrary

  genera, so that the better species will be found in the worse genus

  and the worse in the better: whereas the usual view is that of the

  better species the genus too is better. Also see if he has placed

  the species inside the worse and not inside the better genus, when

  it is at the same time related in like manner to both, as (e.g.) if he

  has defined the 'soul'
as a 'form of motion' or 'a form of moving

  thing'. For the same soul is usually thought to be a principle alike

  of rest and of motion, so that, if rest is the better of the two, this

  is the genus into which the soul should have been put.

  Moreover, judge by means of greater and less degrees: if

  overthrowing a view, see whether the genus admits of a greater degree,

  whereas neither the species itself does so, nor any term that is

  called after it: e.g. if virtue admits of a greater degree, so too

  does justice and the just man: for one man is called 'more just than

  another'. If, therefore, the genus rendered admits of a greater

  degree, whereas neither the species does so itself nor yet any term

  called after it, then what has been rendered could not be the genus.

  Again, if what is more generally, or as generally, thought to be the

  genus be not so, clearly neither is the genus rendered. The

  commonplace rule in question is useful especially in cases where the

  species appears to have several predicates in the category of essence,

  and where no distinction has been drawn between them, and we cannot

  say which of them is genus; e.g. both 'pain' and the 'conception of

  a slight' are usually thought to be predicates of 'anger in the

  category of essence: for the angry man is both in pain and also

  conceives that he is slighted. The same mode of inquiry may be applied

  also to the case of the species, by comparing it with some other

  species: for if the one which is more generally, or as generally,

  thought to be found in the genus rendered be not found therein, then

  clearly neither could the species rendered be found therein.

  In demolishing a view, therefore, you should follow the rule as

  stated. In establishing one, on the other hand, the commonplace rule

  that you should see if both the genus rendered and the species admit

  of a greater degree will not serve: for even though both admit it,

  it is still possible for one not to be the genus of the other. For

  both 'beautiful' and 'white' admit of a greater degree, and neither is

  the genus of the other. On the other hand, the comparison of the

  genera and of the species one with another is of use: e.g. supposing A

  and B to have a like claim to be genus, then if one be a genus, so

  also is the other. Likewise, also, if what has less claim be a

  genus, so also is what has more claim: e.g. if 'capacity' have more

  claim than 'virtue' to be the genus of self-control, and virtue be the

  genus, so also is capacity. The same observations will apply also in

  the case of the species. For instance, supposing A and B to have a

  like claim to be a species of the genus in question, then if the one

  be a species, so also is the other: and if that which is less

  generally thought to be so be a species, so also is that which is more

  generally thought to be so.

  Moreover, to establish a view, you should look and see if the

  genus is predicated in the category of essence of those things of

  which it has been rendered as the genus, supposing the species

  rendered to be not one single species but several different ones:

  for then clearly it will be the genus. If, on the other, the species

  rendered be single, look and see whether the genus be predicated in

  the category of essence of other species as well: for then, again, the

  result will be that it is predicated of several different species.

  Since some people think that the differentia, too, is a predicate of

  the various species in the category of essence, you should distinguish

  the genus from the differentia by employing the aforesaid elementary

  principles-(a) that the genus has a wider denotation than the

  differentia; (b) that in rendering the essence of a thing it is more

  fitting to state the genus than the differentia: for any one who

  says that 'man' is an 'animal' shows what man is better than he who

  describes him as 'walking'; also (c) that the differentia always

  signifies a quality of the genus, whereas the genus does not do this

  of the differentia: for he who says 'walking' describes an animal of a

  certain quality, whereas he who says 'animal' describes an animal of a

  certain quality, whereas he who says 'animal' does not describe a

  walking thing of a certain quality.

  The differentia, then, should be distinguished from the genus in

  this manner. Now seeing it is generally held that if what is

  musical, in being musical, possesses knowledge in some respect, then

  also 'music' is a particular kind of 'knowledge'; and also that if

  what walks is moved in walking, then 'walking' is a particular kind of

  'movement'; you should therefore examine in the aforesaid manner any

  genus in which you want to establish the existence of something;

  e.g. if you wish to prove that 'knowledge' is a form of

  'conviction', see whether the knower in knowing is convinced: for then

  clearly knowledge would be a particular kind of conviction. You should

  proceed in the same way also in regard to the other cases of this

  kind.

  Moreover, seeing that it is difficult to distinguish whatever always

  follows along with a thing, and is not convertible with it, from its

  genus, if A follows B universally, whereas B does not follow A

  universally-as e.g. 'rest' always follows a 'calm' and

  'divisibility' follows 'number', but not conversely (for the divisible

  is not always a number, nor rest a calm)-you may yourself assume in

  your treatment of them that the one which always follows is the genus,

  whenever the other is not convertible with it: if, on the other

  hand, some one else puts forward the proposition, do not accept it

  universally. An objection to it is that 'not-being' always follows

  what is 'coming to be' (for what is coming to be is not) and is not

  convertible with it (for what is not is not always coming to be),

  and that still 'not-being' is not the genus of 'coming to be': for

  'not-being' has not any species at all. Questions, then, in regard

  to Genus should be investigated in the ways described.

  Book V

  1

  THE question whether the attribute stated is or is not a property,

  should be examined by the following methods:

  Any 'property' rendered is always either essential and permanent

  or relative and temporary: e.g. it is an 'essential property' of man

  to be 'by nature a civilized animal': a 'relative property' is one

  like that of the soul in relation to the body, viz. that the one is

  fitted to command, and the other to obey: a 'permanent property' is

  one like the property which belongs to God, of being an 'immortal

  living being': a 'temporary property' is one like the property which

  belongs to any particular man of walking in the gymnasium.

  [The rendering of a property 'relatively' gives rise either to two

  problems or to four. For if he at the same time render this property

  of one thing and deny it of another, only two problems arise, as in

  the case of a statement that it is a property of a man, in relation to

  a horse, to be a biped. For one might try both to show that a man is

  not a biped, and also that a hors
e is a biped: in both ways the

  property would be upset. If on the other hand he render one apiece

  of two attributes to each of two things, and deny it in each case of

  the other, there will then be four problems; as in the case of a

  statement that it is a property of a man in relation to a horse for

  the former to be a biped and the latter a quadruped. For then it is

  possible to try to show both that a man is not naturally a biped,

  and that he is a quadruped, and also that the horse both is a biped,

  and is not a quadruped. If you show any of these at all, the

  intended attribute is demolished.]

  An 'essential' property is one which is rendered of a thing in

  comparison with everything else and distinguishes the said thing

  from everything else, as does 'a mortal living being capable of

  receiving knowledge' in the case of man. A 'relative' property is

  one which separates its subject off not from everything else but

  only from a particular definite thing, as does the property which

  virtue possesses, in comparison with knowledge, viz. that the former

  is naturally produced in more than one faculty, whereas the latter

  is produced in that of reason alone, and in those who have a reasoning

  faculty. A 'permanent' property is one which is true at every time,

  and never fails, like being' compounded of soul and body', in the case

  of a living creature. A 'temporary' property is one which is true at

  some particular time, and does not of necessity always follow; as,

  of some particular man, that he walks in the market-place.

  To render a property 'relatively' to something else means to state

  the difference between them as it is found either universally and

  always, or generally and in most cases: thus a difference that is

  found universally and always, is one such as man possesses in

  comparison with a horse, viz. being a biped: for a man is always and

  in every case a biped, whereas a horse is never a biped at any time.

  On the other hand, a difference that is found generally and in most

  cases, is one such as the faculty of reason possesses in comparison

 

‹ Prev