Book Read Free

Various Works

Page 124

by Aristotle


  man', states the property of the present time, and so he cannot have

  rendered the property correctly, seeing that he has described it

  without any definite proviso. For constructive purposes, on the

  other hand, see whether, in rendering the property of the present

  time, he has, in stating it, made a definite proviso that it is the

  property of the present time that he is stating: for then the property

  will in this respect have been correctly stated. Thus (e.g.) a man who

  has said that it is the property of a particular man 'to be walking

  now', has made this distinction in his statement, and so the

  property would have been correctly stated.

  Next, for destructive purposes, see whether he has rendered a

  property of the kind whose appropriateness is not obvious except by

  sensation: for then the property will not have been correctly

  stated. For every sensible attribute, once it is taken beyond the

  sphere of sensation, becomes uncertain. For it is not clear whether it

  still belongs, because it is evidenced only by sensation. This

  principle will be true in the case of any attributes that do not

  always and necessarily follow. Thus (e.g.) any one who has stated that

  it is a property of the sun to be 'the brightest star that moves

  over the earth', has used in describing the property an expression

  of that kind, viz. 'to move over the earth', which is evidenced by

  sensation; and so the sun's property could not have been correctly

  rendered: for it will be uncertain, whenever the sun sets, whether

  it continues to move over the earth, because sensation then fails

  us. For constructive purposes, on the other hand, see whether he has

  rendered the property of a kind that is not obvious to sensation,

  or, if it be sensible, must clearly belong of necessity: for then

  the property will in this respect have been correctly stated. Thus

  (e.g.) a man who has stated that it is a property of a surface to be

  'the primary thing that is coloured', has introduced amongst the

  rest a sensible quality, 'to be coloured', but still a quality such as

  manifestly always belongs, and so the property of 'surface' would in

  this respect have been correctly rendered.

  Next, for destructive purposes, see whether he has rendered the

  definition as a property: for then the property will not have been

  correctly stated: for the property of a thing ought not to show its

  essence. Thus (e.g.) a man who has said that it is the property of man

  to be 'a walking, biped animal' has rendered a property of man so as

  to signify his essence, and so the property of man could not have been

  correctly rendered. For constructive purposes, on the other hand,

  see whether the property which he has rendered forms a predicate

  convertible with its subject, without, however, signifying its

  essence: for then the property will in this respect have been

  correctly rendered. Thus (e.g.) he who has stated that it is a

  property of man to be a 'naturally civilized animal' has rendered

  the property so as to be convertible with its subject, without,

  however, showing its essence, and so the property of man' would in

  this respect have been correctly rendered.

  Next, for destructive purposes, see whether he has rendered the

  property without having placed the subject within its essence. For

  of properties, as also of definitions, the first term to be rendered

  should be the genus, and then the rest of it should be appended

  immediately afterwards, and should distinguish its subject from

  other things. Hence a property which is not stated in this way could

  not have been correctly rendered. Thus (e.g.) a man who has said

  that it is a property of a living creature to 'have a soul' has not

  placed 'living creature' within its essence, and so the property of

  a living creature could not have been correctly stated. For

  constructive purposes, on the other hand, see whether a man first

  places within its essence the subject whose property he is

  rendering, and then appends the rest: for then the property will in

  this respect have been correctly rendered. Thus (e.g.) he who has

  stated that is a property of man to be an 'animal capable of receiving

  knowledge', has rendered the property after placing the subject within

  its essence, and so the property of 'man' would in this respect have

  been correctly rendered.

  4

  The inquiry, then, whether the property has been correctly

  rendered or no, should be made by these means. The question, on the

  other hand, whether what is stated is or is not a property at all, you

  should examine from the following points of view. For the

  commonplace arguments which establish absolutely that the property

  is accurately stated will be the same as those that constitute it a

  property at all: accordingly they will be described in the course of

  them.

  Firstly, then, for destructive purposes, take a look at each subject

  of which he has rendered the property, and see (e.g.) if it fails to

  belong to any of them at all, or to be true of them in that particular

  respect, or to be a property of each of them in respect of that

  character of which he has rendered the property: for then what is

  stated to be a property will not be a property. Thus, for example,

  inasmuch as it is not true of the geometrician that he 'cannot be

  deceived by an argument' (for a geometrician is deceived when his

  figure is misdrawn), it could not be a property of the man of

  science that he is not deceived by an argument. For constructive

  purposes, on the other hand, see whether the property rendered be true

  of every instance, and true in that particular respect: for then

  what is stated not to be a property will be a property. Thus, for

  example, in as much as the description 'an animal capable of receiving

  knowledge' is true of every man, and true of him qua man, it would

  be a property of man to be 'an animal capable of receiving knowledge'.

  commonplace rule means-for destructive purposes, see if the

  description fails to be true of that of which the name is true; and if

  the name fails to be true of that of which the description is true:

  for constructive purposes, on the other hand, see if the description

  too is predicated of that of which the name is predicated, and if

  the name too is predicated of that of which the description is

  predicated.]

  Next, for destructive purposes, see if the description fails to

  apply to that to which the name applies, and if the name fails to

  apply to that to which the description applies: for then what is

  stated to be a property will not be a property. Thus (e.g.) inasmuch

  as the description 'a living being that partakes of knowledge' is true

  of God, while 'man' is not predicated of God, to be a living being

  that partakes of knowledge' could not be a property of man. For

  constructive purposes, on the other hand, see if the name as well be

  predicated of that of which the description is predicated, and if

  the description as well be predicated of that of which the name is

  predicated. For then what
is stated not to be a property will be a

  property. Thus (e.g.) the predicate 'living creature' is true of

  that of which 'having a soul' is true, and 'having a soul' is true

  of that of which the predicate 'living creature' is true; and so

  'having a soul would be a property of 'living creature'.

  Next, for destructive purposes, see if he has rendered a subject

  as a property of that which is described as 'in the subject': for then

  what has been stated to be a property will not be a property. Thus

  (e.g.) inasmuch as he who has rendered 'fire' as the property of

  'the body with the most rarefied particles', has rendered the

  subject as the property of its predicate, 'fire' could not be a

  property of 'the body with the most rarefied particles'. The reason

  why the subject will not be a property of that which is found in the

  subject is this, that then the same thing will be the property of a

  number of things that are specifically different. For the same thing

  has quite a number of specifically different predicates that belong to

  it alone, and the subject will be a property of all of these, if any

  one states the property in this way. For constructive purposes, on the

  other hand, see if he has rendered what is found in the subject as a

  property of the subject: for then what has been stated not to be a

  property will be a property, if it be predicated only of the things of

  which it has been stated to be the property. Thus (e.g.) he who has

  said that it is a property of 'earth' to be 'specifically the heaviest

  body' has rendered of the subject as its property something that is

  said of the thing in question alone, and is said of it in the manner

  in which a property is predicated, and so the property of earth

  would have been rightly stated.

  Next, for destructive purposes, see if he has rendered the

  property as partaken of: for then what is stated to be a property will

  not be a property. For an attribute of which the subject partakes is a

  constituent part of its essence: and an attribute of that kind would

  be a differentia applying to some one species. E.g. inasmuch as he who

  has said that 'walking on two feet' is property of man has rendered

  the property as partaken of, 'walking on two feet' could not be a

  property of 'man'. For constructive purposes, on the other hand, see

  if he has avoided rendering the property as partaken of, or as showing

  the essence, though the subject is predicated convertibly with it: for

  then what is stated not to be a property will be a property. Thus

  (e.g.) he who has stated that to be 'naturally sentient' is a property

  of 'animal' has rendered the property neither as partaken of nor as

  showing the essence, though the subject is predicated convertibly with

  it; and so to be 'naturally sentient' would be a property of 'animal'.

  Next, for destructive purposes, see if the property cannot

  possibly belong simultaneously, but must belong either as posterior or

  as prior to the attribute described in the name: for then what is

  stated to be a property will not be a property either never, or not

  always. Thus (e.g.) inasmuch as it is possible for the attribute

  'walking through the market-place' to belong to an object as prior and

  as posterior to the attribute 'man', 'walking through the

  market-place' could not be a property of 'man' either never, or not

  always. For constructive purposes, on the other hand, see if it always

  and of necessity belongs simultaneously, without being either a

  definition or a differentia: for then what is stated not to be a

  property will be a property. Thus (e.g.) the attribute 'an animal

  capable of receiving knowledge' always and of necessity belongs

  simultaneously with the attribute 'man', and is neither differentia

  nor definition of its subject, and so 'an animal capable of

  receiving knowledge' would be a property of 'man'.

  Next, for destructive purposes, see if the same thing fails to be

  a property of things that are the same as the subject, so far as

  they are the same: for then what is stated to be a property will not

  be a property. Thus, for example, inasmuch as it is no property of a

  'proper object of pursuit' to 'appear good to certain persons', it

  could not be a property of the 'desirable' either to 'appear good to

  certain persons': for 'proper object of pursuit' and 'desirable'

  mean the same. For constructive purposes, on the other hand, see if

  the same thing be a property of something that is the same as the

  subject, in so far as it is the same. For then is stated not to be a

  property will be a property. Thus (e.g.) inasmuch as it is called a

  property of a man, in so far as he is a man, 'to have a tripartite

  soul', it would also be a property of a mortal, in so far as he is a

  mortal, to have a tripartite soul. This commonplace rule is useful

  also in dealing with Accident: for the same attributes ought either to

  belong or not belong to the same things, in so far as they are the

  same.

  Next, for destructive purposes, see if the property of things that

  are the same in kind as the subject fails to be always the same in

  kind as the alleged property: for then neither will what is stated

  to be the property of the subject in question. Thus (e.g.) inasmuch as

  a man and a horse are the same in kind, and it is not always a

  property of a horse to stand by its own initiative, it could not be

  a property of a man to move by his own initiative; for to stand and to

  move by his own initiative are the same in kind, because they belong

  to each of them in so far as each is an 'animal'. For constructive

  purposes, on the other hand, see if of things that are the same in

  kind as the subject the property that is the same as the alleged

  property is always true: for then what is stated not to be a

  property will be a property. Thus (e.g.) since it is a property of man

  to be a 'walking biped,' it would also be a property of a bird to be a

  'flying biped': for each of these is the same in kind, in so far as

  the one pair have the sameness of species that fall under the same

  genus, being under the genus 'animal', while the other pair have

  that of differentiae of the genus, viz. of 'animal'. This

  commonplace rule is deceptive whenever one of the properties mentioned

  belongs to some one species only while the other belongs to many, as

  does 'walking quadruped'.

  Inasmuch as 'same' and 'different' are terms used in several senses,

  it is a job to render to a sophistical questioner a property that

  belongs to one thing and that only. For an attribute that belongs to

  something qualified by an accident will also belong to the accident

  taken along with the subject which it qualifies; e.g. an attribute

  that belongs to 'man' will belong also to 'white man', if there be a

  white man, and one that belongs to 'white man' will belong also to

  'man'. One might, then, bring captious criticism against the

  majority of properties, by representing the subject as being one thing

  in itself, and another thing when combined with its accident,

  saying, for example, that 'man' is one
thing, and white man'

  another, and moreover by representing as different a certain state and

  what is called after that state. For an attribute that belongs to

  the state will belong also to what is called after that state, and one

  that belongs to what is called after a state will belong also to the

  state: e.g. inasmuch as the condition of the scientist is called after

  his science, it could not be a property of 'science' that it is

  'incontrovertible by argument'; for then the scientist also will be

  incontrovertible by argument. For constructive purposes, however,

  you should say that the subject of an accident is not absolutely

  different from the accident taken along with its subject; though it is

  called 'another' thing because the mode of being of the two is

  different: for it is not the same thing for a man to be a man and

  for a white man to be a white man. Moreover, you should take a look

  along at the inflections, and say that the description of the man of

  science is wrong: one should say not 'it' but 'he is

  incontrovertible by argument'; while the description of Science is

  wrong too: one should say not 'it' but 'she is incontrovertible by

  argument'. For against an objector who sticks at nothing the defence

  should stick at nothing.

  5

  Next, for destructive purposes, see if, while intending to render an

  attribute that naturally belongs, he states it in his language in such

  a way as to indicate one that invariably belongs: for then it would be

  generally agreed that what has been stated to be a property is

  upset. Thus (e.g.) the man who has said that 'biped' is a property

  of man intends to render the attribute that naturally belongs, but his

  expression actually indicates one that invariably belongs:

  accordingly, 'biped' could not be a property of man: for not every man

  is possessed of two feet. For constructive purposes, on the other

  hand, see if he intends to render the property that naturally belongs,

  and indicates it in that way in his language: for then the property

  will not be upset in this respect. Thus (e.g.) he who renders as a

  property of 'man' the phrase 'an animal capable of receiving

 

‹ Prev