Why Faith Fails The Christian Delusion

Home > Other > Why Faith Fails The Christian Delusion > Page 46
Why Faith Fails The Christian Delusion Page 46

by John W. Loftus

religion; and not only the Christian religion, but the Protestant religion; and not

  only the Protestant religion, but the Church of England." It is utterly inadequate

  and more than a bit egocentric.

  Other, more serious, attempts have been made to define religion, in

  psychology, sociology, anthropology, and biology. Some emphasize individual

  experience (especially the "transcendent feeling" or the "oceanic feeling," etc.);

  others stress ritual or myth or belief or institutions or, inevitably, morality. In

  reality, all of these are aspects of religion, but none of them is the essence or sine

  qua non of religion: there are religions without god(s), without (much) ritual,

  without (much) myth, without (many) institutions, and-depending on who you

  talk to-without morality. Rather, all of these are potential elements or building

  blocks of religions, in what many contemporary theorists have suggested as a

  "modular" approach to religion. In other words, according to thinkers like Pascal

  Boyeru and Scott Atran,2 religion is not a "thing" at all but a composite of basic

  elements which, most critically, are not fundamentally "religious" in and of

  themselves. That is, there are religious rituals and there are nonreligious rituals;

  there are religious stories and there are nonreligious stories; there are religious

  institutions and there are nonreligious institutions; and, most importantly for our

  present purpose, there are religious moralities and there are nonreligious

  moralities. All of these are human phenomena, not specifically or exclusively

  religious phenomena.

  If there is, nevertheless, one quality that religions seem to share, it is what has

  been called "agency." Agency essentially means "intelligence" or "will" or,

  perhaps most profoundly, "intention." Agents are the kinds of beings who have

  intelligence or will or intention, who are not mere objects of natural forces but

  who make some choices on the basis of their own nature and interests. Agents

  are, in short, "persons," and human beings are the agents or persons with which

  we are most familiar. As Graham Harvey puts it:

  Persons are those with whom other persons interact with varying degrees of

  reciprocity. Persons may be spoken with. Objects, by contrast, are usually

  spoken about. Persons are volitional, relational, cultural and social beings.

  They demonstrate intentionality and agency with varying degrees of

  autonomy and freedom. That some persons look like objects [or do not have

  visible appearance at all] is of little more value to an understanding of

  [religion] than the notion that some acts, characteristics, qualia, and so on

  may appear human-like to some observers. Neither material form nor

  spiritual or mental faculties are definitive.3

  What is important is that humans are inveterate agent-detectors, looking for

  will or intention or purpose or goal-oriented behavior in each other and in the

  world around them. And we tend to find it, whether or not it is there. Thus, the

  characteristic feature of religion is the claim that there are nonhuman and

  superhuman agents in the world, lacking some of the "qualia" of humans (like

  bodies or mortality) but possessing the most important one-mind or personality

  or intention. This "religious perspective," if you will, humanizes the world or,

  more critically, socializes the world, because these nonhuman religious agents

  (like a god) not only can be spoken with but also must be spoken with. They are

  understood by members of the religion to be a real and inescapable part of their

  social world. This leads us to a definition of religion offered by Robin Horton

  almost fifty years ago:

  [I] n every situation commonly labeled religious we are dealing with action

  directed toward objects which are believed to respond in terms of certain

  categories-in our own culture those of purpose, intelligence, and emotion-

  which are also the distinctive categories for the description of human

  action. The application of these categories leads us to say that such objects

  are "personified." The relationship between human beings and religious

  objects can be further defined as governed by certain ideas of patterning

  and obligation such as characterize relationships among human beings. In

  short, religion can be looked upon as an extension of the field of people's

  social relationships beyond the confines of purely human society. And for

  completeness' sake, we should perhaps add the rider that this extension

  must be one in which human beings involved see themselves in a dependent

  position vis-a-vis their nonhuman alters 4

  If religion is the expansion of society to include nonhuman and superhuman

  agents, then what is morality? Much ink has been spilled on this question too,

  most of it also biased, egocentric, and inadequate. Let us, as before, start with

  what morality is not. First and foremost, morality is not any partic ular rule or

  principle or set of rules or principles. That is, morality as such is not chastity or

  marital fidelity or honesty or nonkilling; these are all specific (although perhaps

  widely held) moral claims or issues but not "morality" in and of itself-any more

  than theism is "religion" in and of itself.

  Further, and more surprisingly, morality is not essentially about "goodness," if

  only because "goodness" is completely relative. In other words, while people of

  a certain moral temper might consider prohibiting same-sex marriage to be

  "good," no doubt most same-sex couples consider it "not good." Likewise, if

  some remote tribe believed it was "good" to sacrifice humans or to throw virgins

  in volcanoes to appease the volcano god, this behavior was "not good" for the

  victims. "Good" must always and necessarily be "good for someone" or "good

  for some purpose." It also goes without saying that morality is not what is

  "pleasurable" or "makes you happy," since occasionally the things that might

  give you pleasure-like sex or taking someone's property-are not deemed moral.

  Finally, and most surprisingly, morality is not essentially about "prosocial"

  behavior. This is a common misconception, but of course it depends on one's

  particular view of what society ought to be. Morality tends to be equated, first of

  all, with only the "positive" or "beneficial" values and behaviors, like altruism or

  generosity and love. But indisputably, any morality, including Judeo-Christian

  morality, accepts that there is a time to kill and a time to heal, a time to love and

  a time to hate, a time for war and a time for peace. When called upon (often by

  religion), killing and hating and warring are delightfully moral, even the highest

  and noblest thing we can do, a virtual commandment. More, "prosocial" is

  another relative term: killing witches may be "good for society" but is not good

  for witches, who are part of society. Banning gay marriage or preventing

  abortion may be good for one person's notion of society and not good for another

  person's. Worse yet, hardly anyone ever acts for the "good of society" but rather

  for some more local and personal good: most of us would act more altruistically

  toward ou
r family or friends than toward strangers or enemies. We would kill to

  defend ourselves and our property, and the law sometimes recognizes this as a

  praiseworthy action (note the "make my day" laws that allow killing an intruder

  in your home). Finally, many things that preoccupy the Christian moral

  sensibility have little or nothing to do with prosociality, like nakedness or

  premarital sex; other cultures have adopted the exact opposite stance on these

  issues and have been happy and successful. At the same time, other cultures

  have their own moral preoccupations, like covering a woman's face and figure in

  some Muslim countries, which do not constitute "moral" concerns in Christian

  countries in the first place.

  If morality is not any of these things fundamentally, then what is it? Michael

  Shermer's stab at the question in his The Science of Good and Evil makes a

  decent first approximation: morality, he says, refers to "right and wrong thoughts

  and behaviors in the context of the rules of a social group."5 What this terse

  statement reminds us is that (1) morality always refers back to a set of rules and

  (2) each social group may have its own set of such rules. Therefore, as in the

  case of religion, we should look for the essence of morality in some larger and

  deeper area than the details of any particular moral system.

  The answer can be sought in our new understanding of religion. Why are

  humans such obsessive agency detectors? Because we, as an inherently social

  species, are necessarily interested in the actions and intentions of other members

  of our group (which may include, we now realize, nonhuman agents as well).

  Therefore, we need to evaluate each other's behavior-to be able to determine the

  meaning of that behavior, the intention of that behavior, and the predictability of

  that behavior. Indeed, the very existence of society depends on, one might even

  say is, a shared set of standards for the interpretation, evaluation, and prediction

  of behavior.

  In a word, humans-hopelessly social creatures that we are-do and must engage

  in the appraisal of each other's actions. Morality is one form of such appraisal.

  Morality is a kind of talk about behavior, a discourse or language about which

  behaviors we commend and which behaviors we condemn. As Kai Nielsen has

  said it better than just about anyone:

  Moral language is the language we use in verbalizing a choice or a

  decision; it is the language we use in appraising human conduct and in

  giving advice about courses of action; and finally, it is the language we use

  in committing ourselves to a principle of action. Moral language is a

  practical kind of discourse that is concerned to answer the questions: "What

  should be done?" or "What attitude should be taken toward what has been

  done, is being done, or will be done?"6

  In short, as a social process of behavioral appraisal, "morality functions to guide

  conduct and alter behavior or attitudes." 7 Of course, it does not do so infallibly

  or in isolation.

  We say that morality does not guide and alter behavior infallibly because the

  existence of moral rules and of other people's moral outrage does not guarantee

  consistently and exclusively "good" behavior. Despite the presence of moral

  injunctions against killing and stealing, for instance, some folks persist in killing

  and stealing. Even worse, despite the fact that morality supposedly serves as a

  "conversation stopper," a bedrock basis for behavior and behavioral appraisal,

  the presence of moral injunctions has not ended and does not appear about to end

  the moral conversation. Instead, humans can and do argue about what the

  standards of appraisal are, what they mean, and when and how to apply them.

  Does "Thou shalt not kill" mean all killing, or merely "murder" (i.e., illicit

  killing)? Does it mean that you should avoid all killing, or only try to minimize

  killing (say, in war)? Does it mean killing anything at all, or only killing

  humans? (So much for carnivorism-or eating of any kind!)

  So humans constantly appraise each other's behavior and intentions (partly to

  determine future behavior), and they do so in relation to some group standard of

  behavior-some collective sense of what is "approved" or "disapproved" behavior.

  These standards unarguably differ across religions and cultures (although some

  big items do frequently appear). But morality is ultimately nothing more than a

  special case of the more general human predilection to appraise behavior and to

  erect systems and standards of appraisal. Even more, morality is not the only

  form that such appraisal systems/standards and such appraisal language can take.

  "Morality" is one entry in the universe of appraisal-talk, of which there are many

  other entries. What I mean is that "moral" and "immoral" are two labels that can

  be attached to behaviors depending on their conformity to group standards. But

  there are other labels, too, available to members to praise or denounce (and

  hopefully affect and control) behavior: legal/illegal, sane/ insane,

  mature/immature, normal/abnormal, polite/impolite, ethical/ unethical,

  professional/unprofessional, and so on. None of these other pairs of terms quite

  overlaps with moral/immoral.

  As Nielsen also explains, "Not all practical discourse is moral discourse. Not

  all conduct is moral conduct and not all advice or appraisal of conduct is moral

  advice or moral appraisal. Nor are all attitudes or dispositions to action moral

  attitudes or moral dispositions to action." s That is, not every behavioral issue is

  a "moral" issue, and not every standard of behavior is a "moral" standard. As we

  mentioned, most Westerners do not regard the display of a woman's face or arms

  to be a moral concern at all, and some tribes like the Warlpiri or the Yanomamo

  did not regard public nakedness to be a moral concern. The Jams consider eating

  vegetables or killing insects to be a moral problem, while the average Westerner

  does not. Nietzsche once asserted that there are no moral facts; in truth, there are

  no universal moral questions.

  Finally, just as religion can and should be decomposed into more fundamental

  building blocks that are not "religious" in themselves, morality can and should

  be decomposed into more fundamental building blocks that are not "moral" in

  themselves. Shermer calls these "premoral sentiments" and includes among

  them:

  [A]ttachinent and bonding, cooperation and mutual aid, sympathy and

  empathy, direct and indirect reciprocity, altruism and reciprocal altruism,

  conflict resolution and peacemaking, deception and deception detection,

  community concern and caring about what others think about you, and

  awareness of and response to the social rules of the group.9

  Haidt and Graham condense the rudiments of morality down to five

  "psychological preparations for detecting and reacting emotionally to issues

  related to harm/care, fairness/reciprocity, ingroup/loyalty, authority/ respect, and

  purity/sanctity"10 Most of these, it can be noticed, have little to do with religion

  and could easily stand without religion.

  MORALITY WITHOUT
CHRISTIANITY

  So Christianity has its own behavioral interest and its own appraisal language-or

  perhaps we should say interests and appraisals, since not all Christians seem to

  agree on the details of "Christian morality." It cannot even be claimed that

  Christianity is the only basis for a single morality, let alone for all morality. For

  example, some Christians think that dancing is bad, while others do not; some

  think that coffee or alcohol are bad, while others do not.

  Different religions have their particular behavioral rules and appraisal terms.

  Judaism was heralded as a religion of justice long before Christianity was

  invented; the word "justice" occurs dozens of times in the Torah/Old Testament,

  and the book of job is centered on it (see Alan Dershowitz's The Genesis of

  .7ustice for a discussion of the evolution of justice in the Torah's first book").

  Here, as in many of the cases to follow, "morality" might not quite be the right

  word to describe the specific concerns, but the concerns are recognizable as

  manifestations of an appraisal discourse. For instance, the Big Ten of moral rules

  were written centuries before the Gospels, with their admonitions against killing

  and stealing and lying and bearing false witness. But as anyone with minimal

  familiarity with the Judeo-Christian scriptures knows, not all of the "ten

  commandments" are "moral" in the conventional sense of the term. There is

  nothing "moral" (in the sense of "prosocial" or "altruistic") in having no other

  gods before some god, or in avoiding graven images ("or any likeness of any

  thing that is in heaven above, or that is in the earth beneath, or that is in the

  water under the earth," as Exodus 20:4 orders and which the average Western

  Christian utterly ignores), nor in keeping the Sabbath, nor in not coveting your

  neighbor's possessions (which is the engine of Western capitalism).

  What most Christians seem to conveniently forget is that the socalled "ten

  commandments" are neither the only rules nor the main rules in Judaism. Why,

  after the first tablets were broken, the Hebrew god gave Moses a new set with

  different commandments in Exodus 34, such as to keep the feast of unleavened

  bread, to offer the firstborn to their god (presumably by sacrifice, since they are

  also instructed not to offer the blood of sacrifice along with leaven), to observe

  the feast of weeks, and to assemble the men-children three times a year. Most

  modern Christians, if they have even heard of these rules, do not obey them and

  do regard them as "moral" worries.

  Judaism also has a concern for "sin," but a cursory examination shows that

  "sin" is not the same thing as the modern Christian concept of "immorality." Sin

  in ancient Judaism was more akin to uncleanness or impurity: the dietary laws

  do not say it is "immoral" to eat pork or shellfish but that those substances are an

  "abomination," and a woman is unclean after birth, not immoral. And Judaism's

  behavioral rules are hardly exhausted with the ten (or twenty) orders but are

  famously said to run to 613 ritzvot or commandments. Among these mandates

  are that every man should write a copy of the Torah for himself,12 wear the

  tefillin or phylactery on the head and arm,13 not reap his entire field,14 and

  exempt a bridegroom from public labor or military service for one year;15 that a

  widow whose husband had no children should not marry anyone other than her

  dead husband's brother;16 that one not kiss or hug or wink at or skip with a

  relative lest one commits incest;17 that one not borrow money at interest;18 and

  one of my personal favorites, that one release any servant that one "buys" after

  six years.19

  Islam is another wellknown religion with a clear set of "moral" principles.

 

‹ Prev