Book Read Free

Randal Marlin

Page 50

by Propaganda


  ADVERTISIng

  The Case Against government Controls

  The case against government controls on advertising was usefully articulated in an

  article, “Advertising and Ethics,” by Phillip Nelson, a professor of economics at the

  252 PROPAGANDA AND THE ETHICS OF PERSUASION

  BV-Propaganda-Interior-04.indd 252

  9/5/13 4:52 PM

  State University of New York.13 He argued against government sanctions for controlling advertising because he felt that government control would be wasteful, ineffect-

  ive, and unnecessary in the light of possible alternatives. The arguments are far from

  compelling, but they are worth critiquing inasmuch as they articulate ideas that have

  some plausibility.

  1. Government regulation has had a bad track record, in particular a record of counter-

  productivity. For example, by control ing rents at a fixed level, accommodation prices

  are kept lower and the stimulus to build new housing is lessened, thus making low-

  cost accommodation more difficult to obtain. This may be so, but that is only one

  area of government regulation. There are many others that show no obvious counter-

  productivity, for example, motor vehicle licensing. The abandonment of a government

  system of water supply testing emerged as a contributing factor in the outbreak in

  Walkerton, Ontario of a deadly e.coli infection. So the argument against government

  regulation of advertising, on the basis that government regulation in general is bad,

  is not very strong.

  2. Advertising generates social well-being. That is true of some advertising, perhaps

  even of most advertising. However, it doesn’t address the question of how to deal with

  advertising that misleads, insults, demeans, or is otherwise reprehensible.

  3. There is a distinction between advertising of experience qualities (qualities that the

  purchaser verifies on using the product) and advertising of search qualities (quali-

  ties that can be determined prior to purchase, such as cost, size, shape, etc.). Nelson

  points out that if there is any deception in the description of the search qualities,

  people will not buy the product. In the case of experience qualities, the customer

  might be fooled once but will not be in line for repeat purchases. Therefore, false

  advertising will not pay for any company that wants to stay in business for long.

  Since self-interest will dictate truthfulness in the advertising of experience qualities,

  legislation should not be needed. If people are rational and act in their own interest,

  there ought not to be any false or misleading advertising. This argument has some

  merit, but, like the legendary bumblebee that ought not to be able to fly in the light

  of aerodynamic principles, this kind of deceptive advertising of experience quali-

  ties nevertheless occurs and with some frequency, as can be seen from convictions

  obtained in Canada under the Competition Act.

  4. Some forms of deception are harmless, because they trick people into doing what

  they ought to do in their own interest anyway. Strangely, he views this kind of decep-

  tion as a case of providing information because it leads people to act in the way they

  would act if they were fully informed.

  CHAPTER 7: THE QUESTIon oF ConTRoLS 253

  BV-Propaganda-Interior-04.indd 253

  9/5/13 4:52 PM

  5. If advertising were deceptive, people would not believe it; thus, in the long run, deception would not be in the interest of advertisers. That is true, but the observation

  does not support the case against regulation. So long as the majority of advertisers are

  truthful, there will be a tendency to believe advertisements. However, if this tendency

  exists, it can be exploited by a few unscrupulous advertisers for their own benefit.

  6. Because it is not possible to prevent all fraud, Nelson suggests putting up with exist-

  ing abuses rather than trying to regulate them out of existence. There are costs to all

  forms of legal enforcement, and there are diminishing returns the closer one moves

  toward reducing crime to zero. That point is sound but limited in scope. From the

  valid point that one cannot prevent all fraud, we cannot infer that it would be inadvis-

  able to try to prevent some fraud.

  7. Perhaps Nelson’s least impressive argument is one in defence of advertising prod-

  ucts that are of no real intrinsic benefit to the customer on the grounds that “if I

  don’t make/sell it, someone else will.” The form of that argument is identical to the

  rationalization of any protection racket operator, contract killing organization, or

  suchlike. Even if it is true that someone else will do it anyway, that does not serve as a

  justification for my doing it.

  In contrast to Nelson’s largely hypothetical treatment of deception as something

  advertisers ought to eschew in their own interest, Burton Leiser looks at some actual

  practices involving deception.14 While not attempting to provide a complete list, he

  provides some interesting illustrative examples, among which are the following:

  1. Offering for sale at a “reduced” price what was never offered for sale at the suppos-

  edly “regular” price;

  2. Offering “free” sets of encyclopedias, but asking for a small monthly service charge

  for a 10-year research service;

  3. Advertising “free” books or records to join a club, when they are not free but are

  consideration in a binding contract to purchase a certain number of books or

  records;

  4. Small type to obscure limitations on, for example, insurance coverage; and

  5. Misleading language, as when a health insurance policy advertises that it “will pay

  your hospital bills,” but it does not include all hospital bills and maybe not all of

  the bills themselves.15

  Leiser makes a strong case for government intervention where products are adver-

  tised in ways that mask health or safety risks to consumers, though he would prefer

  advertisers to behave in ways that would make such intervention unnecessary.

  254 PROPAGANDA AND THE ETHICS OF PERSUASION

  BV-Propaganda-Interior-04.indd 254

  9/5/13 4:52 PM

  The Consumer Protection Movement, Misleading Advertising, and

  Canada’s Competition Act

  Public agitation for government regulation of industry in the interests of consumers

  is nothing new. The outcry in the wake of Upton Sinclair’s classic revelation of the

  horrors of Chicago’s meat-packing industry, The Jungle,16 led to government legislation imposing standards on the industry. In the late 1950s, Vance Packard raised the alarm

  about the impact of advertising on our behaviour with The Hidden Persuaders,17 and in the mid-1960s Ralph Nader spearheaded the consumerist movement with his revelations, in Unsafe at Any Speed,18 about safety flaws in automobile design.19 The alleged attempt by General Motors to hire a detective to find material to discredit Nader20

  led to the company paying a hefty out-of-court settlement to him after he launched

  a lawsuit against it based on privacy rights. Nader used the funds to organize many

  public interest groups including the Public Interest Research Groups to be found in

  many universities throughout the United States and Canada.

  The movement for consumer protection turned out to be very popular. Many

  countries around the world have passed such laws in response to
public pressure. In

  some cases, existing regulatory bodies were given added powers, as with the Federal

  Trade Commission (FTC) in the United States. As explained on the FTC’s website,

  it was created in 1914 for the purpose of preventing unfair methods of competition

  in commerce as part of the battle to “bust the trusts.”21 The move from breaking up

  monopolies and cartels to prohibiting misleading advertising has a logical basis.

  Corporations willing to engage in misleading advertising have an unfair advantage

  over those who for ethical reasons refrain from doing so. Fairness is therefore a major

  reason for justifying measures to maintain truth in advertising, but there is also a pub-

  lic concern for market efficiency. Where advertising is not truthful, consumers waste

  time pursuing and purchasing goods that in the end turn out not to be what they

  want, all because the goods were misrepresented. A third and compelling reason for

  insisting on truth in advertising and proper labelling of goods is that the health and

  safety of the public can be at risk if contents of drugs or foods are not properly iden-

  tified or if false claims for strength, performance, and durability are made for such

  things as tools or machinery.

  In Canada, misleading advertising is prohibited under the Competition Act,

  which has established a Competition Bureau that deals with misleading advertising

  along with fair trading generally, including price-fixing, bid-rigging, phony “sales,”

  “Made in Canada” claims, and much else. The same bureau enforces the administra-

  tion of the Consumer Packaging and Labelling Act, the Textile Labelling Act, and the

  Precious Metals Marking Act. When it issued enforcement guidelines for “Product

  of Canada” and “Made in Canada” claims, it covered representations relating to all

  three acts.22

  CHAPTER 7: THE QUESTIon oF ConTRoLS 255

  BV-Propaganda-Interior-04.indd 255

  9/5/13 4:52 PM

  Penalties for misrepresentation of goods or services can be quite severe, and the situation in modern commerce has long gone beyond the rule of caveat emptor (let the buyer beware). In today’s world, the seller must be wary of making performance or other claims

  for his or her goods without having adequate evidence to support these claims. The line

  between so-called “puffery,” where advertisements make superlative claims for goods or

  services in non-specific ways (“enjoy the best eating at Joe’s”), and cases of specific mis-

  representation (“our additive will cut your fuel consumption by 10 per cent”) may not

  always be easy to draw. That is one reason why administrative bodies with prosecutorial

  powers have been set up to regulate misleading advertising. The criminal law may be

  suitable for cases of outright fraud, as in the case of advertising and collecting payment

  for goods or services one has no intention of delivering. But misleadingly worded sugges-

  tions that a potential customer has already won a prize, to be awarded under a condition

  of making a purchase, may need to be dealt with by less drastic measures, for example, by

  some regulatory fine or forced discontinuance of the deception.

  The criminal law has rightly been described as a rough engine, not suitable for the

  fine-grained judgments that often have to be made in determining the degree either

  to which a given advertisement is misleading or of the harm that is likely to result. As

  a practical matter, the requirement of mens rea (a guilty state of mind in commission of an offence) may make successful prosecution unlikely because of the difficulty of

  proving intention. By contrast, regulatory offences not involving criminal law can be

  dispatched, and appropriate fines or other penalties applied, without having to prove

  the existence of criminal intention or recklessness. This does not mean that violations

  of the law, as interpreted by some administrative officials or tribunal, will automati-

  cally be successfully prosecuted. Usually there is a provision for a defence of “due dili-

  gence,” meaning that the person accused of misleading advertising may be acquitted if

  he or she made appropriate efforts to verify the truth of the claims.

  For reasons partly in line with those already mentioned, the acts enforced by the

  Competition Bureau go beyond requiring non-deceptive information in that they make

  it mandatory in certain cases to disclose aspects of the nature and contents of the goods

  offered for sale. It may not be obvious to a buyer whether, say, a sweater is acrylic or made of wool. Forcing disclosure of the content assists the potential buyer in making a choice.

  The main rationale here would seem to be market efficiency, but there is also a semblance

  of fraud when inferior materials are used in products made to look like more expensive

  versions, though no specific claims are made to that effect. Requiring proper labelling

  reduces the likelihood of such deception.

  All of these legal initiatives have a positive side, but there are also costs. There is

  the cost of the bureaucracy needed to administer the program, and there are other

  costs including that of penalties to those who run afoul of the regulations. Rather

  than just sit and wait to prosecute violations, the Competition Bureau tries to inform

  potential violators about the risks they run if they do not learn about and conform

  to the regulations. It will review proposed market strategies to resolve issues where

  256 PROPAGANDA AND THE ETHICS OF PERSUASION

  BV-Propaganda-Interior-04.indd 256

  9/5/13 4:52 PM

  doubts as to legality might arise. In recent years, it has issued pamphlets, guidelines, and other information bulletins to advise how it is likely to interpret and act on provisions of the Competition Act. The guidelines cover such things as deception about

  winning a prize, telemarketing, representations made over the Internet, price claims,

  promotional contests, etc.23

  The FTC has carried out investigative work in the United States beginning in

  1928 when private utility officials described under oath their methods for influenc-

  ing newspaper editors and publishers, schools, and universities.24 These propaganda

  activities, so described by Jack Levin, were well-documented, but the growth of the

  PR industry along with so many paid lobbyists suggests that government initiatives

  supporting a fair and free flow of information to the people and specifically to the

  US Congress on matters affecting corporate and public interests may need to be

  supplemented.

  Legal controls over advertising are not solely the prerogative of the FTC or, in

  Canada, the Competition Bureau. Many US states have their own statutes. For example,

  the California Department of Consumer Affairs lists 18 different categories of law-

  governed activities under “Advertising,” starting with “Bait and Switch,” and 14 under

  “Misrepresentation,” starting with “Affiliation or Association.” In Canada, there are stat-

  utes such as the Food and Drug Act and the Tobacco Act that also place restrictions on

  advertising. And provinces have also enacted consumer protection laws. On both sides

  of the border, a body set up to regulate broadcasting also plays a role. This is the Federal

  Communications Commission (FCC) in the United States and the Canadian Radio

  Television and Telecommunications Commission (CRTC) in Ca
nada. These bodies are

  tasked among other things with the job of ensuring diversity in news and entertainment

  available to the public through broadcasting satellite and cable.

  Specific kinds of prohibited marketing deceptions are spelled out in the Canadian

  Competition Act, recently amended in 2009. There are also general provisions. A

  recent example shows that penalties can be quite steep. The Competition Bureau

  announced on June 28, 2011 that Bell Canada had agreed to pay a penalty of $10 mil-

  lion for making misleading advertising claims.25

  The following are excerpts and paraphrases from some of the updated provisions

  of the Competition Act26 and are not meant to be a complete exposition of the law.

  s.52(1) No person shal , for the purpose of promoting, directly or indirectly, the supply or use of a product or for the purpose of promoting, directly or indirectly, any

  business interest, by any means whatever, knowingly or recklessly make a representa-

  tion to the public that is false or misleading in a material respect.

  The general language of “any business interest” allows for prosecution of misrepresen-

  tations concerning services or other benefits.

  CHAPTER 7: THE QUESTIon oF ConTRoLS 257

  BV-Propaganda-Interior-04.indd 257

  9/5/13 4:52 PM

  s.52(1.1): For greater certainty, in establishing that subsection (1) was contravened, it is not necessary to prove that

  (a) any person was deceived or misled;

  (b) any member of the public to whom the representation was made was within

  Canada; or

  (c) the representation was made in a place to which the public had access.

  This provision allows for prosecution of misleading advertising without waiting for

  someone to be victimized. The last clause indicates that such things as misleading tele-

  phone or e-mail solicitations may be included among the prohibitions. Another subsec-

  tion declares that the law applies not only to those who make representations but also to

  those who permit representations to be made.

  The act appears to take into account the possibility of misleading people by imag-

  ery or suggestion rather than by literal statement in the following provision:

  s.52(4) In a prosecution for a contravention of this section, the general impression conveyed by a representation as well as its literal meaning shall be taken into account

 

‹ Prev