Book Read Free

Why Nationalism

Page 6

by Yael Tamir


  alone. This is where nationalism comes into play, endowing the

  random process of border drawing with a purpose, providing

  reasons for its ongoing existence.

  Historically, borders were determined in different ways. In a

  few cases national borders are natural ones; in most instances

  they are a result of wars and conquests, purchases, marriages, and

  treaties. All of these processes are less acceptable as a basis of

  legitimacy in modern times. It is difficult to imagine that in the

  twenty- first century one could sell or hand over a country as

  alimony. Excluding such procedures, democratic states must seek

  legitimacy in national self- determination and self- rule. We are

  then back to square one, searching for a proper definition of a

  political self or a nation.

  The state and the nation chose each other as partners because:

  “In the long freedom wars liberalism has won a thousand impor-

  tant battles, securing first the individual and his rights, and then

  the right of others long excluded from liberty’s fruits. But the

  costs of victory are now being paid: the price of liberal reliance

  on contract and consent has been the impoverishment of its poli-

  tics.”4 Negative procedural politics can provide guidelines for

  fair political action, yet these politics can neither sketch the

  boundaries of a political entity nor endow a political system with

  meaning. Nationalism fulfills these tasks in a modern, secular

  manner. As we shall see, it is a flexible and permissive provider

  adjusting itself to the needs of the people as well as to those of

  the state. Nationalism endows the state with intimate feelings

  linking the past, the present, and the future. The fact that indi-

  viduals feel they are part of a continuous entity induces in them

  mutual dependencies and responsibilities and invigorates the

  will to jointly pursue common ends. Consequently, individuals

  are likely to develop an entire network of reciprocal attachments,

  40 • Chapter

  5

  expectations, and obligations. When such a sense of belonging

  is associated with the state, political institutions turn from bu-

  reaucratic entities into an extended family, although the kinship

  ties in question are highly metaphorical, and though the state

  is a contingent historical product, it “feels like part of the order

  of nature; it links individual and community, past and present;

  it gives to cold, impersonal structures an aura of warm, intimate

  togetherness.”5

  With the help of nationalism, states turn into homelands—

  places one is affiliated with due to love and fate rather than due

  to instrumental considerations. The traditional marriage vows

  exchanged before building a private home, promising eternity

  rather than probability, reflect the kind of dedication states would

  like their citizens to develop: “From this day forward, for better,

  for worse, for richer, for poorer, in sickness and in health, till

  death do us part.” No patriot could have phrased it more

  accurately.

  Part II

  Love and Marriage:

  The Virtues of Nationalism

  One does not fall in love with a woman or enter the womb of a

  church, as a result of logical persuasion. Reason may defend an act

  of faith— but only after the act has been committed, and the man

  committed to the act. . . . A faith is not acquired; it grows like a

  tree. Its crown points to the sky; its roots grow downwards into

  the past and are nourished by the dark sap of the ancestral humus.

  Arthur Koestler, The God That Failed

  6

  Living beyond Our

  Psychological Means

  Nationalism entered the modern world through a democratic

  door and an economic corridor, bringing with it a generous

  alimony: a bottom- up justification for the formation of the

  modern nation- state. The voyage from Nutopia to the real world

  suggests that borderless states are dystopian; in order to be

  democratic and promote justice, states must depend on a clear

  definition of territory and membership. The need for borders and

  demarcation is grounded not only in statism, it also touches a

  very personal chord. In an ever- changing world it helps individu-

  als define their identity, providing them with interpretive tools

  to decipher reality and make sense of their daily actions.

  Categorization is deeply grounded in human psychology— it

  is a necessary tool of self- definition. The term human is a far too

  thin mode of delineation. Individuals need to rely on “thick

  identities” to make their lives meaningful. It is therefore appro-

  priate to repeat today, more than two hundred years after they

  were written, the iconic words of the French intellectual

  Joseph de Maistre: “I have seen, in my times, Frenchmen, Italian,

  and Russians. I even know due to Montesquieu, that one may

  be a Persian; but as for Man I have never met in my life; if he

  exists, it is without my knowledge.”1

  44 • Chapter

  6

  This is not to say that there are no common human features;

  we have more in common with members of our species (as wel

  as with other species) than we care to admit. Our individuality,

  which makes us unique, is formed through a series of exchanges.

  The features of modern individualism cannot be developed in

  solitude. Asked to choose an animal he identifies with, Isaiah

  Berlin said: “A penguin, because penguins live in colonies, they

  cannot survive on their own.” This was his way of saying some-

  thing profound about himself and about humanity. Humans may

  be able to survive on their own, yet even the loneliest of literary

  figures, Robinson Crusoe, had to find Friday to converse with

  and share the knowledge he had acquired back home— without

  the ability to converse he would have lost a significant part of

  his humanity.

  It may be assumed that personal autonomy is dependent on

  our ability to free ourselves from the shackles of belonging, yet

  freedom is hollow outside of a meaning- providing system.2 For

  our choices to be valuable they must have a cultural and norma-

  tive context. Many of our most personal decisions— the life

  plan we make, the career we embark on, the family we raise (or

  choose not to raise)— reflect social, cultural, and religious norms.

  Modern individuals who wish to shape their life autonomously

  must first internalize a set of norms and behaviors that would

  guide their action. The challenge then is to develop social inter-

  actions that enrich and liberate the self rather than impoverish

  and restrain it.3

  Like morality, identity is a sphere in which no one can be

  passive. In every choice one makes one must decide whether to

  be “a contributing partner” or a “free rider”; the former acts

  within a cultural framework and contributes to its ability to

  grow and flourish, and the latter flirts with different options

  Our Psychological Means • 45

  other individuals shape, e
njoying their efforts to keep such op-

  tions viable. Identity thus carries not only the mark of our an-

  cestors and contemporaries but also of our own (free) choices.

  Freedom and determinism keep interacting in our lives, making

  us who we are.

  We define our identity against the background of those things

  that matter to us. Cultural membership is “the context within

  which we choose our ends, and come to see their value, and this

  is a precondition . . . of the sense that one’s ends are worth pur-

  suing.”4 Our social and cultural context provides the contours

  within which choice becomes essential rather than arbitrary, thus

  transforming freedom into autonomy. Hence, “to bracket out

  history, nature, society, demands of solidarity, everything but

  what I find in myself, would be to eliminate all candidates

  for what matters.”5

  The need to belong to a cultural community, then, is not

  merely an expression of a psychological craving to live in a known

  environment and be part of a community to which we can de-

  velop feelings of attachment. It is an epistemological need for

  systems of interpretation that will allow us to understand the

  world and choose a way of life as well as a creative need for means

  of interpretation, exchange, and expression.

  Like many other goods the importance of feeling at ease with

  one’s identity is highlighted by its absence. Living in a commu-

  nity that supports our identity, we may not be aware of the im-

  portance of what it offers, but when we find ourselves in an alien

  environment, forced to deny or disguise our identity, we experi-

  ence pain and anxiety. In a beautiful, poetic paragraph Berlin

  described the state of mind of those individuals who reject their

  identity and are forced to set out in search of a new one. They

  are, he writes:

  46 • Chapter

  6

  betwixt and between, unmoored from one bank without reaching

  the other, tantalized but incapable of yielding, complicated,

  somewhat tormented figures . . . liable to waves of self- pity, aggres-

  sive arrogance, exaggerated pride in those very attributes which

  divided them from their fellows; with alternating bouts of self-

  contempt and self- hatred, feeling themselves to be objects of scorn

  or antipathy to those very members of the society by whom they

  most wish to be recognized and respected . . . it is a well- known

  neurosis in an age of nationalism in which self- identification with

  a dominant group becomes supremely important, but, for some

  individuals, abnormally difficult.6

  This is why individuals desire to secure for themselves not

  only a set of Mil ian liberties but also recognition as members

  of particular groups and affirmation of the uniqueness and wor-

  thiness of such groups. Most of all they demand:

  recognition (of their class or nation, or color or race) as an inde-

  pendent source of human activity, as an entity with a will of its

  own, intending to act in accordance with it (whether it is good or

  legitimate or not), and not to be ruled, educated, guided, with

  however light a hand, as being not quite fully human and therefore

  not quite fully free.7

  At the heart of modern politics, Berlin concluded, lies “a great

  cry for recognition on the part of both individuals and groups

  and in our own day, of professions and classes, nations and

  races.”8 Not only do individuals see their personal freedom as

  dependent on their group’s ability to be self- governing, they also

  see their own self- esteem as closely linked to that of their group.

  Consequently, they regard offenses and humiliations of their

  group as a personal injury and take pride and satisfaction in the

  group’s success and prosperity.

  Our Psychological Means • 47

  A significant aspect of maintaining a positive self- esteem is

  making comparisons that favor the in- group over the out- group.

  Identity biases perceptions; members of the in- group are seen

  as bearers of positive values and qualities while members of

  the out- group are seen as carriers of negative ones. Group

  membership also biases memory so that “the good actions of

  the in- group are better- remembered than the bad, and for the

  out- group, the bad are better- remembered than the good.”9 As

  positive self- esteem is dependent on an appraisal of both the

  in- group and the out- group, it is impossible to separate the

  costs and benefits of membership. A large number of studies led

  Dominic Abrams and Michael Hogg to formulate “the self-

  esteem hypothesis” according to which “inter- group discrimina-

  tion is believed to be at least partly motivated by the individual’s

  desire to achieve and maintain positive self- esteem.”10

  Many have hoped that the need to belong to a nation, or any

  other particular group, is an expression of a transient develop-

  mental stage humanity will grow out of. That group membership

  will be replaced with a global one, thus abolishing particularism,

  ethnocentrism, group favoritism, and stereotyping, preparing the

  ground for global coexistence.

  In the wake of World War I, traumatized by the experiences

  of the war and the loss of young lives, leading intellectuals enter-

  tained the idea of cosmopolitanism. Influenced by Kant’s

  “Perpetual Peace” and the moral teaching of the Enlightenment,

  they were seeking a rational formula that would allow them to

  establish a human brotherhood that would end all wars. Albert

  Einstein was among these intellectuals; in his reflections on the

  causes of war he approached Sigmund Freud and asked him to

  explain why war persists. Freud’s answer expresses skepticism

  about the healing power of rationality. The ideal condition of

  things, he wrote,

  48 • Chapter

  6

  would be a community of men who had subordinated their instinc-

  tual life to the dictatorship of reason. Nothing else could unite

  men so completely and so tenaciously, even if there were no emo-

  tional ties between them. But in all probability this is a Utopian

  expectation.11

  Compelling individuals to act continually in accordance

  with axioms that contradict their instinctual inclinations, he

  concludes, is asking them “to live, psychologically speaking,

  beyond their means.”12 The great American statesman James

  Madison was therefore right when stating that “the latent causes

  of fraction are sown in the nature of Man.”13

  Some, like Kenneth Minogue, argue that nationalism is to be

  understood “as distortions of reality which allow men to cope

  with situations which they might otherwise find unbearable.”14

  Minogue is right; we embrace ideologies because they make our

  life bearable and because other options have far more damaging

  consequences. As the argument will evolve, it will become clear

  why, despite being fabricated, nationalism helps individuals to

  cope with the modern world, living active and meaningful lives.

>   If the behavioral and attitudinal trends cosmopolitans would

  like to eliminate are deeply inherited in human nature and not

  the outcome of nationalism, and if they evolve in response to a

  set of basic needs as old as humanity itself, then it is quite safe

  to predict that if nationalism were to sink into oblivion, other

  groups would be formed, allowing people to enjoy a sense of

  belonging and placing particular affiliations in conflict with uni-

  versal ones. Humanity has always been divided into communities

  marked by one set of features or another: families, vil ages, tribes,

  localities, nations, states as well as religions, races, ethnicities,

  genders, classes, and ideologies. Which of these communities has

  a more negative effect on human behavior?

  Our Psychological Means • 49

  History tells us that people are ready to kill and die in the

  name of all of these groups. In recent centuries nationalism has

  played a major role in evoking hateful and bel igerent attitudes,

  yet such actions could be evoked by each and every one of the

  abovementioned groups; from Helen of Troy to Romeo and

  Juliet we have ample proof that even love, the most noble feeling

  of all, can turn deadly. If subordinating human judgments to pure

  reason is beyond human means, learning to weigh the dictate

  of reason against the emotional and moral bias grounded in

  membership must be our educational and political target.

  Social psychology teaches us that membership in a group nec-

  essarily leads individuals to express in- group favoritism, but

  actual dislike or hostility toward the out- group is closely related

  to the feeling of being subject to “an imposed, unjust distribu-

  tion of resources.”15 Felt injustice or perceived unfair treatment

  is a central organizing concept in discussions of intergroup

  conflict:

  Existing theory and research in social psychology suggests that

  judgments of injustice provide the cognitive structure and dynamic

  motivational force that justifies conflictual inter- group behavior. . . .

  Perception of injustice of the actions of the out- group lead to

  protest, retaliation, aggression, and an increase in prejudice. In

  general, violation of expectations of how rewards should be handed

  out or how decisions are made (or conflict handled) are the main

 

‹ Prev