Book Read Free

Henry Sidgwick- Eye of the Universe

Page 7

by Bart Schultz

modernism, and the fate of the university.

  Still, for Sidgwick the ultimate meaning of education ran deeper than

  any canon or curriculum, and reflected his conversational virtues. In line

  with recent sentiment, he would have agreed that although it is important

  which books one has read, more important still is how one has read

  the books. Sidgwickian inquiry, like Socratic inquiry, demanded critical

  thinking, not displays of barren erudition or fawning invocations of great

  thinkers and great books. As Balfour, who had been his student before

  becoming his brother-in-law, observed: “Of all the men I have known he

  was the readiest to consider every controversy and every controversialist

  on their merits. He never claimed authority; he never sought to impose

  his views; he never argued for victory; he never evaded an issue.” In an

  afterthought richly suggestive of the tensions in Sidgwick’s life, Balfour

  adds: “Whether these are the qualities which best fit their possessor to

  found a ‘school’ may well be doubted.” (M )

  Sidgwick regarded this as the meaning of education, even of culture,

  which he rarely missed an opportunity to advance. In a later essay on “The

  Pursuit of Culture,” filled with the reflections of a lifetime, he explained

  that

  since the most essential function of the mind is to think and know, a man of culti-

  vated mind must be essentially concerned for knowledge: but it is not knowledge

  merely that gives culture. A man may be learned and yet lack culture: for he may

  be a pedant, and the characteristic of a pedant is that he has knowledge without

  culture. So again, a load of facts retained in the memory, a mass of reasonings got

  up merely for examination, these are not, they do not give culture. It is the love of knowledge, the ardour of scientific curiosity, driving us continually to absorb new

  facts and ideas, to make them our own and fit them into the living and growing

  system of our thought; and the trained faculty of doing this, the alert and supple

  intelligence exercised and continually developed in doing this, – it is in these that culture essentially lies. (PE )

  Perhaps, in the end, it was the promotion of culture in this sense that de-

  fined Sidgwick’s reformism and his efforts to “elevate and purify” social

  life. Like both Mill and Dewey, he had before his mind a vision of an

  educating society, not simply an educated society. But his endeavors

  followed a certain pattern. Although, in one capacity or another, he often

  found himself participating in the more conventional forms of public and

  private address, the one project to which he was unstintingly devoted,

  P: GCV

  c.xml

  CY/Schultz

  

  January , 

  :

  

  Henry Sidgwick: Eye of the Universe

  for which he never seemed to want energy, was the discussion group.

  Not only did he always remain faithful to his first and formative such

  group, the famous Cambridge Apostles, but he became a mainstay of

  any number of other discussion societies as well: the “Grote Club,” the

  Eranus, the Metaphysical Society, the Political Economy Club, the Ad

  Eundem Society, and Synthetic Society all received years of commitment

  from him, and these are only the better known of the groups to which he

  lent his skills. Such interaction provided him with his model for critical

  inquiry – be it philosophical, theological, or scientific – and thus for both

  his academic work and his work for academic reform – for example, his

  work for philosophy as an academic discipline, for universities open to

  women and extending their resources to all classes, and for a curriculum

  less preoccupied with rote learning of the classics and more attuned to

  modern methods and topics. Pluralistic and interdisciplinary, drawing

  from academic and nonacademic worlds, these were vehicles for cultivating

  humanity that went beyond narrow institutional reformism. And the traces

  of his participation in these groups are visible in The Methods of Ethics,

  even if it was in person that Sidgwick struck others as the true lumen

  siccum, or “pure white light.”

  The lure of discussion was always the same: free and open inquiry into

  issues of deep concern, usually involving religious or moral questions, and

  this as a search for unity in a conflictual world and an antidote to the dogma

  and dogmatism of school and church. If the Enlightenment project were

  to be realized, it would have to be realized in this context, with the sincere

  pursuit of truth and no authority but the better argument. What Sidgwick

  brought to these discussions, however, was genuinely exceptional, and

  reflective of the character that he brought to his friendships. As his student

  and colleague F. W. Maitland put it, in a review of Henry Sidgwick, A

  Memoir:

  Sidgwick was a wonderful talker; a better I have never heard. . . . Sidgwick’s talk never became, and never tended to become, a monologue. He seemed at least

  as desirous to hear as to be heard, and gave you the impression that he would

  rather be led than lead. Even more than the wit and the wisdom, the grace and

  the humour, it was the wide range of sympathy that excited admiration when the

  talk was over. To see with your eyes, to find interest in your interests, seemed to

  be one of his main objects, while he was amusing and instructing and delighting

  you. As a compliment that was pleasant; but I cannot think that it was a display

  of mere urbanity. Sidgwick genuinely wished to know what all sorts of people

  P: GCV

  c.xml

  CY/Schultz

  

  January , 

  :

  First Words

  

  thought and felt about all sorts of things. His irony never hurt, it was so kindly;

  and, of all known forms of wickedness, ‘Sidgwickedness’ was the least wicked.

  Good as are the letters in this book, I cannot honestly say that they are as good,

  or nearly as good, as their writer’s talk. A letter, being a monologue, cannot

  represent just what seemed most to distinguish him from some other brilliant

  talkers.

  Maitland allowed that Sidgwick was a “most unegotistical talker, and a

  most unegotistical man,” whose singular virtue was “truthfulness.”

  Relatives, friends, colleagues, former pupils, acquaintances were all in

  agreement about the singular attractiveness of Sidgwick as a conversational

  partner: he impressed everyone from Gladstone to Madame Blavatsky.

  Again, this did not necessarily refer to his lecture style, which, though

  it had the merits of careful, many-sided argument, could be something

  of a strain for those not truly engaged with the relevant subject. Many

  students found his lecturing admirable – W. R. Sorley called his teaching

  “a training in the philosophical temper – in candor, self-criticism, and

  regard for truth” – but even some of the good ones, such as Bertrand

  Russell and G. E. Moore, found
him dull. Russell observed that Sidgwick

  always told precisely one joke per lecture, and that after the suspense

  of awaiting its appearance had passed, attention flagged. But Russell

  would also in due course confess that he and Moore had not given

  Sidgwick anything like the respect that he deserved, even as both of

  them more or less unconsciously absorbed a great deal of Sidgwick’s

  outlook.

  According to James Bryce, who knew Sidgwick well and joined him in

  many discussion societies:

  Sidgwick did not write swiftly or easily, because he weighed carefully everything

  he wrote. But his mind was alert and nimble in the highest degree. Thus he

  was an admirable talker, seeing in a moment the point of an argument, seizing

  on distinctions which others had failed to perceive, suggesting new aspects from

  which a question might be regarded, and enlivening every topic by a keen yet

  sweet and kindly wit. Wit, seldom allowed to have play in his books, was one of the

  characteristics which made his company charming. Its effect was heightened by

  a hestation in his speech which often forced him to pause before the critical word

  or phrase of the sentence had been reached. When that word or phrase came, it

  was sure to be the right one. Though fond of arguing, he was so candid and fair,

  admitting all that there was in his opponent’s case, and obviously trying to see

  the point from his opponent’s side, that nobody felt annoyed at having come off

  P: GCV

  c.xml

  CY/Schultz

  

  January , 

  :

  

  Henry Sidgwick: Eye of the Universe

  second best, while everybody who cared for good talk went away feeling not only

  that he knew more about the matter than he did before, but that he had enjoyed

  an intellectual pleasure of a rare and high kind. The keenness of his penetration

  was not formidable, because it was joined to an indulgent judgment: the ceaseless

  activity of his intellect was softened rather than reduced by the gaiety of his

  manner. His talk was conversation, not discourse, for though he naturally became

  the centre of nearly every company in which he found himself, he took no more

  than his share. It was like the sparkling of a brook whose ripples seem to give out

  sunshine.

  “A first-rate talker,” “a brilliant talker,” “the best talker I ever heard” –

  such phrases are littered throughout the reminiscences of Sidgwick. In his

  younger days, as an undergraduate and junior Fellow, he was apparently

  more aloof, striking some as cold or priggish, with a chilly Socratic wit.

  When F. W. H. Myers praised a mediocre religious writer, exclaiming “Of

  such is the Kingdom of Heaven!,” Sidgwick sneered, “H-h-h-ave you been

  there?” And even some of his later friends, such as his prize student and

  literary executor E. E. Constance Jones, could paint Sidgwickedness in

  this cooler light, complaining that the Memoir failed to catch the “Socratic irony, that Horatian satire, that malice (in the French, not the English,

  sense of the word) which gave a peculiar zest and charm to Sidgwick’s

  conversation.” When Balfour exclaimed that he would follow the Church

  of England through thick and thin, Sidgwick dryly replied that he would

  follow it through thin.

  On Myers’s account, the reserve and preoccupation of Sidgwick’s

  youth, when he was professedly “cased in a bark of selfish habit,” gave

  way because “by sheer meditation, by high resolve, he made himself such

  as we all know him.” Whether this was quite the case may be doubted –

  it rather smacks of the Victorian worship of self-command and character

  building. But Myers would come to know Sidgwick very well, as a long-

  standing member of the “Sidgwick Group” of psychical researchers. What

  is surely correct is that Sidgwick regarded himself as a kind of psycholog-

  ical experiment – or “experiment in living,” to use the Millian expression.

  He did think of his life in terms of a test of the human potential, of the

  possibility of a more sympathetic and conversational culture, one less de-

  pendent on orthodox religion. The “New Woman” whom he did so much

  to encourage was to be accompanied by a “New Man,” and both would

  enter a “New Age.” Such was the distillation of Sidgwick’s quest to solve

  the “deepest problems” of human life.

  P: GCV

  c.xml

  CY/Schultz

  

  January , 

  :

  First Words

  

  Tracing the vicissitudes of this experiment, of how Sidgwick became

  what he was, is no small task. The multitude of respects in which he re-

  mained a creature of his time will become plain enough. Certainly, he

  was not immune to talk of character and self-control, or civilization and

  progress, or race and rule. And he felt, to varying degrees, the three great

  anxieties of modern liberalism. As sketched by Alan Ryan, these are: “fear

  of the culturally estranged condition of what has been variously called the

  ‘underclass,’ the ‘unwashed mob,’ the lumpenproletariat, or (by Hegel) the

  Pöbel . . . unease about ‘disenchantment,’ the loss of a belief that the world possesses a religious and spiritual meaning . . . [and] fear that the degeneration of the French Revolution between  and  into a regime of

  pure terrorism was only the harbinger of revolutions to come.” These

  anxieties have often congealed into something resembling the Platonic

  dread of genuine democracy (as apt to degenerate into mob rule, dema-

  goguery, etc.) or have resulted in a kind of “self-inflicted wound,” since

  liberals “want the emancipation that leads to disenchantment, but want

  the process that emancipates us to relocate us in the world as well.” This

  last, as we shall see, was what produced the most troubled Sidgwickian

  dreams.

  But if Sidgwick felt these anxieties, so did Mill, James, Dewey, and a host

  of others whose works remain highly relevant and contested today, and it is

  vital to achieve some comparable understanding of just how he negotiated

  these matters, so crucial to the development of the public sphere.

  Clearly, Sidgwick’s experiment was filled with unresolved tensions. It

  was Sidgwick the philosopher who chastened a nephew for dismissing a

  scientific heretic for having no claim to be heard: “He asks for attention,

  not to his authority, but to his arguments.” An admirable position, but it

  was also Sidgwick the philosopher who held that “those who could hope

  to advance the study of philosophy, or even could profit by the study, were

  few” (M ). How did he construe the role of the philosopher in the

  educating society? What were his hopes for the democratic potential of

  the more open, more sympathetic, more utilitarian society of the future?

  How might the conversational norms of the private discussion group be

  translated into a larger cultural sp
here? Between Mill’s belief in a cul-

  tural elite or vanguard, the Coleridgean clerisy, and Dewey’s Whitmanian

  faith in radical democracy and social intelligence, where does one find

  Sidgwick? Did quantity of participation stand in inverse relation to qual-

  ity of participation? Was he the apostle of the democratic Socrates, or the

  P: GCV

  c.xml

  CY/Schultz

  

  January , 

  :

  

  Henry Sidgwick: Eye of the Universe

  elitist Plato? Whose voices mattered, and why? And what did all this talk

  have to do with utilitarianism?

  II. Sidgwick the Apostle

  I still think the best motto for a true Metaphysic are those two lines of

  Shelley: –

  I am the eye with which the Universe

  Beholds itself and knows itself divine.

  Sidgwick to Roden Noel (M )

  It is not too much to say that Cambridge University destroyed the

  young Henry Sidgwick, and as a result the mature Henry Sidgwick fell in

  love with the place. For when Sidgwick arrived at Trinity College in the

  autumn of , he was as fortified in Anglican orthodoxy as any young,

  rising member of the bourgeoisie could be, thanks in large measure to his

  first mentor, Edward White Benson, the future archbishop of Canterbury.

  But by the time of his graduation in , wreathed in every possible

  honor, he was in a state of religious, moral, and philosophical turmoil

  that took ten years to work out – his years, as he explained to Benson, of

  “Storm and Stress.” The ongoing crisis culminated in the resignation of

  his Fellowship because he could no longer in good conscience subscribe

  to the Thirty-nine Articles of the Church of England.

  In external respects, his life had been an unbroken success story. As at

  Rugby, he distinguished himself in both classics and mathematics, and he

  was reading voraciously in literature, poetry, philosophy, political econ-

  omy, and many other areas. He had won the Bell scholarship in his

  second term, and the Craven in , when he was also made a scholar of

  Trinity College. In , he added Sir William Browne’s prize for Latin

  and Greek epigrams. Although he took both the classical and the mathe-

 

‹ Prev