Book Read Free

Henry Sidgwick- Eye of the Universe

Page 10

by Bart Schultz


  January , 

  :

  

  Henry Sidgwick: Eye of the Universe

  them what could be learnt, and then, if argument was desirable, argue at

  close quarters.”

  As will become increasingly evident, Sidgwick’s construction of the

  fleshly body in relation to sympathetic understanding played an exceed-

  ingly important role in his religious, ethical, and parapsychological strug-

  gles. Some would also try to situate this obsession with figurative and

  literal forms of telepathic empathizing, mingling of minds, and so on, in

  the context of the fascination with mesmerism that first became marked

  during the earlier Victorian period, and that itself represented a response

  to anxiety over social conflict and the growth of democracy, with new forms

  of political leadership seeking to understand and achieve crowd control

  and consensus in novel ways. This line of interpretation, not heretofore

  developed in connection with Sidgwick, will be more fully addressed in

  Chapter , but it is suggestive of just how emblematic of social currents

  the seemingly more eccentric side of Sidgwickian sympathy may actually

  have been, of just how much his parapsychological interests reflected what

  was “in the air.”

  Moreover, Sidgwick’s friendship with John Addington Symonds, the

  source of some of the most intense intellectual and emotional exchanges

  of his life, was very much shaped by Symonds’s chronic invalidism and

  the way this affected his philosophical outlook. Symonds shared many

  of Sidgwick’s interests, especially in forms of depth psychology, and his

  own explorations of Platonic eros provided further forms of struggle with

  bodily existence and how it related to the intimacy of minds. Sidgwick

  was positively robust compared to Symonds, and in the only times he ever

  experienced anything close to Symonds’s tubercular physical weakness

  were during this undergraduate bout and in the last months of his life.

  It appears that he did make the most of such experiences. Evident

  in the foregoing remarks is the struggle with egoism and the body, via

  sympathetic talk, that would color the rest of his life, especially during

  his times of intellectual crisis. His diary and commonplace book, from his

  early years at Cambridge, are filled with records of his battle with self and

  flesh. Consider this earnest prayer, recorded in his diary:

  Before the Sacrament. I confess my errors to

  Jesus Christ in whom I humbly hope & pray

  that I believe with a saving faith –

  . My selfishness – This I feel is my great evil

  P: GCV

  c.xml

  CY/Schultz

  

  January , 

  :

  First Words

  

  combined with my self-consciousness & my

  occasional reactionary asceticism it leads to

  acts of great folly as well as wrong-doing.

  O God deliver me from this make it

  my sole aim primarily to do thy will,

  secondarily to further my own health

  & self-improvement intellectually morally

  & physically; but always relatively if

  not subordinately to the welfare of

  others – give me a complete devotion

  to Jesus Christ & a desire to imitate

  him in his utter abandonment of self

  in the cause of those whose nature He

  took – grant me to realize so as to

  feel these great realities; that I may

  not merely prate about but acknowledge

  from my heart the superiority of heavenly things

  to earthly.

  . Pride of Intellect – O God grant me neither

  to exalt too high nor to despise this

  gloriously capable part of my nature.

  The “reactionary asceticism” leading to “acts of great folly as well as

  wrong-doing” was apparently quite real, and this may be a reference back

  to his earlier abstemiousness, his habit of drinking only water, which his

  physicians claimed contributed to his digestive problem. But his somewhat

  compulsive battling with his own constitution took other forms as well,

  such as his efforts to overcome his insomnia and stammering. Indeed, it

  is intriguing that his celebrated conversation involved just such a struggle

  on the very surface, as it were, in that he was often complimented for

  deploying his stammer to enhance the effect of his wit, turning a kind of

  physical resistance into a triumph of intellect. As he wrote to Dakyns, in

  August of , “Strive not to let your spirit be clouded by your flesh: in

  every disease this is the worst danger. I mean what is called hypochondria,

  the state when one’s thoughts are enslaved to one’s clay.” It is not at all

  far-fetched to read these things as symptomatic portents or manifestations

  of the battles against materialism characteristic of his parapsychology and

  his own self-experimentation. But then, one had to watch out for the

  intellect as well.

  P: GCV

  c.xml

  CY/Schultz

  

  January , 

  :

  

  Henry Sidgwick: Eye of the Universe

  It should be remarked that Sidgwick apparently had quite extraordi-

  nary powers of mental concentration, no doubt related to that absorption

  in thought that often kept him from recognizing friends and acquaintances

  when he passed them in the street. Oscar Browning recorded his obser-

  vations of Sidgwick during the University Scholarship exam, noting how

  while everyone else was scribbling away at their Latin verses, Sidgwick

  simply sat there motionlessly meditating for nearly the entire period. With

  only minutes to go, he came out of his spell and wrote out his entire exam

  perfectly.

  Absorption in self and pride of intellect – such were the sins of the

  young Sidgwick. And sins they were, to his mind, even after the influence

  of Benson started to fade. The commonplace book records:

  But I desire only studies that however abstract in . . . reasonings have for their end human happiness. Thus Political Economy to make men happier and better en

  masse: Theology, to know, not what conduces to my eternal weal, but to our &c.

  The strongest conviction I have is a belief in what Comte calls “altruisme”: the

  cardinal doctrine, it seems to me, of Jesus of Nazareth. I do not penetrate into my

  innermost feelings: it may be that my philanthropy has it’s root in selfishness: I

  may be convinced that the only means of securing my own happiness is to pursue

  that of my fellow-creatures: but surely if this profound and enlightened selfishness

  be a vice, and I sometimes fear that it is, in me, no better regimen could be applied to it than that suggested by itself, namely, devotion to Society. Whether Comtist

  or not I feel as if I never should swerve from my cardinal maxim, wh is also his

  “L’amour pur principe. Le progres pour but.”

  Such remarks, linking Christiani
ty to Comte, should suggest the thor-

  oughly religious context (even without Benson) of Sidgwick’s early dab-

  blings with utilitarianism. His reluctance to penetrate his innermost feel-

  ings was not at all like that of the eighteenth-century skeptics – say, Hume,

  who asked, “Why rake into those corners of nature which spread a nuisance

  all around?” Nor, at this early stage, did he show any great confidence in

  Bentham’s artificial harmony of interests, as so often construed, however

  misleadingly, as simply a matter-of-fact acceptance of the prevalence of

  self-interested motives. Even in his later sympathy with Bentham, he was

  apt to regard the prevalence of self-interest as akin to the prevalence of sin,

  something that had to be recognized and dealt with realistically, though

  certainly not applauded. He was bent on disciplining himself to altruism,

  always suspecting, however, that his deeper nature could be betraying him.

  P: GCV

  c.xml

  CY/Schultz

  

  January , 

  :

  First Words

  

  His consolation was that perhaps he could satisfy his true self by altruistic

  action.

  And of course, the truth is that Sidgwick did seek to penetrate his in-

  nermost feelings, and his gloriously capable intellect was largely employed

  in doing precisely that. After all, that was his Apostolic quest. Again, al-

  though during his first year or so at Cambridge he was still under Benson’s

  sway, the next year saw him “fall under different influences, which went

  on increasing” until he was “definitely enlisted as an ‘Academic Liberal.’ ”

  And it was the “rapidity and completeness of his transfer of allegiances”

  that would later strike him, and the way in which it was effected by groups

  like the Apostles and by his own independent studies, rather than by his

  formal schooling, about which he hardly ever spoke with any enthusiasm

  (rather the opposite). But the transformation was not like that of, say,

  Bertrand Russell, who would speedily abandon the religion of his youth

  under similar Apostolic circumstances, but then turn a scornful eye on

  the entire Christian tradition. Sidgwick would always regard insouciant

  atheism or agnosticism as shallow, insensitive to the religious experience

  and the demands of the human heart.

  Sidgwick’s account of his transition is of the first importance, and neatly

  outlines the different sides of his quest.

  To explain more precisely the ‘contrast’ of which I have spoken, I will begin by

  sketching briefly the ideal which, under the influence primarily of J. S. Mill, but

  partly of Comte seen through Mill’s spectacles, gradually became dominant in

  my mind in the early sixties: – I say ‘in my mind,’ but you will understand that it

  was largely derived from intercourse with others of my generation, and that at the

  time it seemed to me the only possible ideal for all adequately enlightened minds.

  It had two aspects, one social and the other philosophical or theological. What we

  aimed at from a social point of view was a complete revision of human relations,

  political, moral and economic, in the light of science directed by comprehensive

  and impartial sympathy; and an unsparing reform of whatever, in the judgment of

  science, was pronounced to be not conducive to the general happiness. This social

  science must of course have historical knowledge as a basis: but, being science, it

  must regard the unscientific beliefs, moral or political, of past ages as altogether

  wrong, – at least in respect of the method of their attainment, and the grounds

  on which they were accepted. History, in short, was conceived as supplying the

  material on which we had to work, but not the ideal which we aimed at realizing;

  except so far as history properly understood showed that the time had come for

  the scientific treatment of political and moral problems.

  P: GCV

  c.xml

  CY/Schultz

  

  January , 

  :

  

  Henry Sidgwick: Eye of the Universe

  As regards theology, those with whom I sympathised had no close agreement in

  conclusions, – their views varied from pure positivism to the ‘Neochristianity’ of

  the Essayists and Reviewers: and my own opinions were for many years unsettled

  and widely fluctuating. What was fixed and unalterable and accepted by us all was

  the necessity and duty of examining the evidence for historical Christianity with

  strict scientific impartiality; placing ourselves as far as possible outside traditional sentiments and opinions, and endeavouring to weigh the pros and cons on all

  theological questions as a duly instructed rational being from another planet – or

  let us say from China – would naturally weigh them.

  This account comports well with the better-known one affixed to the

  sixth edition of the Methods, in which Sidgwick alludes to the suffocating

  orthodoxy of both Benson and the formal Cambridge curriculum: “My

  first adhesion to a definite Ethical system was to the Utilitarianism of Mill:

  I found in this relief from the apparently external and arbitrary pressure

  of moral rules which I had been educated to obey, and which presented

  themselves to me as to some extent doubtful and confused; and some-

  times, even when clear, as merely dogmatic, unreasoned, incoherent.”

  (ME xvii) But it also indicates the larger historical currents that Sidgwick

  was caught up in. Utilitarianism was but one possible form for this en-

  thusiasm, and it did not in itself define the complex of religious questions

  and controversies, the general innovativeness, of the era. In fact, as will

  be shown, it did not represent the direction of the times at all, but was

  in some respects a more old-fashioned creed. The academic liberals were

  a much more diverse and divided group than the term “Millian” would

  suggest.

  The academic liberals of these years, the many university figures who

  went in for reformism and public service, certainly cherished ambitious

  hopes for the revamping of all that was sectarian, and they expected to play

  a leading role in preparing the nation for greater democratization, better

  and broader education, increased professionalization, and more progres-

  sive, less superstitious and dogmatic forms of worship and morality. The

  Apostles were of course much identified with this movement, as were sev-

  eral other vanguard groups around Oxbridge, though as a movement it

  could shelter philosophies as diverse as Sidgwick’s utilitarianism, Huxley’s

  Darwinism, T. H. Green’s idealism, and the Oxford Hellenism of Pater

  and the early Symonds.

  Theologically, the Essays and Reviews proved to be a turning point, when

  published in . The book was a collection of critical and latitudinarian

  P: GCV

  c.xml

  CY/Schultz

  

>   January , 

  :

  First Words

  

  or Broad Church pieces, designed to encourage open discussion of biblical

  questions by figures of eminence – Benjamin Jowett, Frederick Temple,

  Baden Powell, Mark Pattison, H. B. Wilson, Rowland Williams, and C. W.

  Goodwin. Of these, only Goodwin, of Cambridge, was a layperson. The

  heated controversy that followed its appearance predictably pointed up

  the differences that now existed between Sidgwick and Benson. Sidgwick

  was disgusted by the reaction of the church and sent a harsh letter to the

  Times, stating: “What we all want is, briefly, not a condemnation, but a

  refutation. The age when ecclesiastical censures were sufficient in such

  cases has passed away. . . . For philosophy and history alike have taught

  them [the laity] to seek not what is ‘safe,’ but what is true.” (M –

  ) This was what Benson had in mind when he complained about the

  insane desire to jump off one’s own shadow. Some years later, after the

  book had been condemned by the Convocation of Canterbury, Benson

  would defend the promotion of Temple to the see of Exeter, but he would

  do so on the grounds that Temple did not share the views of the other

  contributors.

  To seek not what is safe but what is true, and to do so with strict

  scientific impartiality, even on questions of religion and morality – these

  were convictions that Sidgwick absorbed as his own, the convictions of

  his generation. How could one go out, in good Rugby fashion, to do one’s

  Duty, when all was doubtful, even Duty itself?

  The content of Sidgwick’s theological transformation will be addressed

  in subsequent chapters. First, however, it is necessary to consider at greater

  length a more fundamental transformation, the transformation reverber-

  ating throughout Sidgwick’s talk about talk and self-creation – namely, his

  Apostolic vision of the pursuit of truth. This is the key to his theological

  and ethical development, and even to his talk itself. However playful the

  Apostolic banter may have been, it had a very real effect on Sidgwick and

  the growth of his utilitarian orientation. Lurking within his utilitarianism,

  one always finds a poetic Apostolic soul.

  IV. Pursuit of Truth

  Truth, I hold, not to be that which every man troweth, but to be that which lies

 

‹ Prev