Book Read Free

Henry Sidgwick- Eye of the Universe

Page 44

by Bart Schultz


  P: IJD,JRQ ,FhN,GLS

  cB.xml

  CY/Schultz

  

  February , 

  :

  

  Henry Sidgwick: Eye of the Universe

  ultimate rational end for himself,’ and ‘ for him all-important’? He does not attempt to define them; and it is largely the use of such undefined phrases which causes

  absurdities to be committed in philosophy.

  G. E. Moore, Principia Ethica

  The logical contradiction involved in Egoism has been powerfully argued by

  von Hartmann in his criticism of Nietzsche and Max Stirner. . . . More recently Mr. Moore has incisively expressed the difficulty as follows: ‘What Egoism holds,

  therefore, is that each man’s happiness is the sole good – that a number of different things are each of them the only good thing there is – an absolute contradiction!

  No more complete and thorough refutation of any theory could be desired. Yet

  Professor Sidgwick holds that Egoism is rational,’ a conclusion which he pro-

  ceeds to characterize as ‘absurd’ ( Principia Ethica, , p. ). I should agree with him that the position is self-contradictory in a sense in which universalistic Hedonism is not, and that with all his subtlety Sidgwick failed altogether to

  escape what was really an inconsistency in thought, even if he escaped an actual

  or formal contradiction. But to point out this logical contradiction does not seem

  to me quite so easy and final a way of refuting Sidgwick’s position as it does

  to Mr. Moore for these reasons: () The Egoist with whom Professor Sidgwick

  is arguing would probably not accept Mr. Moore’s (and my own) conception of

  an absolute objective good, though I should admit and have contended . . . that if he fully thought out what is implied in his own contention that his conduct

  is ‘reasonable’ he would be led to that conception. () Sidgwick only admitted

  that the Egoist was reasonable from one point of view – reasonable as far as he

  goes, i.e. when he refuses to ask whether his judgements are consistent with what

  he cannot help recognizing as the rational judgements of other men, and limits

  himself to asking whether he can make his own judgements consistent with them-

  selves from his own point of view. No doubt Sidgwick ought to have gone on

  to admit that this imperfectly reasonable point of view was not really reasonable

  at all, and to some extent he has done this in his last Edition. And () after all,

  even if we admit that the Egoist is unreasonable, there remains the question ‘Why

  should he care to be reasonable?’ It was largely the difficulty of answering this

  question on universalistic Hedonist principles which drove Professor Sidgwick

  to admit a ‘dualism of the Practical Reason,’ and I am not sure that the question

  has been very satisfactorily answered by Mr. Moore who, though he is no Hedo-

  nist, appears to be unwilling to give the good will the highest place in his scale

  of goods.

  Hastings Rashdall, The Theory of Good and Evil

  Although many may hope that Shaver is right in claiming that “neither

  Hobbes nor Sidgwick provides good arguments for rational egoism” and

  P: IJD,JRQ ,FhN,GLS

  cB.xml

  CY/Schultz

  

  February , 

  :

  Consensus versus Chaos

  

  that “Sidgwick suggests good arguments against it,” his suggestion that

  most philosophers after Sidgwick have been inclined to reject egoism,

  and that this view has been only weakly articulated for much of the last

  century, may well seem puzzling. True, Moore, Rashdall, Ross, and

  Prichard were quite hostile to any such view, and many of the most promi-

  nent movements of the so-called great expansion in substantive moral

  theory – Rawlsianism chief among them – have shared various neo-Kantian

  assumptions about practical reason. But there is a fairly impressive consen-

  sus (including Shaver) that Moore and the rest responded to the dualism

  with arguments that were as unsatisfactory as they were curt – thus, for

  J. L. Mackie, “egoism can coherently resist any such proof by adher-

  ing to the use of such two-place predicates as ‘right,’ ‘ought,’ and ‘good

  for’: Objectivity and universalization with respect to these are powerless

  against it.” Moore, according to Mackie, was guilty of the worst sort

  of effrontery when he chastised Sidgwick for failing to define such ex-

  pressions as “the ultimate rational end for himself,” given how Moore

  himself had so insisted on the indefinable nature of “good.” And Moore’s

  claim that “good” must be a one-place predicate, absolute, was nothing but

  sheer assertion, or an unargued assumption that “an undefined one-place-

  predicate ‘good’ can be straightforwardly meaningful, but a two-place-

  predicate ‘good for’ or ‘all-important for’ cannot.” And as Skorupski has

  put it,

  What is clear to him [Sidgwick] is that the egoistic principle can be stated in

  a rational and universal form. Of course an egoist who thinks his own good is

  the only good thing, the only thing that everyone has reason to promote, can be convicted of attaching irrational significance to his good as against that of others.

  Such an egoist thinks his own good the only thing that is ‘agent-neutrally’ good,

  the one thing that provides everyone with reasons for action. (The term is not

  used by Sidgwick; it comes from more recent moral theory.) But egoism need

  not appeal to the idea of the agent-neutrally good. The egoist may instead hold simply that his own good is the only good relative to him – this is not a tautological doctrine. And he can put this in universal terms by saying that everyone ought to

  pursue what is good relative to them, namely their own good.

  It now becomes clear that hedonism is a doctrine about what a person’s good

  is. To advance from it to utilitarianism we need at least to add that every person’s

  good is agent-neutrally good. The rational egoist can block our considerations at this point, unless we can make it plausible that reasons as such are agent-neutral.

  P: IJD,JRQ ,FhN,GLS

  cB.xml

  CY/Schultz

  

  February , 

  :

  

  Henry Sidgwick: Eye of the Universe

  Even if one claims, as Skorupski does, that pure practical reason as such

  does rest with agent-neutral reasons, the vanquishing or subordination of

  agent-relative reasons, including those deployed by rational egoists, is not

  generally regarded as simply the correction of an obvious mistake. Indeed,

  many defenders of agent-neutral reasons – including both Skorupski and

  Thomas Nagel – end up in partial retreat, allowing that agent-relative

  reasons cannot be altogether discounted. Crisp goes even further down

  the Sidgwickian path, defending a dual-source view of practical reason

  that admittedly incorporates “a version of what Henry Sidgwick called

  ‘the dualism of practical re
ason.’ ” And this allows the rational egoist

  considerable room for maneuver, as Samuel Scheffler, long associated with

  a similar dualistic account, has also observed. Thus, Hurka, in a recent

  defense of perfectionism, framed his argument by explaining that in “the

  absence of a compelling argument that goodness must be understood in

  the . . . Moorean way, I will assume with Sidgwick that claims about agent-

  relative goodness are coherent, and ask how they may affect the recursive

  account of self-interest and altruism.”

  To be sure, to cast Sidgwick’s dualism in this way is to invite again the

  question of why he narrowed the contenders down to utilitarianism and

  egoism. That is, Moore’s claim was that the expressions “my own good”

  and “good for me” are misguided because such talk can only mean that

  “something which will be exclusively mine, as my own pleasure is mine”

  is also “good absolutely,” but if “it is good absolutely that I should have it, then everyone else has as much reason for aiming at my having it as I have

  myself.” If the Sidgwickian counter to this is simply that there is such a

  thing as agent-relative goodness – such that, as Hurka puts it, “the question

  is only whether there are different ultimate ends for different people” –

  then egoism is only one variety of the challenge to agent-neutral reasons,

  Broad’s “self-referential altruism” being one of many other options.

  This is not to deny that, on Sidgwick’s rendering, as we have just seen,

  egoism houses many different alternatives, from Aristotle to Hobbes to

  Goethe. Still, for all its richness in representing “the personal point of

  view,” egoism plainly does not encompass all agent-relative reasons, and

  when Sidgwick broaches the matter of nonegoistic agent-relative reasons,

  he is often less than perspicuous. Interestingly, however, he also on occa-

  sion gestures toward further indeterminacies in practical reason, conflicts

  between agent-neutral reasons, as when he invokes the Socratic complaint

  about the injustice of a universe in which virtue goes unrewarded. And it

  P: IJD,JRQ ,FhN,GLS

  cB.xml

  CY/Schultz

  

  February , 

  :

  Consensus versus Chaos

  

  may be in part for this reason that some commentators have suggested

  that what really bothered Sidgwick was not merely the specific challenge

  of egoism, but the general indeterminacy of practical reason.

  In this connection, it should be added that the contrast between

  Sidgwick and Moore is not quite as simplistic as the just-quoted passages

  make it sound. As Hurka spells it out,

  [T]he concept of Sidgwick’s that Moore rejected was not well-being but agent-

  relative goodness. And his main reason for rejecting it was his belief that goodness

  is an unanalysable property. If goodness is this kind of property, it is hard to see

  how an object can have it “from one point of view” but not “from another”; surely

  it must either have the property or not. Compare squareness. An object cannot be

  square from one point of view but not from another; it is either square or not. (The

  object can look square from one point of view but not from another, but looking

  square is not the same as being square.) So it must be with goodness if that is a

  simply property. But Sidgwick held that goodness can be analyzed, in particular

  as what a person ought to desire, and it is perfectly possible to say that what each

  person ought to desire is different, say, just his own pleasure.

  Plausibly, this is the conflict, though as remarked in the last section, it

  is hardly obvious why Sidgwick’s “ought” did not share various features

  of the Moorean “good” in its idealizing. Still, his greater metaethical

  caution made a difference, allowing the cogency of agent-relative reasons

  generally.

  For all that, it is difficult to deny that Sidgwick was fairly obsessed with

  the varieties of egoism, and this concern has struck many as apt, given

  the power of egoism as a source for agent-relative reasons, the “personal

  point of view.” Thus, it is not surprising that Kurt Baier, for example, in

  his recent account of the subject, should suggest that rational egoism is

  “the most deeply entrenched normative theory of egoism” and that “the

  jury on this case is still in disarray.” Sidgwick, he allows, was engaged with

  just this form of the theory, in a weak version admitting that even if it is

  always rational to act out of self-interest, acting against one’s interest may

  also be rational.

  In fact, in his major work, The Rational and the Moral Order, Baier

  addresses Sidgwick’s views at length, particularly the dualism of practical

  reason:

  How serious is Sidgwick’s problem? In my view . . . it is quite serious, especially if one starts, as many do, from Sidgwick’s unfortunate formulation of it. Thus, his

  P: IJD,JRQ ,FhN,GLS

  cB.xml

  CY/Schultz

  

  February , 

  :

  

  Henry Sidgwick: Eye of the Universe

  bifurcation of practical reason need not give rise to a contradiction, even on those

  occasions when, as surely sometimes happens, the two principles do conflict. A

  contradiction would arise only if both the reasons they supported were what I

  called requiring rather than merely permissive, and even then only if they were

  indefeasible. If even only one of them is merely permissive, if it is simply perfectly rational or reasonable, say, to act for one’s own good, but not necessarily always

  irrational or unreasonable not to act for one’s own good, then one could act for the

  general good and contrary to one’s own without its necessarily being the case that

  when the two principles offer reasons for incompatible actions, one both ought

  to act for the universal good and not for one’s own, and that one ought to act for one’s own and not for the universal good.

  However, as Sidgwick seems to have sensed, there is still a problem even if this

  is granted. For if my argument . . . is sound, then Sidgwick’s position would allow that it may always be in accordance with reason to promote the universal good and

  always in accordance with reason to promote one’s own good and that, when one

  cannot do both, it is in accordance with reason to do either. Nevertheless, Sidgwick also appears to have thought, and it would seem to agree with common sense, that

  moral reasons, which he took to be those based on the universal good, defeat,

  if not all other kinds, surely at least prudential ones. . . . Sidgwick seems to have grasped this much, even if perhaps only obscurely. For in various places in which

  he produces arguments designed to persuade the Egoist to see the rationality of

  Universal Hedonism, their thrust is always to show not merely that the Universal

  Hedonist is also or equally rational, but that the Egoist ought to give up his position and become a Universal Hedonist. The thrust of his argument “from t
he

  Point of View of the Universe,” for example, appears to be that everyone should

  look at things from that point of view, and that anyone who does must adopt the

  principles of Universal Hedonism as defeating that of Egoistic Hedonism when

  the two conflict. Thus Sidgwick seems to have sensed the need for a demonstration

  that moral reasons have a greater defeating force than prudential ones, hence his

  argument from the point of view of the universe. In any case, whether or not he

  sensed it, he is surely wrong in his claim . . . that a completely rational morality requires a demonstration of a “harmony” (i.e., coextensionality) between the

  maxims of prudence . . . and of benevolence.

  These remarks both situate Sidgwick’s dualism as a live issue and

  indicate some different ways of tackling it. What is perhaps especially

  instructive is that, like Moore and Rashdall, Skorupski and Shaver, Baier

  is basically drawn to Sidgwick’s universalizing challenge to the egoist: why

  is your good so special? How, then, does one stop on the slippery slope

  before reaching the point of view of the universe? Thus, for Baier, the

  P: IJD,JRQ ,FhN,GLS

  cB.xml

  CY/Schultz

  

  February , 

  :

  Consensus versus Chaos

  

  better alternative to any attempted proof of the harmony or moral order

  of the universe is the demonstration that when morality and prudence

  conflict, “the requirements of morality defeat those of prudence.”

  But again, a more thoroughly Sidgwickian view is possible. Crisp argues

  that “Sidgwick is sometimes described as a utilitarian. But it is more precise

  to ascribe to him a version of the dual-source view, held on the basis of the

  neutral argument for the existence of options.” Quoting the distinction

  passage, he explains that (contra Shaver) it makes “a clear appeal to the

  separateness of persons as grounding a counterbalance to the reason to

  promote the good.” And for Crisp,

  Sidgwick was rightly pessimistic about the reconciliation of Rational Egoism and

  Utilitarianism. His version of the dual-source view contains at its heart an irrecon-

 

‹ Prev