Book Read Free

Henry Sidgwick- Eye of the Universe

Page 47

by Bart Schultz


  Since, however, it is manifest, at the close of the treatise, that I do not consider the principle of Rational Egoism to have been confuted, but only contradicted; and

  since I carefully explain, on p. , how in my view this confutation is avoided, I

  confess that I can hardly understand my critic’s misunderstanding.

  Here Sidgwick is actually appealing to common sense to support the

  axiomatic grounding of utilitarianism, but doing so by linking it to the

  “common belief that the design of the Creator of the world is to realise

  Good.” And he is insistently denying that egoism has been confuted by

  any of the arguments presented in the first two editions (by “contra-

  dicted” he could mean “shown to be inconclusive by the equal rationality

  of utilitarianism,” but this is not obvious), even going so far as to concede

  the weakness of the case for utilitarianism. He uses the expression the

  “dualism of practical reason” as a label for his own “ethical view,” and his

  indignation is reminiscent of that expressed in the Methods over the pos-

  sibility that the wages of virtue could be “dust.” Puzzlingly, Shaver does

  not consider this exchange in any detail. But it both affirms Sidgwick’s

  dualism in uncompromising terms and vividly expresses his worry about

  how the moral content of common sense might be dependent on religious

  belief.

  True, in “Some Fundamental Ethical Controversies,” Sidgwick did

  admit that he had earlier set out rational egoism “without a sufficient ra-

  tional justification,” as Gizycki had claimed. And he allowed the tenability

  of Gizycki’s view that “the preference of Virtue or general happiness to

  private happiness is a dictate of reason, which remains no less clear and co-

  gent, however ultimate and uncompensated may be the sacrifice of private

  happiness that it imposes,” because “even if the reality and essentiality

  of the distinction between one individual and another be granted, I do

  P: IJD,JRQ ,FhN,GLS

  cB.xml

  CY/Schultz

  

  February , 

  :

  Consensus versus Chaos

  

  not see how to prove its fundamental practical importance to anyone who

  refuses to admit it.” Yet, revealingly, Sidgwick concludes this passage by

  flatly stating “but I find such a refusal impossible to myself, and I think it

  paradoxical.”

  Impossible? Paradoxical? Why “impossible,” of all things, unless some-

  thing along the lines of Schneewind’s interpretation is correct?

  Sidgwick does also appeal to common sense, but in a curious way that ad-

  mits that the explicit articulation of egoism has not been all that common:

  I admit that it is only a minority of moralists who explicitly accept this dualism of rational or governing principles; but I think myself justified in inferring a wider

  implicit acceptance of the dualism from the importance attached by dogmatic

  moralists generally to the conception of a moral government of the world, and

  from the efforts of empirical utilitarians to prove – as in Bentham’s posthumous

  treatise – that action conducive to greatest happiness is always also conducive to

  the agent’s greatest happiness.

  If his own statement of the dualism has proved controversial, and thus

  somewhat confidence-shaking, nonetheless his confidence is partly re-

  stored by the fact that “while to some critics the sacrifice of self to others

  seems solely rational, others avow uncompromising egoism; and no one

  has seriously attemped to deny that the choice between one or other alter-

  native – according to any forecast of happiness based on mere mundane

  experience – is occasionally forced on us.” If Gizycki and Rashdall fell

  on one side, Barratt fell on the other.

  Thus, the upshot would seem to be that common sense in fact contains,

  in implicit form, a potentially explosive contradiction, waiting to emerge

  once the religious worldview fades. Put differently, Sidgwick questions,

  in a way that other secular utilitarians did not, the degree to which the

  utilitarian evolution of morality may in fact, perhaps paradoxically, have

  depended on the evolution of Christianity. Lurking behind the minimal

  metaphysics of the Methods is the hope that secular morality will be able

  to go it alone, but also the profound worry that this may prove impossible.

  One is strongly tempted to interpret this in the light of Sidgwick’s per-

  sonal struggles and his reluctance to openly attack religion. That is, as

  the material presented in Chapter  strongly suggests, Sidgwick was pro-

  foundly uncertain about the degree to which commonsense morality would

  lean toward utilitarian justifications of self-sacrifice, should religious skep-

  ticism grow more pervasive, and a fuller discussion of egoism’s grounding

  P: IJD,JRQ ,FhN,GLS

  cB.xml

  CY/Schultz

  

  February , 

  :

  

  Henry Sidgwick: Eye of the Universe

  would necessitate the very thing he had determined not to give: an open,

  explicit critical discussion of the failings of theology. It was one thing to

  claim that practical reason required a theistic postulate for its unity; it

  was something else again to demonstrate why theology could not pro-

  vide this and how that might undermine the moral force of self-sacrifice,

  as embedded in common sense. Sidgwick was so obviously exercised by

  what would happen when the religious worldview finally came apart in the

  popular consciousness, and so drawn to the view (despite his criticisms of

  Seeley) that utilitarianism captured in a refined way the virtue of Christian

  benevolence, that the possibility that utilitarianism was actually drawing

  on intellectual capital supplied by the Christian inheritance was for him a

  rather natural worry. Yes, common sense on balance supported utilitarian-

  ism, and carried some justificatory force. But common sense was evolving,

  hard to pin down, and at least somewhat divided. Could the aversion to

  frank egoism be sustained without a broadly religious consciousness? How

  else to explain the characteristic confession:

  [T]he reason why I keep strict silence now for many years with regard to theology

  is that while I cannot myself discover adequate rational basis for the Christian

  hope of happy immortality, it seems to me that the general loss of such a hope,

  from the minds of average human beings as now constituted, would be an evil of

  which I cannot pretend to measure the extent. I am not prepared to say that the

  dissolution of the existing social order would follow, but I think the danger of such dissolution would be seriously increased, and that the evil would certainly be very

  great. (M )

  Presumably, Sidgwick was not being silently horrified at the prospect of

  further progress toward a society of ideal utilitarians of an enlightened sec-

  ular bent, or even a society of perfectionists. Yet Shaver�
��s account supplies

  no explanation whatsoever of this fundamental Sidgwickian concern. At

  most, Shaver explains that Sidgwick

  thinks utilitarianism provides a good explanation of differences in common-sense

  morality over time, place, and occupation. For example, theft is venial where labour

  is unnecessary. . . . He also thinks utilitarianism can be seen as what common-sense morality is coming increasingly to approximate. . . . This supports the conclusion that utilitarianism underlies common-sense morality. Sidgwick does not claim

  that rational egoism provides a poorer explanation or destination, and he has some

  reason not to do so: since rational egoists and utilitarians will usually make the same recommendations, the appeal to differences over time, place, and occupation may

  P: IJD,JRQ ,FhN,GLS

  cB.xml

  CY/Schultz

  

  February , 

  :

  Consensus versus Chaos

  

  be insufficiently fine grained to reveal a winner. However, Sidgwick does record

  one change that favours utilitarianism. Rational egoism has difficulty explaining

  duties to those who cannot reciprocate. But such duties have become increasingly

  popular: Sidgwick notes the condemnation of exposing infants and the extension

  of aid for the sick and poor. (ME n) He might now add the concern with animal

  welfare. If so, utilitarianism better explains not just our verdicts and reasoning,

  but also changes in common sense.

  To emphasize, during the era of Herbert Spencer, the utilitarian support

  for protecting the vulnerable was surely admirable, and Shaver is correct

  to call attention to this part of Sidgwick’s argument. But clearly, none

  of this goes very far toward explaining how Sidgwick could at the same

  time be so worried about the direction of commonsense morality and the

  undermining of the social order. Shaver himself goes on to observe:

  It is quite plausible to think Sidgwick overestimates the force of his indirect

  utilitarian considerations. Utilitarianism is probably more demanding than he

  supposes. It is less plausible, but still possible, that he underestimates the force

  of the indirect rational egoist considerations. If so, common-sense morality may

  be friendlier to rational egoism, and more hostile to utilitarianism, than has been

  argued. This, I think, shows the importance of Sidgwick’s appeal to common-sense

  moral reasoning and to historical change. Provided these favour utilitarianism over

  rational egoism, Sidgwick might concede that, when attention is confined to the

  dictates of each regarding sacrifices, the case for choosing utilitarianism over

  rational egoism on the basis of common sense is inconclusive.

  But of course, if Sidgwick were worried about precisely such potential

  errors in his assessment, and not very confident in his – or anyone else’s –

  ability to predict the direction of historical change, then he would be much

  more anxious about the viability of egoism, in this respect, than Shaver

  suggests, and rightly so.

  There can be little doubt that Sidgwick was more agnostic in just this

  way, and that this in part explains his deep gloom over the “failure” of the

  Methods. In June of , he had written to Myers:

  As for my philosophy, it gets on slowly. I think I have made out a point or two

  about Justice: but the relation of the sexes still puzzles me. It is a problem with ever new x’s and y’s emerging. Is the permanent movement of civilized man towards the Socialism of force, or the Socialism of persuasion (Comte), or individualism

  (H. Spencer)? I do not know, and yet everything seems to turn on it.

  P: IJD,JRQ ,FhN,GLS

  cB.xml

  CY/Schultz

  

  February , 

  :

  

  Henry Sidgwick: Eye of the Universe

  This is not an idiosyncratic expression of ignorance. Quite the con-

  trary. As Sidgwick wryly argued in his essay on “Political Prophecy and

  Sociology”:

  [I]nnovators whose social and political ideals are really in their inception quite

  unhistorical, are naturally led to adopt the historical method as an instrument of

  persuasion. In order to induce the world to accept any change that they desire, they

  endeavour to show that the whole course of history has been preparing the way

  for it – whether ‘it’ is the reconciliation of Science and Religion, or the complete

  realisation of Democracy, or the fuller perfection of Individualism, or the final

  triumph of Collectivism. The vast aggregate of past events – many of them half-

  known and more half-understood – which makes up what we call history, afford

  a malleable material for the application of this procedure: by judicious selection

  and well-arranged emphasis, by ignoring inconvenient facts and filling gaps of

  knowledge with convenient conjectures – it is astonishing how easy it is plausibly

  to represent any desired result as the last inevitable outcome of the operation of

  the laws of social development; the last term of a series of which the formula is

  known to the properly instructed historian. (MEA –)

  Or the properly instructed theologian, moral theorist, and so on, and on.

  Naturally, this also suggests the importance of the complications arising

  from the various indirect forms of utilitarianism and egoism, when it came

  to making out the direction of common sense and its epistemic worth. What

  could be more obvious than Sidgwick’s overwhelming sense that he had

  succeeded only in bringing out the incalculable nature of so much that

  was of importance in human affairs, rendering the particular demands

  of duty highly uncertain and contestable? This was a most ironic fate

  for someone with utilitarian sympathies, who had prized the objective,

  conflict-resolving features of this position, but it is hard to deny that it

  was Sidgwick’s, especially given the tentativeness of his major treatises

  on economics and political theory. The point will be spelled out in later

  chapters.

  And this penumbra of uncertainty about the nature of good – how to

  interpret it, how to calculate it, and consequently how to estimate the value

  of indirect strategies – goes far toward providing a reasonable explanation

  of the depth of Sidgwick’s anxiety about the death of God as it bore on

  ethics. This is not only concern about the disenchantment coming with

  the popular realization that the life of virtue might be dust (though it

  is certainly that as well), but also concern that narrower, materialistic

  forms of egoism could be that much harder to dismiss. Consider, by way

  P: IJD,JRQ ,FhN,GLS

  cB.xml

  CY/Schultz

  

  February , 

  :

  Consensus versus Chaos

  

  of example, the spectre of James Fitzjames Stephen, an illustrious old

  Apostle whose infamous attack on Mill, Liberty, Eq
uality, Fraternity, was

  reviewed by Sidgwick in , just as he was completing the Methods:

  The third part of the treatise is so far original that it attacks the one element

  in Christian teaching which the most virulent antagonists of Christianity have

  hitherto left unassailed – the sentiment of human brotherhood. In discussing

  ‘Fraternity’ Mr. Stephen seems to confound two very distinct issues, how far

  men actually do love each other, and how far it would be for their mutual benefit

  that they should. Sometimes, indeed, the discussion seems to be almost narrowed

  to the question whether Mr. Fitzjames Stephen loves his fellow-men: which, he

  assures us, is only the case to a very limited extent. Life, to Mr. Stephen, would

  be intolerable without fighting: a millennium where the lion is to lie down with the

  lamb, presents to him a very flat and tedious prospect: he has no patience with the

  sentimentalists who insist on pestering him with their nauseous affection. These

  facts are not without interest for the psychological student: and we may admit that

  they exhibit forcibly the difficulty of realising the evangelical ideal.

  Sidgwick claims that these are not “serious arguments against the prac-

  tical doctrine that any possible increase of mutual goodwill among the

  members of the human family is likely to be attended with an increase of

  their common happiness.” But he allows that Stephen “generally assumes

  that every one must necessarily wish to impose his own idea of happiness

  upon every one else: indeed in one place he goes so far as to say that if two

  persons’ views of what constitutes happiness are conflicting, they cannot

  have a mutual wish for each other’s happiness.”

  Worth recalling in this context is Sidgwick’s statement, in the first

  edition of the Methods, that

  we cannot even concede to Hobbes that under existing circumstances it is a clear universal precept of Rational Self-love that a man should “seek peace and ensue

  it:” since some men gain, by the disturbance of society, wealth, fame, and power,

  to an extent to which in peaceful times they could not hope to approximate: and

  though there is always some risk involved in this mode of pursuing these goods,

  it may be reduced to a small amount by a cool and skilful person who has the art

  of fishing in troubled waters. It may be admitted that this road to success is over-

 

‹ Prev