Book Read Free

Henry Sidgwick- Eye of the Universe

Page 63

by Bart Schultz


  always voyaging, the friends of Socrates knew what soaring was all about.

  As Symonds explained, when recounting some of Tennyson’s views

  on how “moral good is the crown of man,” though it would be nothing

  “without immortality” – views that were expressed at a dinner party also

  including Symonds, his father, and Gladstone:

  In all this metaphysical vagueness about matter, morals, the existence of evil, and

  the evidences of God there was something almost childish. Such points pass with

  most men for settled as insoluble after a time. But Tennyson has a perfect simplicity about him which recognises the real greatness of such questions, and regards

  them as always worthy of consideration. He treats them with profound moral

  earnestness. His “In Memoriam” and “Two Voices” illustrate this habit. There

  is nothing original or startling – on the contrary, a general common-placeness,

  about his metaphysics; yet, so far as they go, they express real agitating questions –

  express, in a poet’s language, what most men feel and think about.

  Ironically, then, Sidgwick’s “club” was a very metaphysically engaged

  one. Given this, and his philosophical erudition, the obvious question that

  presents itself is why he was not more receptive to the Kantian–Hegelian

  answers to the problems that he had so labored over. Kant and Kantism

  also spoke to the issue of the dualism of practical reason, and they also

  offered up a solution couched in the language of immortality. How could a

  mind as philosophically penetrating as Sidgwick’s have pronounced para-

  psychology the more promising prospect?

  Thus, a more extensive comparison between Sidgwick’s project and

  the Idealist one might prove singularly helpful. After all, many of the

  questions to be addressed concern the degree to which Sidgwick was, in

  his own peculiar fashion, in fact engaged in a project akin to Green’s, or

  P: GYQ

  ca.xml

  CY/Schultz

  

  February , 

  :

  

  Henry Sidgwick: Eye of the Universe

  for that matter Jowett’s, both of whom he knew and admired as fellow

  academic liberals. Next to evolutionism, it was Idealism – whether in

  the older, more Platonic form represented by Jowett, or in the newer

  Kantian–Hegelian synthesis represented by Green and Bradley – that

  exercised Sidgwick as a philosophical and political rival, a more serious

  rendering of the perfectionist alternative than Arnold’s. And it did so in

  part because the entire Oxford philosophical context reflected in its own

  way the Apostolic ethic of personal growth through intimate (if tutorial)

  friendships between teachers and students. Indeed, later Victorian Oxford

  carried this to a pitch rather beyond tranquil Cambridge, though the

  differences between the two institutions are often overstated. Symonds

  was an Oxford product, a student of Jowett, Green, Conington, and the

  other lights of liberalism. Green, as it happened, would end up marrying

  Symonds’s sister, Charlotte.

  To be sure, there was much straightforward philosophical debate over

  Sidgwick’s work, particularly over the Methods, emanating from Oxford.

  The later objections of Moore and Rashdall, mainly directed at Sidgwick’s

  defenses of egoism and hedonism, were all anticipated earlier on, partic-

  ularly by Green and Bradley (but also by others who resist easy classifica-

  tion, notably such Cambridge figures as Goldsworthy Lowes Dickenson

  and James Ward – two more of Sidgwick’s spiritual offspring). But

  Green, more than these others, was Sidgwick’s immediate rival, the friend

  and contemporary who also represented the academic liberal agenda and

  whose influence, like Jowett’s, extended far beyond the academic setting.

  He represented much more, to Sidgwick, than a mere alternative academic

  philosophy.

  In so many respects, Green is the bridge to Sidgwick’s deeper concerns –

  speculative, social, and sexual. An earnest academic liberal with deep

  religious convictions worked into an Idealist philosophy bordering on

  spiritualism, and an inspiring teacher who, among other things, coached

  Symonds in Plato, Green was the one who invariably appeared whenever

  Sidgwick looked over his shoulder. They virtually began philosophizing

  together; Sidgwick would recall how Green was stimulated to philosophize

  by his classics, such that when “he was out walking one day with Green,

  they came upon a bridge which his companion attempted to prove was a

  different bridge for each of them.” Green too was pained that the

  most intelligent critics had rather, it would seem, that the ideas which poetry

  applies to life, together with those which form the basis of practical religion,

  P: GYQ

  ca.xml

  CY/Schultz

  

  February , 

  :

  Friends versus Friends

  

  should be left to take their chance alongside of seemingly incompatible scientific

  beliefs, than that anything calling itself philosophy should seek to systematise

  them and to ascertain the regions to which they on the one side, and the truths of

  science on the other, are respectively applicable.

  Green, as noted in previous chapters, had no use for psychical research

  and found in Idealist metaphysics the revivifying intellectual and cultural

  force that would fill the void left by disintegrating Christian orthodoxy. Or

  rather, he took his philosophical mission to be one of supporting Christian

  orthodoxy, albeit of the Mauricean, Broad Church variety, mixed with his

  own Evangelical Puritanism, an aspect of his familial background for which

  he always evinced some sympathy. As he put it to a former pupil in ,

  he could find no greater satisfaction “than to think that I at all helped to lay

  the intellectual platform for your religious life.” If he were “only a breeder

  of heretics,” he would suspect his philosophy, which, if it is “sound,” ought

  “to supply intellectual formulae for the religious life whether lived by an

  ‘orthodox’ clergyman or (let us say) a follower of Mazzini.” Green, that

  is, “never dreamt of philosophy doing instead of religion,” and his own

  interest in it “is wholly religious” in “the sense that it is to me . . . the reasoned intellectual expression of the effort to get to God.”

  Thus, Green’s attitude may well seem quite different from Sidgwick’s.

  As Schneewind has it, for Sidgwick, “philosophy is the rational search for

  truth, and if Christianity turns out to possess it, so much the better for

  Christianity. For Green, it seems, philosophy has the task of showing that

  Christianity does possess the truth, and if the philosopher fails to come to

  that result, then it follows that he has more work to do.” But this is not

  quite right. Plainly, Sidgwick worried considerably about his philosophical

  results being so hard on the human heart, and kept searchin
g.

  It is scarcely odd that Sidgwick and Green should have shared much by

  way of the religious attitude. Green was also a Rugby product – indeed, one

  of Sidgwick’s old Rugby friends. During the sixties, both were hammering

  out their distinctive philosophical worldviews and often doing so by direct

  exchange – for instance, while on a walking tour of the continent in .

  Sidgwick would later confess, in his “Reminiscences of T. H. Green,”

  that he was at this point “in a crude and confident stage of utilitarianism”

  and consequently “quite unappreciative” of Green’s line. And plainly,

  he did not appreciate his “sniffing” at psychical research. Green was a

  strange figure, the model for a character named Professor Grey in Mary

  (Mrs. Humphrey) Ward’s Robert Elsmere, a novel about an earnest young

  P: GYQ

  ca.xml

  CY/Schultz

  

  February , 

  :

  

  Henry Sidgwick: Eye of the Universe

  man who loses his orthodox faith but finds a new one in working for the

  underprivileged, inspired in part by professor Grey. By all accounts, Green

  was, if not as austere as some claimed, exceedingly earnest and lost in his

  own soul searching. As Melvin Richter has judiciously described him:

  There was general agreement about the quality of Green’s mind. ‘You never talked

  to him without carrying away something to remember and ponder over.’ Yet it

  seemed highly unlikely that he would accommodate himself to university life any

  better than he had done to Rugby. The classical philology that bulked so large in

  the Greats curriculum bored him. In his first trial by examination, he failed to

  distinguish himself. Absorbed in his efforts to articulate views unusually personal

  and deeply felt, he was notorious for puzzling on Monday over essays that had

  been due the previous Friday. None of this augured well for a successful university

  career. And yet the class of degree achieved by a poor clergyman’s son might fix

  the course of his future life. With First Class Honours doors would be opened

  to him, beyond which he otherwise could not hope to penetrate. Left to himself,

  Green’s character might have manifested itself in a mediocre record which would

  have condemned him to eking out an existence as a schoolmaster, or to burying

  himself in an obscure government post. But Green fortunately profited from the

  ministrations of his tutor, that Pascal of the undergraduate heart.

  Jowett saw something worth stimulating in this gauche freshman.

  Just what Jowett saw in his earnest young Anglican Evangelical is, as

  Richter explains, most illuminating: “As he said many years later, the only

  person in his experience who at all resembled this singular young man was

  another Rugbeian who had entered Balliol twenty years before, Arthur

  Hugh Clough.” If Clough was the “more indolently dreamy” of the two,

  and Green the more abstract, Jowett was nonetheless a shrewd judge of his

  students. As Richter puts it, referring to Clough and Green: “Reserved

  and self-contained, they moved in a detached sphere of almost inhuman

  high principle. Society and politics were to them intimate realities, the

  great problems of which it had fallen to them personally to resolve.” Had

  Sidgwick taken up the Balliol option, following Rugby, there might have

  been another young Cloughian in Jowett’s care and keeping.

  But as he would shortly discover with yet another dreamy student –

  namely, Symonds – Jowett found that Green needed more than a little

  prodding.

  Jowett decided that it was only through his Puritan sense of duty that Green

  could be made to work. And so, particularly after Green disappointed his friends

  P: GYQ

  ca.xml

  CY/Schultz

  

  February , 

  :

  Friends versus Friends

  

  and family by taking a Second in Moderations, his tutor began to prod. Green’s

  essays, he remarked, were much too dry and dull, a fault which might be repaired

  by reading poetry. But Jowett’s major stroke was yet to come. One day he said

  casually: ‘If you do not get your First, Green, I shall have a good deal to answer for.’ This remark Green later recalled as the turning point of his life. Knowing

  how much the prestige of the college meant to his tutor, Green’s sense of duty

  was called into play: the gospel of work taught by Carlyle, Dr. Arnold, and Jowett

  had now to be applied to himself and his conditions. And so he plunged into the

  task ahead.

  With the support and stimulus of Jowett, and the help of C. S. Parker

  and John Conington – the University Professor of Latin and another old

  (though strikingly radical) Rugbeian – Green was stirred up, transformed,

  and in due course, after many walks and many talks and many reading par-

  ties, became a successful First, the first lay Fellow of Balliol, and in due

  course Professor. He became a fixture of the “Old Mortality Society,” the

  somewhat less secretive Oxford equivalent of the Apostles that included

  such notable figures as Symonds, Bryce, Dicey, Walter Pater, and Algernon

  Swinburne. All in all, he represented the virtues of that very personal and

  intimate form of education that had come to mark Oxford, an outgrowth,

  in part, of the Tractarian movement’s transformation of the tutorial into a

  transfiguring personal experience, a spiritual awakening. It was common

  Oxbridge ground that, in the words of Noel Annan, “all fellows, certainly

  all directors of studies and tutors, should try, as far as they were able, to

  become the guide, philosopher and friend of those they taught.” Edu-

  cation was a very important and a very personal business – indeed, not a

  business at all, but a special form of intimacy. The Platonic revival came

  to fruition in Jowett’s Oxford.

  But Green imbibed this in a fashion that mixed Platonic elitism with

  a good deal of Puritan moral democracy. W. L. Newman gave a famous,

  and by all accounts accurate, description of him:

  His habitual dress of black and grey suited him well and was true to his character.

  He was drawn to plain people, to people of the middle and lower class rather than

  to the upper, to the puritans of the past and the nonconformists of the present, to

  Germans, to all that is sober-suited and steady-going. One judged from his feeling

  for homely, unadorned and solid worth what he must feel for things showy, brilliant

  and hollow.

  P: GYQ

  ca.xml

  CY/Schultz

  

  February , 

  :

  

  Henry Sidgwick: Eye of the Universe

  Of course, Sidgwick was also in love with things German, and in the

  sixties he vied with Green for superior knowledge of German biblical

  criticism and philosophy. In ,
he had explained to Dakyns: “I should

  like to get at this Oxford Hegelianism and see what it means. I used to

  talk with Green, but I did not draw much.” (M ) Again, Sidgwick

  was always perfectly ready to admit the importance of Kant and Kantism.

  Indeed, he began his lectures on the metaphysics of Kant by observing

  that “it is partly at least to Kant that we trace the origin of the systems

  of metaphysical thought which have most vogue at the present day – the

  Agnosticism of Spencer (though here the influence is indirect, through

  Hamilton and Mansel), and more directly the Idealism or Spiritualism of

  which I take Green as a representative” (LPK ). Thus, he found the

  root of both Spencer’s evolutionism and Green’s Idealism in the works of

  Kant, which suggests how he attached much more importance to the latter

  than the arguments of the Methods reveal.

  Now, as many have observed, when Green translated his general predis-

  positions into philosophical Idealism, it was in a somewhat more demo-

  cratic and reforming fashion than that of many later Idealists, such as

  his student F. H. Bradley. Little wonder that, whereas Sidgwick’s ex-

  changes with Bradley were marked by an unusual asperity on both sides, his

  exchanges with Green were far more congenial.

  Green, of course, in good Hegelian fashion, did not fear the growth of

  the state in quite the way that most of the old Benthamites or Millians did,

  but rather regarded it as potentially a positive force for spiritual develop-

  ment, for positive freedom, especially when it came to education. The

  disciples of Jowett may have been concerned with the practical business

  of running the empire on Platonic grounds, but the disciples of Green –

  notably Arnold Toynbee – also went on to produce the settlement move-

  ment and nurse the work of Mary Ward and Jane Addams, who went far

  toward implementing the Mauricean social gospel of bringing the classes

  together and opening up educational and cultural opportunities to all. The

  library fireplace at Mary Ward House (formerly the Passmore Edwards

  Settlement, an early settlement that complemented Toynbee Hall) bore

  the initials T. H. G., in honor of its philosophical inspirer, after whom the

  library was named. Ironically, in the late s it would also house the

 

‹ Prev