Book Read Free

Henry Sidgwick- Eye of the Universe

Page 105

by Bart Schultz


  the argument for laissez-faire requires “besides the psychological proposi-

  tion that every one can best take care of his own interest” the “sociological

  proposition that the common welfare is best attained by each pursuing

  exclusively his own welfare and that of his family in a thoroughly alert and

  intelligent manner” (EP ). And he stresses how no actual nation

  is composed of individuals having only the few simple and general characteristics

  which are all we can include in our conception of the civilised man to whom our

  abstract political reasoning relates. An actual nation consists of persons of whom

  the predominant number have, besides the general characteristics . . . a certain vaguely defined complex of particular characteristics which we call the ‘national

  character’ of Englishmen, Frenchmen, etc.; among which sentiments and habits

  of thought and action, formed by the previous history of the nation, must always

  occupy a prominent place: and a consideration of these particular characteristics

  may properly modify to an important extent the conclusions arrived at by our

  general reasoning. (EP –)

  This fixation on “national character” was, as previously noted, perva-

  sive during this period, a legacy of Romanticism that had passed into

  P: IJD

  cA.xml

  CY/Schultz

  

  February , 

  :

  

  Henry Sidgwick: Eye of the Universe

  the post-Darwinian ethos, and one that can be found throughout the

  work of Sidgwick and his various social scientific friends. It is quite cen-

  tral to Sidgwick’s thought, complementing his account of commonsense

  morality.

  Clearly, Sidgwick is once again setting up the individualistic (or non-

  paternalistic) principle for an extended beating, decorously disguised by

  his admission that it is in the main sound and the best point of departure

  for considering admissible deviations. He wastes no time in explaining

  that it will not do either as a basic or ultimate principle or as the means

  of advancing human happiness. In fact, the Elements goes a bit further,

  claiming

  general – if not universal – assent for the principle that the true standard and criterion by which right legislation is to be distinguished from wrong is conduciveness

  to the general ‘good’ or ‘welfare.’ And probably the great majority of persons

  would agree to interpret the ‘good’ or ‘welfare’ of the community to mean, in

  the last analysis, the happiness of the individual human beings who compose the

  community; provided that we take into account not only the human beings who

  are actually living but those who are to live hereafter.

  At any rate, he continues, this is his view, and thoughout this treatise he

  will “take the happiness of the persons affected as the ultimate end and

  standard of right and wrong in determining the functions and constitution

  of government” (EP ). Of course, in Millian fashion, he owns that “when

  we have agreed to take general happiness as the ultimate end, the most

  important part of our work still remains to be done: we have to establish or

  assume some subordinate principle or principles, capable of more precise

  application, relating to the best means for attaining by legislation the end of

  Maximum Happiness” (EP ). Obviously, this is where the individualistic

  principle comes in.

  This is, to be sure, a fairly generous assessment of the general political

  consciousness, one that cannot help but make many of Sidgwick’s concerns

  about the dualism of practical reason fade into the background, at least

  somewhat, though this is consistent with his statements about common

  sense being only implicitly or potentially as receptive to egoism as it is

  to utilitarianism, with the decline of religion. The actual rational egoistic

  arguments of Hobbes or Bentham (or of orthodox political economists,

  for that matter) find little resonance in the Elements, and the generous

  reconstruction of political common sense would seem to be at odds with

  P: IJD

  cA.xml

  CY/Schultz

  

  February , 

  :

  Colors

  

  Sidgwick’s worries about the rank selfishness evident in party politics. Not

  surprisingly, it was of the Elements that Hayek complained that although

  it was “in many respects an admirable work,” it scarcely “represents what

  must be regarded as the British liberal tradition and is already strongly

  tainted with that rationalist utilitarianism which led to socialism.” Hayek

  was not one to be put off the scent by Mauricean subterfuges.

  Indeed, the list of deviations from individualism that Sidgwick assem-

  bles is quite daunting, covering again a vast range of items such as educa-

  tion, defense, child care, poor relief, public works, collective bargaining,

  and so forth. He delicately teases apart the different degrees of interven-

  tion, according to whether the government “merely regulates, and perhaps

  subvents,” or “itself undertakes a department of business,” or actually

  “establishes a legal monopoly of the business in its own favour – as in the

  case of the post office in England” (EP ). He stresses two cases that he

  thinks point up in a quite obvious way the limitations of the individual-

  istic principle: “the humane treatment of lunatics, and the prevention of

  cruelty to the inferior animals.” Such restrictions do not aim at securing

  the freedom of the lunatics or the animals, but are “a one-sided restraint

  of the freedom of action of men with a view to the greatest happiness of

  the aggregate of sentient beings.” An unfortunate note explains that the

  “protection of inferior races of men will be considered in a subsequent

  chapter.” (EP –)

  In typical manner, such considerations lead Sidgwick back to the dis-

  cussion of socialism. Many of the cases discussed shade imperceptibly

  from individualism to socialism – thus, “when it is evident that children

  are, through their parents’ poverty, growing up in such a way as to render

  them likely to be burdensome or dangerous to society, it seems prima facie

  a prudent insurance against this result for the community to assist in their

  support and education.” Here, Sidgwick recognizes, there is indeed a slip-

  pery slope, though not one that can realistically be avoided. For “similar

  arguments may be used to justify a governmental provision of sustenance

  for adults, in order that they may not be driven into criminal courses: and

  if either kind of governmental assistance is once admitted as justifiable

  in principle, it is not very easy to limit the burden that may be thrown

  on industrious and provident individuals by the improvidence of others.”

  This question lands us in “the debatable territory between Individualism

  and Socialism.” (EP ) But Sidgwick is starting to sound much mo
re

  like Green on temperance than Mill on liberty.

  P: IJD

  cA.xml

  CY/Schultz

  

  February , 

  :

  

  Henry Sidgwick: Eye of the Universe

  In the Elements, the extremist form of socialism is labelled “collec-

  tivism” rather than “communism.” Against collectivism or communism

  Sidgwick, as usual, urges that it would under the present circumstances

  “arrest industrial progress,” in such a way that “the comparative equality

  in incomes which it would bring about would be an equality in poverty”

  (EP ). But in this book, much more a product of the turbulent eighties

  that witnessed the rebirth of working-class activism, he seems far less con-

  fident that the extreme form of socialism has had its day, and admits in less

  qualified fashion that such a scheme “has much attraction for thoughtful

  and sympathetic persons; not only from its tendency to equalise wealth,

  but also from the possibilities it holds out of saving the waste and avoiding

  the unmerited hardships incident to the present competitive organisation

  of business; and of substituting industrial peace, mutual service, and a

  general diffusion of public spirit, for the present conflict of classes and

  selfish struggles of individuals” (EP ). The general case of socialistic

  interference is presented in, if anything, an even more favorable, polit-

  ically relevant light than it was in the Principles, and the evolution to-

  ward collectivism is cast as “quite conceivable,” through “improvements

  in the organisation and working of governmental departments, aided by

  watchful and intelligent public criticism – together with a rise in the

  general level of public spirit throughout society” (EP –). The col-

  lectivist idea is only impracticable “at the present time or in the proximate

  future.”

  Allowing that much of the relevant discussion is a matter for political

  economy, Sidgwick is nonetheless anxious to “point out certain general

  considerations which must to some extent govern our estimate of the expe-

  diency” of socialistic schemes especially concerned with “the mitigation

  of the harshest inequalities in the present distribution of incomes” (EP

  ). He thinks it “indubitable that the attainment of greater equality in

  the distribution of the means and opportunities of enjoyment is in itself

  a desirable thing, if only it can be attained without any material sacrifice

  of the advantages of freedom,” and he accepts, as he did in the Methods

  and the Principles, “Bentham’s view, that any given quantum of wealth

  is generally likely to be less useful to its owner, the greater the total of

  private wealth of which it forms a part . . . that the utility of a given quantum of any particular commodity to its possessor tends to be diminished,

  in proportion as the total amount of the commodity in his possession

  is increased” (EP ). While admitting the force of the arguments for

  P: IJD

  cA.xml

  CY/Schultz

  

  February , 

  :

  Colors

  

  maintaining incentives to productivity, and for the “effective maintenance

  and progress of intellectual culture” through “the existence of a numerous

  group of persons enjoying complete leisure and the means of ample ex-

  penditure,” Sidgwick still insists that “at least the removal of the extreme

  inequalities, found in the present distribution of wealth and leisure, would

  be desirable, if it could be brought about without any material repression

  of the free development of individual energy and enterprise” (EP ).

  The discussion that follows is hardly what one would call utopian, with

  its account of the English Poor Law as guilty of diminishing “the induce-

  ments to industry and thrift, without any counterbalancing tendency to

  stimulate labour by enlarging its opportunities” – such systems “simply

  and nakedly take the produce of those who have laboured successfully

  to supply the needs of those who have laboured unsuccessfully or not at

  all.” Again, he tends to favor measures that avoid such controversy, be-

  cause their “primary aim is not to redistribute compulsorily the produce of

  labour, but to equalise the opportunities of obtaining wealth by productive

  labour, without any restriction on the freedom of adults.” (EP ) Inter-

  estingly, against the objection that even such schemes as these cost money,

  and will have to be funded by taxation that is effectively redistributive, he

  argues that such arguments ignore the fact

  that the institution of private property as actually existing goes beyond what

  the individualistic theory justifies. Its general aim is to appropriate the results

  of labour to the labourer, but in realising this aim it has inevitably appropriated

  natural resources to an extent which, in any fully peopled country, has entirely

  discarded Locke’s condition of ‘leaving enough and as good for others.’ In any

  such country, therefore, the propertied classes are in the position of encroaching

  on the opportunities of the unpropertied in a manner which – however defensible

  as the only practicable method of securing the results of labour – yet renders a

  demand for compensation justifiable from the most strictly individualistic point

  of view. It would seem that such compensation may fitly be given by well-directed

  outlay, tending either to increase the efficiency and mobility of labour, or to bring within the reach of all members of a civilised society some share of the culture

  which we agree in regarding as the most valuable result of civilisation: and in

  so far as this is done without such heavy taxation as materially diminishes the

  stimulus to industry and thrift of the persons taxed, this expenditure of public

  money, however justly it may be called Socialistic, appears to be none the less de-

  fensible as the best method of approximating to the ideal of Individualistic justice.

  (EP )

  P: IJD

  cA.xml

  CY/Schultz

  

  February , 

  :

  

  Henry Sidgwick: Eye of the Universe

  This passage, reflecting the familiar line of argument dealing with

  Spencer’s inconsistent individualism, marks again Sidgwick’s penetrating

  assessment of how the champions of laissez-faire have tended to “tacitly

  assume” conditions of equality of opportunity – or at least, “the loss to the

  community arising from the restricted opportunities of large masses has

  been tacitly overlooked.” Given that, when he wrote this, it was still the

  case that some  percent of the land in England was owned by the aristoc-

  racy, the whiff of Ricardian radicalism about the conflictual components

  of the English economy
is undeniable. And the conclusion Sidgwick

  derives is, as we have seen, more general than the Ricardian one, given the

  difficulty of drawing the line between property in land and property in

  manufacturing or financial assets.

  The ensuing discussion, concerning poor relief, draws together a num-

  ber of Sidgwick’s arguments on the topic, from his various unpublished

  lectures on the “Theory of Almsgiving” and the “Poor Law,” to his in-

  troduction to the English translation of Aschrott’s book on The English

  Poor Law System, a work that he much admired. After reviewing the

  French system, with its dependence on private charity, he sums up

  the English system and introduces a comparison to the German one.

  The English system

  secures adequate sustenance from public funds to all persons who are in complete

  destitution, while it aims at minimising the encouragement thus offered to idleness

  and unthrift by attaching unattractive – though not physically painful – conditions

  to the public relief given to ordinary adult paupers. Practically, it succeeds better as regards industry than thrift. So far as able-bodied men are concerned, experience

  has shown that the required combination of unattractiveness with sufficiency of

  provision for physical needs is attainable by insisting that the recipient of relief

  shall submit to the constraints of a ‘workhouse.’ But the system has hitherto failed

  to bring about the general provision against old age, which – for the most part –

  might be made without difficulty even by unskilled labourers in the period of early

  manhood, if they were content to defer marriage for a moderate term of years.

  Further, it would be unpractically severe to insist on the condition of entering

  the workhouse in the temporary disablement of breadwinners through sickness or

  accident; while to dispense with it even in these cases involves a serious discour-

  agement to providence. These evils are avoided by the German method – so far

  as can be applied – of compulsory insurance against sickness, accidental disable-

  ment, chronic infirmity, and old age. This method, it may be observed, involves

  governmental interference, which is in one aspect greater than that entailed by

  P: IJD

  cA.xml

  CY/Schultz

  

  February , 

 

‹ Prev