Book Read Free

Henry Sidgwick- Eye of the Universe

Page 121

by Bart Schultz


  opinion he remains true in , regarding the Socialistic drift of the last

  twenty years as a lamentable temporary divergence from the true and main

  movement of political thought and fact.” Moreover, against any too-ready

  acceptance concerning the drift toward secularism, Sidgwick rhetorically

  asks whether it is “not a historical commonplace that the tendency towards

  a practically secular view of human life has rarely been more marked than

  it was in the educated class – including the clergy of the most civilised

  country in Europe – in the age that preceded Luther?” (MEA )

  The point, Sidgwick explains, is that “prophecies, based on analogous

  historic cases” are always “very imperfect,” and though the history of

  civilization is a history of change that is usually gradual, the change is

  “still sufficiently rapid to establish profound differences between any two

  stages separated by a considerable interval of time.” These doubts and

  cautionaries – quintessential Sidgwick – lead him back to the question of

  whether we have any real knowledge of the “fundamental laws of social

  evolution as a whole,” since “only a positive answer to this question can

  justify us in confidently forecasting the future of society for any consider-

  able way ahead.” And of course, Pearson’s claims had rested on precisely

  this argument, to the effect that it was often easier to forecast the big de-

  velopments of social evolution than the nearer and more specific future.

  “Fortunately,” Sidgwick argues, concerning whether there really is any

  science of social dynamics worthy of the name, “there is a simple criterion

  of the effective establishment of a science – laid down by the original and

  powerful thinker who must certainly be regarded as the founder of the

  science of society, if there is such a science – the test of Consensus of

  experts and Continuity of scientific work.” This criterion, derived from

  Comte, shows “that the social science is not yet effectively constructed –

  at least so far as the department of ‘social dynamics’ is concerned – since

  it is certain that every writer on the subject starts de novo and builds on

  his own foundation.” (MEA )

  Curiously, amazingly, Sidgwick does not directly address Pearson’s

  racialist claims. One could read his review without appreciating what

  Pearson’s fundamental worry actually was. Yet, with what were apparently

  Pearson’s most firmly grounded claims now skilfully undercut, the reader

  is left to imagine the havoc that Sidgwick’s considerations could make

  with them. And what Sidgwick does do is to delicately divert attention

  to a work on Social Evolution by Benjamin Kidd, which serves as the ob-

  ject of a thoroughly effective, highly sarcastic assault on the mingling of

  P: IJD

  cB.xml

  CY/Schultz

  

  February , 

  :

  

  Henry Sidgwick: Eye of the Universe

  biology and sociology. In fact, Kidd comes off as the kind of singularly

  moronic camp follower of social Darwinism that the Spencers and Comtes

  had left in their wake. Kidd is like a youthful student of history who gets

  carried away by – infatuated with – vast generalizations, generalizations

  that more mature study would end up loading “with qualifications and

  reserves.” When it comes to the

  general moral superiority of the Anglo-Saxon in his dealings with inferior races –

  I think that any Anglo-Saxon who will study with strict impartiality the ‘wretched

  details of ferocity and treachery which have marked the conduct of civilised men

  in their relations with savages,’ is not likely to rise from the study thanking heaven that he is not a Frenchman or a Spaniard; but rather with a humble hope that the

  page of history recording these details is now turned for West-European nations

  generally, and that the future historian of the Europeanisation of Africa will have

  a different tale to tell. (MEA –)

  And the inevitable conclusion is, of course: “Scientific prevision of this

  kind will perhaps be ultimately attained, as the slow fruit of long years of

  labour yet to come; – but even that is one of the things which it would be

  rash confidently to predict.”

  Yet it is very difficult to know just what to make of this piece. Why did

  Sidgwick avoid all mention of race? More Brycean prudence? Another

  Mauricean dodge? After all, if Sidgwick casts aspersions on the supposed

  moral superiority of Anglo-Saxons, he nonetheless still assumes that they

  are dealing with “inferior races.” If he hopes that the Europeanization

  of Africa will not be a repeat of the Europeanization of, say, America,

  he nonetheless accepts the legitimacy of the Europeanization of Africa.

  Against Pearson, or other segregationists, Sidgwick would quite clearly

  insist on affording the “inferior races” every opportunity to “prove” them-

  selves, particularly via education. But they would still be proving them-

  selves, and the education would still be that designed by Sidgwick and

  his colleagues. This is at the least highly Eurocentric, and quite possi-

  bly racist. And if Bryce could contemplate the possibility of permanent

  segregation in the United States, and Pearson do likewise with respect to

  Australia, both of them duly impressing Sidgwick with their work, how

  candid could the Elements have been, in stating that exclusion from the

  franchise on grounds of race was a question for political societies “neces-

  sarily different from that which has been generally contemplated in the

  discussions of the present treatise”?

  P: IJD

  cB.xml

  CY/Schultz

  

  February , 

  :

  Colors

  

  For despite his doubts, how could Sidgwick have said what he said,

  without being all-too-impressed by Pearson’s quasi-Nietszchean perfec-

  tionist remnant and Balfour’s racial progressivism and brutal attitudes? Is

  this not simply another facet – or possible facet – of the much-sought-after,

  reinvigorating new religion?

  A fundamental question remains, however. It is very far from plain that

  these different figures actually held anything even faintly resembling a co-

  herent biological notion of race, or even the same one, however confused.

  Balfour’s notion of race, for instance, was an odd mix of Lamarckian spec-

  ulation and ethnic bigotry, linked to a virtually mystical notion of national

  character. And Bryce, in his  Romanes Lecture on “The Relations of

  the Advanced and Backward Races of Mankind,” at least admitted that

  “[a]ll the great peoples of the world are the result of a mixing of races”

  and allowed that some “of the races now deemed backward may show a

  capacity for intellectual and moral progress greater than they have been

  credited with. The differences between them and the a
dvanced races lie

  not so much in intelligence as in force of will and tenacity of purpose.”

  True, he again seemed to envision the possible advisability of permanent

  segregation in some cases, and to view race repulsion as virtually inerad-

  icable. Upon revisiting the United States in later years, however, he was

  led to produce an additional chapter, “Further Reflections on the Negro

  Problem,” in which his old views were further moderated. Now, he held

  that the progress of blacks was indisputable, and if there was something

  to the claim that they were inefficient workers, the cause was probably

  environmental. He was much moved by DuBois’s The Souls of Black Folk,

  and he concluded by wondering, when “the sentiment of a common hu-

  manity has so grown and improved within a century as to destroy slavery

  everywhere, may it not be that a like sentiment will soften the bitterness

  of race friction also?”

  Consider in this context a most illuminating letter from Dicey to Bryce,

  dated Christmas , which conveys in short compass a keen sense of the

  shifting utilitarian perspective on race:

  Your subject for the Romanes Lectures which I am delighted to hear you are going

  to deliver is an excellent one. “The Contest Between Civilized and Uncivilized

  Races” is perhaps the most important of the time and will become more and

  more important as the century goes on and happily as yet it has not become a

  party question. Accidental circumstances have recently called my attention to it.

  P: IJD

  cB.xml

  CY/Schultz

  

  February , 

  :

  

  Henry Sidgwick: Eye of the Universe

  There is a terrible danger that, as we cannot talk of human equality with the same

  confidence with which the best men of the th and the earlier th century spoke

  of it, and as we are compelled to attach more importance than they did to race, we

  may come to give up faith in the truth, of which I think they had a firm hold, that

  the qualities which races have in common are at least as important as (I should

  say more important than) the characteristics in which they differ. Then the whole

  matter is complicated to my mind by the growth of an idea, which I think may

  be true that the races with different ideals and different moralities had best live

  apart. I cannot myself feel at all sure that the cry for a “White Australia” is not

  at bottom a sound one. But all I want at present to urge is the great advantage of

  your taking up this topic and dealing with it in your lecture.

  Dicey, the old Benthamite, here regretfully insists on the increasing im-

  portance of race as a political issue, expressing some doubts as to whether

  Pearson might not be right about keeping Australia white. But this comes

  as part of a congratulatory message to Bryce for his willingness to tackle

  head-on a baffling subject that needs thinking through, made the more

  poignant by the manifest confusion of race with something closer to ethnic

  identity.

  Perhaps something akin to these Diceyan and Brycean notes are im-

  portant for considering Sidgwick, marking as they do the slightly more

  moderate, slightly more agnostic attitude amid a veritable sea of grotesque

  prejudice. Indeed, Sidgwick goes well beyond all these figures in keeping

  matters of race far in the background, and this may well have been, not

  only the retreat to the private sphere described by Hobsbawm, but also, at

  least in part, that characteristic Sidgwickian silence when doubtful. If his

  doubts did not end up effectively neutralizing his racist presuppositions,

  they at least moderated them somewhat.

  The most straightforward comments that Sidgwick makes on the sub-

  ject would seem to support this reading. Thus, crucially, The Development

  of European Polity does not contain any specific projections about race to

  speak of, though surely this is where Sidgwick would have put them, out

  of all his major works. He does discuss the future of federation, with an

  eye to Home Rule, explaining how in Croatia

  there has been since  a separate Parliament which legislates on a part of those

  matters that are not regarded as common to the whole of the territories of the Hungarian Crown, the rest of such matters being legislated on in the Hungarian

  Parliament at Buda Pest, to which Croatia sends deputies; the Croatian deputies

  P: IJD

  cB.xml

  CY/Schultz

  

  February , 

  :

  Colors

  

  voting in the Hungarian Parliament not on all matters, but only on such matters

  as are not legislated on separately in the Croatian Parliament. (DEP )

  There is much disputing with Maine over the evolution of patriarchy,

  custom, and law in ancient Greece and Rome, but China, India, Africa,

  and even Australia are nearly absent even as counterpoints. There is the

  stock point – “competent judges hold that it might have prevented serious

  mistakes in our government of India, if the governing statesmen had had

  before their minds the historical development of land-tenure, as we now

  conceive it to have taken place in European countries” – which Sidgwick

  repeated in a half-dozen different works to illustrate how the past might

  afford “instructive analogies.” But there is little effort to demonstrate any

  serious familiarity with non-European states or any serious reliance on

  the concept of race, after the manner of Pearson. The reason for this is

  embedded in the very structure of the book. As Sidgwick explains in his

  opening chapter, he is going to confine his attention “mainly to the political

  institutions of the ancient Greeks and Romans, and of Western Europe

  and its colonies in post-Roman times.” Thus,

  Though there are societies – groups of gregarious men – in which the ‘differenti-

  ation’ into governors and governed is barely perceptible, such societies constitute

  a very insignificant portion of humanity: it is almost universally true that a man

  is a ‘political animal’ in the sense of being either ruler or ruled, either obeying or constituting a government of some kind. But there is a sense in which higher political development has originated almost exclusively in, and is still mainly confined

  to certain portions of the white, or – as some still call it – Causcasian race. They

  alone have developed, along with the development of their civilisation, governing

  organs of which the members are accustomed ‘to rule and obey alternately’ –

  whether () the supreme ruler is merely elected by the citizens for a limited time,

  and then gives up power and may be formally called to account for his exercise of

  it, or () the supreme rule is in whole or in part exercised collectively by a body

  of citizens meeting from time to time.

  In the history of political institutions these forms interest us most, not only as

  citizens of a modern West-European State, but as students of P
olitical Science:

  just as the highest forms of life have a special interest for the biologist. I shall

  accordingly confine my attention mainly to the nations who have shown a power

  of developing them. And among them the most important and conspicuous of

  those whose history is known to us are certainly the Greeks, Romans, and West-

  Europeans. They stand pre-eminent among the civilised portions of humanity as

  having developed, up to the highest point that their civilisation has yet reached, not

  P: IJD

  cB.xml

  CY/Schultz

  

  February , 

  :

  

  Henry Sidgwick: Eye of the Universe

  only political ins titutions, but constitutions and constitutional ideas and theories.

  (DEP )

  Obviously Sidgwick is here simply taking for granted the prejudices of

  his time, since he plainly knew nothing whatsoever of, say, the Iroquois

  nation or the Arapesh. Yet what is noteworthy, in addition, is that he is

  working with a fairly etiolated biology of race, comparatively speaking,

  such that few features of “national character” appear to be attributable to

  it. Development in fact gives one of Sidgwick’s clearest and most extensive

  statements on the subject:

  Some explanation is required of these notions of ‘race’ and ‘family of nations.’

  Firstly, in speaking of the ‘white race,’ I do not mean to imply that there are four

  or five original stocks of human beings, distinguishable by colour and other marks,

  as ‘white,’ ‘brown,’ ‘yellow,’ and ‘black’ races. In the present state of anthropology there is no ground for assuming any such original differences of stocks; and the

  physical differences actually existing are more numerous and complicated, and

  shade off into each other more gradually, than the popular nomenclature suggests.

  And since all varieties of human beings are zoologically of one species – inter-

  marriage between any two generally producing fertile offspring – the physical

  differences of race historically presented may be to an indefinite extent referable

  to crossing of breeds. A special instance of this is perhaps presented by the marked

  differences we find between the fair whites, prevalent in Northern Europe, and

  the dark whites prevalent in Southern Europe and parts of Asia; – as the latter

 

‹ Prev