Book Read Free

The Omnibus Homo Sacer

Page 44

by Giorgio Agamben


  maybe ironically eschatological—has become one of the paradigms of the mod-

  ern theory of the State. But it is certain that the political philosophy of moder-

  nity will not be able to emerge out of its contradictions except by becoming

  aware of its theological roots.

  Bibliography

  Agamben, Giorgio. 1998. Homo Sacer: Sovereign Power and Bare Life. Translated by Daniel Heller-Roazen. Stanford: Stanford University Press.

  Arendt, Hannah. 1963. On Revolution. New York: Viking Press.

  Aristotle. 1971. The Athenian Constitution; The Eudemian Ethics; On Virtues and Vices. Translated by H. Rackham. London: William Heinemann.

  Benjamin, Walter. 2002. ‘Theological-Political Fragment.’ Translated by Edmund Jephcott. In Selected Writings, Volume 3: 1935–1938, 305–6. Cambridge, MA: Belknap Press of Harvard University Press.

  Berns, Laurence. 1987. ‘Thomas Hobbes.’ In History of Political Philosophy, edited by Leo Strauss and Joseph Cropsey, 396–420. 3rd edn. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.

  Bertozzi, Marco. 1983. Thomas Hobbes: L’enigma del Leviatano. Ferrara: Bovolenta.

  Bramhall, John. 1977. Castigations of Mr. Hobbes 1658. New York: Garland Publishing.

  Brandt, Reinhard. 1982. ‘Das Titelblatt des Leviathan und Goyas El Gigante.’ In Furcht und Freiheit: Leviathan Diskussion 300 jahre nach Thomas Hobbes, edited by Udo Bermbach and Klaus-M. Kodalle, 203–31. Opladen: Westdeutscher Verlag.

  Bredekamp, Horst. 2003. Thomas Hobbes Der Leviathan: das Urbild des modernen Staates und seine Gegenbilder, 1651–2001. Berlin: Akademie-Verlag.

  Drewer, Lois. 1981. ‘Leviathan, Behemoth and Ziz: A Christian Adaptation.’ Journal of the Warburg and Courtauld Institutes, 44: 148–56.

  Falk, Francesca. 2011. Eine gestische Geschichte der Grenzen: wie der Liberalismus an der Grenze an seine Grenze kommt. Munich: Fink.

  Farneti, Roberto. 2002. Il canone moderno: filosofia politica e genealogia. Turin: Bollati Boringhieri.

  Hobbes, Thomas. 1680. The Life of Mr. Thomas Hobbes of Malmesbury. London.

  ———. 1843. Eight Books of the Peloponnesian War. In The English Works of Thomas Hobbes of Malmesbury, VIII, edited by Sir William Moleworth. London: John Bohn.

  ———. 1969. The Elements of Law, Natural and Politic. Edited by Ferdinand Tönnies. London: Frank Cass.

  ———. 1983. De Cive. Latin Version. Edited by Howard Warrender. Oxford: Clarendon Press.

  ———. 1996. Leviathan. Edited by Richard Tuck. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

  St Jerome. 1965. The Homilies of Saint Jerome, I: 1–59 (On the Psalms). Translated by Marie Ligouri Ewald. Washington, DC: The Catholic University of America Press.

  Jünger, Ernst and Carl Schmitt. 1999. Briefe 1930–1983. Edited by Helmuth Kiesel. Stuttgart: Klett-Cotta.

  Koselleck, Reinhart. 1988. Critique and Crisis: Enlightenment and Pathogenesis of Modern Society.

  Oxford: Berg.

  ———. 1992. ‘Volk, Nation, Nationalismus, Masse.’ In Geschichtliche Grundbegriffe: Historisches 291

  292

  HOMO SACER II, 2

  Lexikon zur politisch-sozialen Sprache in Deutschland, VII, edited by Otto Brunner, Werner Conze and Reinhart Koselleck, 141–431. Stuttgart: Klett-Cotta.

  ———. 2006. ‘Crisis.’ Translated by Michaela W. Richter. Journal of the History of Ideas, 67, 2: 357–400.

  Loraux, Nicole. 1997. ‘La guerre dans la famille.’ Clio, 5: 21–62.

  ———. 1997. La Cité divisée: l’oubli dans la mémoire de l’Athènes. Paris: Payot. Translated by Corinne Pache (with Jeff Fort) as The Divided City: On Memory and Forgetting in Ancient Athens. New York: Zone Books, 2001.

  Malcolm, Noel. 1998. ‘The Titlepage of Leviathan, Seen in a Curious Perspective.’ The Seventeenth Century, 13, 2: 124–55.

  Meier, Christian. 1979. ‘Der Wandel der politisch-sozialen Begriffswelt im 5 Jahrhundert v. Chr.’

  In Historische Semantik und Begriffsgeschichte, edited by Reinhart Koselleck, 193–227. Stuttgart: Klett-Cotta. Translated by David McLintock as ‘Changing Politicosocial Concepts in

  the Fifth Century B.C.’ In The Greek Discovery of Politics, 157–85. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 1990.

  Midrash Rabbah, Leviticus. 1961. Translated by J. Israelstam and J. Slotki. London: Soncino Press.

  Pocock, J. G. A. 1989. ‘Time, History and Eschatology in the Thought of Thomas Hobbes.’ In Politics, Language and Time: Essays on Political Thought and History, 148–201. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.

  Poesch, Jessie. 1970. ‘The Beasts from Job in the Liber Floridus manuscripts.’ Journal of the Warburg and Courtauld Institutes, 23: 41–51.

  Pufendorf, Samuel. 1934. De jure naturae et gentium libri octo. 2 vols. Oxford: Clarendon Press.

  Schmitt, Carl. 1973. Der Nomos der Erde im Völkerrecht des Jus Publicum Europaeum. Berlin: Duncker and Humblot. Translated by G. L. Ulmen as The Nomos of the Earth in the International Law of the Jus Publicum Europaeum. New York: Telos Press, 2006.

  ———. 1982. Der Leviathan in der Staatslehre des Thomas Hobbes: Sinn und Fehlschlag eines politischen Symbols. Cologne: Hohenheim. Translated by George Schwab as The Leviathan in the State Theory of Thomas Hobbes: Meaning and Failure of a Political Symbol. Westport: Greenwood Press, 1996.

  ———. 2000. ‘State Ethics and the Pluralist State.’ Translated by Belinda Cooper. In Weimar: A Jurisprudence of Crisis, edited by Arthur J. Jacobson and Bernhard Schlink, 300–12. Berkeley: University of California Press.

  ———. 2007. Theory of the Partisan: Intermediate Commentary on the Concept of the Political.

  Translated by G. L. Ulmen. New York: Telos Press.

  Schnur, Roman. 1986. Revolution und Weltbürgerkrieg: Studien zur Ouverture nach 1789. Berlin: Duncker and Humblot.

  Sièyes, Emmanuel-Joseph. 1970. Qu’est-ce que le Tiers état? Edited by Roberto Zapperi. Geneva: Librairie Droz.

  Snow, Donald M. 1996. Uncivil Wars: International Security and the New Internal Conflicts. Boul-der: Lynne Rienner.

  Strack, Hermann L. and Paul Billerbeck. 1928. Kommentar zum Neuen Testament aus Talmud und Midrasch, IV, 2: Exkurse zu einzelnen Stellen des Neuen Testaments. Munich: Beck.

  Vernant, Jean-Pierre. 1988. Myth and Society in Ancient Greece. Translated by Janet Lloyd. New York: Zone Books.

  The Vulgate Bible: Douay-Rheims Translation, Volume III: The Poetical Books. 2011. Edited by Swift Edgar and Angela M. Kinney. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.

  Willms, Bernard. 1970. Die Antwort des Leviathan: Thomas Hobbes’ politische Theorie. Neuwied: Luchterhand.

  This page intentionally left blank

  HOMO SACER II, 3

  THE SACRAMENT

  OF LANGUAGE

  An Archaeology

  of the Oath

  TRANSLATED BY DANIEL ADAM KOTSKO

  Contents

  Translator’s Note

  299

  Abbreviations

  300

  The Sacrament of Language

  301

  Bibliography

  357

  Von diesen Vorgängenen meldet kein Zeuge; sie zu verstehn bietet unser

  eignes Bewusstsein keinen Anhalt. Nur eine Urkunde ist uns von ihnen

  geblieben, so schweigsam dem unkundigen, wie beredt dem kundigen: die

  Sprache.

  (No witness reports these events; our own consciousness offers no grounds to

  understand them. Only one document is left to us by them, as silent to the

  ignorant as it is eloquent to the experienced: language.)

  —Hermann Usener

  Der Schematismus der Verstandesbegriffe ist . . . ein Augenblick in welchem

  Metaphysik und Physik beide Ufer zugleich berühren Styx interfusa.

  (The schematism of the concepts of the intellect . . . is an instant in which the

  shores of metaphysics and physics make contact St
yx interfusa.)

  —Immanuel Kant

  Translator’s Note

  The translator would like to thank Giorgio Agamben, Kevin Attell, Daniel Coluc-

  ciello Barber, Joshua Furnal, Ted Jennings, and Virgil Brower for their suggested

  improvements; Nunzio N. D’Alessio, Dennis Hou, Evan Kuehn, Craig McFarlane,

  and Yotam Pappo for bibliographical assistance; and Emily-Jane Cohen, Sarah

  Crane Newman, and the rest of the staff of Stanford University Press.

  Existing English translations have been used wherever possible, though

  sometimes altered to reflect the translation provided by the author; citations

  of modern texts where a translation is available have the original page numbers

  followed by the English edition cited, while premodern texts are cited according

  to standard textual divisions. All biblical quotations are taken from the New

  Revised Standard Version. All other translations are my own, carried out in con-

  sultation with the author’s translations.

  299

  Abbreviations

  Aen.

  Aeneid (Virgil)

  Ann.

  Annales (Tacitus)

  Apol.

  Apologeticus (Tertullian)

  Cra.

  Cratylus (Plato)

  Mens.

  De mensibus (Lydus)

  Il.

  The Iliad (Homer)

  Inst.

  Institutiones (Gaius)

  Metaph. Metaphysics (Aristotle)

  Od.

  The Odyssey (Homer)

  PL

  Patrologia Latina ( J.-P. Migne, ed.)

  Pyth.

  Pythian Odes (Pindar)

  Rep.

  Republic (Plato)

  Theog.

  Theogonia (Hesiod)

  Tib.

  Life of Tiberius (Suetonius)

  Verr.

  The First Oration Against Verres (Cicero)

  300

  The Sacrament of Language

  1. In 1992 Paolo Prodi’s book Il sacramento del potere (The Sacrament of

  Power) forcefully called attention to the decisive importance of the oath

  in the political history of the West. Situated at the intersection of religion and

  politics, the oath not only testifies to that “dual belonging” (Prodi, 522) that

  defines, according to the author, the specificity and vitality of Western Chris-

  tian culture. It is also, in fact—and this is the diagnosis from which his book

  begins—the “basis of the political pact in the history of the West” (ibid., 11).

  As such, it is possible to find the oath in an eminent role every time this pact

  enters into crisis or turns to renew itself in diverse forms, from the beginning

  of Christianity to the War of Investiture, from the “commune” (“sworn associa-

  tion”) of the late Middle Ages to the formation of the modern State. In keeping

  with its central function, the irreversible decline of the oath in our time can only

  correspond, according to Prodi, to a “crisis in which the very being of man as

  a political animal is at stake” (ibid.). If we are today “the first generations who,

  notwithstanding the presence of some forms and liturgies from the past . . . , live

  our own collective life without the oath as a solemn and total, sacredly anchored

  bond to a political body,” this means, then, that we find ourselves, without being

  conscious of it, on the threshold of “a new form of political association” (ibid.),

  whose reality and meaning we have yet to recognize.

  As is implicit in its subtitle, Il giuramento politico nella storia costituzionale

  dell’Occidente (The Political Oath in the Constitutional History of the West),

  Prodi’s book is a historical study, and, as must happen in such studies, the author

  does not pose for himself the problem of what he defines as the “ a-historical and

  immobile nucleus of the oath-event” (ibid., 22). The definition “from the an-

  thropological point of view,” which is summarily indicated in the introduction,

  thus repeats certain commonplaces drawn from the investigations of historians

  of law, historians of religion, and linguists. As often happens when a phenome-

  non or institution is positioned at the crossroads of diverse territories and disci-

  plines, none of them can lay claim to it entirely on their own, and the attempt

  301

  302

  HOMO SACER II, 3

  at synthesis, which gestures toward its complexity, origin, and overall relevance,

  falters before the often imposing mass of particular studies. Since, however, an

  eclectic compendium of the results of individual disciplines does not seem scien-

  tifically reliable and the model of a “general science of man” has been out of favor

  for some time now, the present study proposes to undertake not an investigation

  into the oath’s origin but rather a philosophical archaeology of the oath.

  Bringing together the stakes of a historical investigation like Prodi’s—which,

  like every true historical study, cannot fail to call the present into question—and

  the results of research into linguistics, the history of law, and religion, the issue

  here, above all, is the question, What is an oath? What is at stake in it, if it de-

  fines and calls into question man himself as a political animal? If the oath is the

  sacrament of political power, what is it in its structure and its history that has

  made it possible for it to be invested with such a function? What anthropolog-

  ical level—a decisive one in every sense—is implicated in it, so that all of man,

  in life and death, can be called to account in it and by it?

  2. The essential function of the oath in the political constitution is clearly ex-

  pressed in the passage from Lycurgus’s Against Leocrates that Prodi uses as an epigraph: “The power that holds together [ to synechon] our democracy is the oath”

  (Lycurgus, 79). Prodi could have cited another passage, from the Neo platonic

  philosopher Hierocles, who, at the twilight of Hellenism, seems to confirm this

  centrality of the oath by making it the principle that completes the Law: “We

  have previously shown that the law [ nomos] is the always uniform operation by

  means of which God eternally and immutably leads everything to existence.

  Now we call oath [ horkos] that which, following this law, conserves [ diatērousan]

  all things in the same state and renders them stable in such a way that, as they

  are held in the guarantee of the oath and maintain the order of the law, the im-

  mutable stability of the order of creation is the completion of the creating law”

  (Hirzel, 74; see also Aujoulat, 109–10).

  It is necessary to pay attention to the words that express the function of

  the oath in the two passages. In both Lycurgus and Hierocles the oath does not

  create anything, does not bring anything into being, but keeps united [ synechō]

  and conserves [ diatēreō] what something else (in Hierocles, the law; in Lycurgus,

  the citizens or the legislator) has brought into being.

  An analogous function seems to be assigned to the oath by what Prodi con-

  siders the fundamental text concerning this institution that has come down to

  us from Roman juridical culture, namely, the passage from De officiis (3.29.10)

  in which Cicero defines the oath thus:

  THE SACRAMENT OF LANGUAGE

  303

  Sed in iure iurando n
on qui metus sed quae vis sit, debet intellegi; est enim iu-

  siurandum affirmatio religiosa; quod autem affirmate quasi deo teste promiseris

  id tenendum est. Iam enim non ad iram deorum quae nulla est, sed ad iustitiam

  et ad fidem pertinet.

  [But in taking an oath it is our duty to consider not what one may have to fear

  in case of violation but wherein its obligation lies: an oath is an assurance backed

  by religious sanctity; and a solemn promise given, as before God as one’s witness,

  is to be sacredly kept. For the question no longer concerns the wrath of the gods

  (for there is no such thing) but the obligations of justice and good faith.]

  Affirmatio does not signify simply a linguistic utterance but what confirms and

  guarantees. (The phrase that follows, “affirmate . . . promiseris,” does nothing

  but reaffirm the same idea: “That which you have promised in the solemn and

  confirmed form of the oath.”) And it is this function of stability and guarantee

  that Cicero draws attention to, writing at the beginning, “In the sacrament it is

  important to consider not so much the danger that it generates, but its own effi-

  cacy [ vis]”; and the answer to the question of what this vis consists in appears unequivocally in the etymological definition of the fides that, according to Cicero, is at stake in the oath: quia fiat quod dictum est appelatam fidem (“good faith

  [ fidem]” is so called because what is promised is “made good [ fiat]” [ibid., 1.23]).

  It is with this specific vis in mind that one must reread the words with which

  Émile Benveniste, at the beginning of his 1948 article “L’expression du serment

  dans la Grèce ancienne” (The Expression of the Oath in Ancient Greece), de-

  fined its function:

  [The oath] is a particular modality of assertion, which supports, guarantees, and

  demonstrates, but does not found anything. Individual or collective, the oath

  exists only by virtue of that which it reinforces and renders solemn: a pact, an

  agreement, a declaration. It prepares for or concludes a speech act which alone

  possesses meaningful content, but it expresses nothing by itself. It is in truth an

 

‹ Prev