Book Read Free

The Omnibus Homo Sacer

Page 123

by Giorgio Agamben


  their body is already in decay, and nothing can save them from selections or

  from death by exhaustion. Their life is short, but their number is endless; they,

  the Muselmänner, the drowned, form the backbone of the camp, an anonymous mass, continually renewed and always identical, of non-men who march and

  labour in silence, the divine spark dead in them, already too empty to really suffer.

  One hesitates to call them living: one hesitates to call their death death, in the

  face of which they have no fear, as they are too tired to understand.

  They crowd my memory with their faceless presence, and if I could enclose

  all the evil of our time in one image, I would choose this image which is familiar

  to me: an emaciated man, with head dropped and shoulders curved, on whose

  face and in whose eyes not a trace of thought is to be seen. (Levi 1986: 90)

  2.2. There is little agreement on the origin of the term Muselmann. As is often

  the case with jargon, the term is not lacking in synonyms. “The expression was

  in common use especially in Auschwitz, from where it spread to other camps as

  well. . . . In Majdanek, the word was unknown. The living dead there were termed

  ‘donkeys’; in Dachau they were ‘cretins,’ in Stutthof ‘cripples,’ in Mauthausen

  ‘swimmers,’ in Neuengamme ‘camels,’ in Buchenwald ‘tired sheikhs,’ and in

  the women’s camp known as Ravensbruck, Muselweiber (female Muslims) or

  ‘ trinkets’”(Sofsky 1997: 329n5).

  The most likely explanation of the term can be found in the literal meaning

  of the Arabic word muslim: the one who submits unconditionally to the will of

  God. It is this meaning that lies at the origin of the legends concerning Islam’s

  supposed fatalism, legends which are found in European culture starting with

  the Middle Ages (this deprecatory sense of the term is present in European lan-

  guages, particularly in Italian). But while the muslim’s resignation consists in the

  conviction that the will of Allah is at work every moment and in even the small-

  est events, the Muselmann of Auschwitz is instead defined by a loss of all will and consciousness. Hence Kogon’s statement that in the camps, the “relatively large

  group of men who had long since lost any real will to survive . . . were called

  ‘Moslems’—men of unconditional fatalism” (Kogon 1979: 284).

  There are other, less convincing explanations. One example appears in the

  Encyclopedia Judaica under the entry Muselmann: “Used mainly at Auschwitz, the term appears to derive from the typical attitude of certain deportees, that

  is, staying crouched on the ground, legs bent in Oriental fashion, faces rigid as

  masks.” Another explanation is suggested by Marsalek, who associates “the typ-

  ical movements of Muselmänner, the swaying motions of the upper part of the body, with Islamic prayer rituals” (Sofsky 1997: 329n5). There is also the rather

  REMNANTS OF AUSCHWITZ

  791

  improbable interpretation of Muselmann as Muschelmann, “shell-man,” a man folded and closed upon himself (Levi seems to allude to this interpretation when

  he writes of “husk-men”).

  In any case, it is certain that, with a kind of ferocious irony, the Jews knew

  that they would not die at Auschwitz as Jews.

  2.3. This disagreement concerning the etymology of the term Muselmann

  has as its precise counterpart an uncertainty as to the semantic and disciplinary

  field in which the term should be situated. It is not surprising that the physi-

  cian Fejkiel, who worked for a long time in the concentration camps, tended

  to treat the Muselmann as a medical case, beset with a particular malnutritional

  disorder endemic to the camps. To a certain degree, it was Bruno Bettelheim

  who first considered this issue, when in 1943 he published his essay “Individual

  and Mass Behavior in Extreme Situations” in the Journal of Abnormal and Social

  Psychology. In 1938–39, before being liberated, Bettelheim spent a year in Dachau and Buchenwald, which at the time were the two largest Nazi concentration

  camps for political prisoners. Though the living conditions of the camps during

  those years cannot be compared to Auschwitz, Bettelheim had seen Muselmänner

  with his own eyes, and immediately recognized the novel transformations that

  “extreme situations” produced in the personalities of camp prisoners. For him,

  the Muselmann became the paradigm through which he conceived his study

  of childhood schizophrenia, written years after he immigrated to the United

  States. The Orthogenic School, which he founded in Chicago to treat autistic

  children, thus had the form of a kind of counter-camp, in which he undertook

  to teach Muselmänner to become men again. There is not one character trait

  in Bettelheim’s detailed phenomenology of childhood autism described in The

  Empty Fortress that does not have its dark precursor and interpretative paradigm

  in the behavior of the Muselmann. “What was external reality for the prisoner

  is for the autistic child his inner reality. Each ends up, though for different

  reasons, with a parallel experience of the world” (Bettelheim 1967: 65). Just as

  autistic children totally ignored reality in order to retreat into an imaginary

  world, so the prisoners who became Muselmänner substituted delirious fantasies

  for the relations of causality to which they no longer paid any attention. In the

  semicross-eyed gaze, hesitant walk, and stubborn repetitiveness and silence of

  Joey, Marcie, Laurie, and the other children of the school, Bettelheim sought a

  possible solution to the enigma that the Muselmann had confronted him with at

  Dachau. Nevertheless, for Bettelheim, the concept of “extreme situation” con-

  tinued to imply a moral and political connotation; for him, the Muselmann

  792

  HOMO SACER III

  could never be reduced to a clinical category. Because what was at stake in the

  extreme situation was “to remain alive and unchanged as a person” (Bettelheim

  1960: 158), the Muselmann in some sense marked the moving threshold in which

  man passed into non-man and in which clinical diagnosis passed into anthro-

  pological analysis.

  As for Levi, whose first testimony was a “Report on the Hygenic and San-

  itary Organization of the Monowitz (Auschwitz, High Silesia) Concentration

  Camp for Jews,” written in 1946 at the request of the Soviet authorities, the

  nature of the experience to which he was called to bear witness was never in

  question. “Actually, what interests me is the dignity and lack of dignity of man,”

  he declared in 1986 to Barbara Kleiner, with a sense of irony that probably went

  unnoticed by his interviewer (Levi 1997: 78). The new ethical material that he

  discovered at Auschwitz allowed for neither summary judgments nor distinc-

  tions and, whether he liked it or not, lack of dignity had to interest him as

  much as dignity. As suggested by the ironically rhetorical Italian title Se questo è

  un uomo (literally “If This Is a Man,” translated as Survival in Auschwitz in English), in Auschwitz ethics begins precisely at the point where the Muselmann,

  the “complete witness,” makes it forever impossible to distinguish between man

  and non-man.

  An explicit political meaning has also been attributed to the extreme thresh-

  old be
tween life and death, the human and the inhuman, that the Muselmann

  inhabits:

  The Muselmann embodies the anthropological meaning of absolute power in an

  especially radical form. Power abrogates itself in the act of killing. The death of the

  other puts an end to the social relationship. But by starving the other, it gains time.

  It erects a third realm, a limbo between life and death. Like the pile of corpses,

  the Muselmänner document the total triumph of power over the human being.

  Although still nominally alive, they are nameless hulks. In the configuration of

  their infirmity, as in organized mass murder, the regime realizes its quintessential

  self. (Sofsky 1997: 294)

  At times a medical figure or an ethical category, at times a political limit or

  an anthropological concept, the Muselmann is an indefinite being in whom not

  only humanity and non-humanity, but also vegetative existence and relation,

  physiology and ethics, medicine and politics, and life and death continuously

  pass through each other. This is why the Muselmann’ s “third realm” is the perfect cipher of the camp, the non-place in which all disciplinary barriers are destroyed

  and all embankments flooded.

  REMNANTS OF AUSCHWITZ

  793

  2.4. Recently, philosophers and theologians alike have invoked the paradigm

  of the “extreme situation” or “limit situation.” The function of this paradigm is

  analogous to the function ascribed by some jurists to the state of exception. Just

  as the state of exception allows for the foundation and definition of the normal

  legal order, so in the light of the extreme situation—which is, at bottom, a

  kind of exception—it is possible to judge and decide on the normal situation.

  As Kierkegaard writes, “the exception explains the general as well as itself. And

  when one really wants to study the general, one need only look around for a real

  exception.” In Bettelheim, the camp, as the exemplary extreme situation, thus

  allows for the determination of what is inhuman and human and, in this way,

  for the separation of the Muselmann from the human being.

  Referring to the concept of the limit situation and, in particular, to the expe-

  rience of the Second World War, Karl Barth justly observed that human beings

  have the striking capacity to adapt so well to an extreme situation that it can no

  longer function as a distinguishing criterion. “According to the present trend,”

  he wrote in 1948,

  we may suppose that even on the morning after the Day of Judgment—if such

  a thing were possible—every cabaret, every night club, every newspaper firm

  eager for advertisements and subscribers, every nest of political fanatics, every

  discussion group, indeed, every Christian tea-party and Church synod would

  resume business to the best of its ability, and with a new sense of opportunity,

  completely unmoved, quite uninstructed, and in no serious sense different from

  what it was before. Fire, drought, earthquake, war, pestilence, the darkening of

  the sun and similar phenomena are not the things to plunge us into real anguish,

  and therefore to give us real peace. “The Lord was not in the storm, the earthquake

  or the fire” (1 Kings 19: 11 ff.). He really was not. (Barth 1960: 115)

  All the witnesses, even those submitted to the most extreme conditions (for

  example, the members of the Sonderkommando), recall the incredible tendency of the limit situation to become habit (“doing this work, one either goes crazy

  the first day or gets used to it”). The Nazis so well understood this secret power

  inherent in every limit situation that they never revoked the state of exception

  declared in February 1933, upon their rise to power. In this sense, the Third Reich

  has been aptly defined as a “Night of St. Bartholomew that lasted twelve years.”

  Auschwitz is precisely the place in which the state of exception coincides

  perfectly with the rule and the extreme situation becomes the very paradigm of

  daily life. But it is this paradoxical tendency of the limit situation to turn over

  into its opposite that makes it interesting. As long as the state of exception and

  the normal situation are kept separate in space and time, as is usually the case,

  794

  HOMO SACER III

  both remain opaque, though they secretly institute each other. But as soon as

  they show their complicity, as happens more and more often today, they illumi-

  nate each other, so to speak, from the inside. And yet this implies that the ex-

  treme situation can no longer function as a distinguishing criterion, as it did for

  Bettelheim; it implies that the extreme situation’s lesson is rather that of absolute

  immanence, of “everything being in everything.” In this sense, philosophy can

  be defined as the world seen from an extreme situation that has become the rule

  (according to some philosophers, the name of this extreme situation is “God”).

  2.5. Aldo Carpi, professor of painting at the Academy of Brera, was deported

  to Gusen in February 1944, where he remained until May 1945. He managed to

  survive because the SS began to commission paintings and drawings from him

  once they discovered his profession. They mostly commissioned family portraits,

  which Carpi produced from photographs; but there were also requests for Italian

  landscapes and “Venetian nudes,” which Carpi painted from memory. Carpi was

  not a realistic painter, and yet one can understand why he wanted to paint the

  actual scenes and figures from the camp. But his commissioners had absolutely

  no interest in such things; indeed, they did not even tolerate the sight of them.

  “No one wants camp scenes and figures,” Carpi notes in his diary, “no one wants

  to see the Muselmann” (Carpi 1993: 33).

  Other witnesses confirm this impossibility of gazing upon the Muselmann.

  One account is particularly eloquent, even if it is indirect. A few years ago,

  the English film shot in Bergen-Belsen immediately after the camp’s liberation

  in 1945 was made available to the public. It is difficult to bear the sight of the

  thousands of naked corpses piled in common graves or carried on the shoulders

  of former camp guards, of those tortured bodies that even the SS could not

  name (we know from witnesses that under no circumstances were they to be

  called “corpses” or “cadavers,” but rather simply Figuren, figures, dolls). And yet since the Allies intended to use this footage as proof of Nazi atrocities and make

  it public in Germany, we are spared no detail of the terrible spectacle. At one

  point, however, the camera lingers almost by accident on what seem to be living

  people, a group of prisoners crouched on the ground or wandering on foot like

  ghosts. It lasts only a few seconds, but it is still long enough for the spectator

  to realize that they are either Muselmänner who have survived by some miracle

  or, at least, prisoners very close to the state of Muselmänner. With the exception of Carpi’s drawings, which he did from memory, this is perhaps the sole

  image of Muselmänner we have. Nevertheless, the same cameraman who had

  until then patiently lingered over naked bodies, over the terrible “dolls” dis-

  REMNANTS OF AUSCHWITZ

  795

  membered and stacked one on top of another, could not be
ar the sight of these

  half-living beings; he immediately began once again to show the cadavers. As

  Elias Canetti has noted, a heap of dead bodies is an ancient spectacle, one which

  has often satisfied the powerful. But the sight of Muselmänner is an absolutely

  new phenomenon, unbearable to human eyes.

  2.6. What no one wants to see at any cost, however, is the “core” of the

  camp, the fatal threshold that all prisoners are constantly about to cross. “The

  Muselmann stage was the great fear of the prisoners, since not one of them knew

  when his fate would become that of the Muslim, the sure candidate for the gas

  chambers or another kind of death” (Langbein 1972: 113).

  The space of the camp (at least of those camps, like Auschwitz, in which

  concentration camp and extermination camp coincide) can even be represented

  as a series of concentric circles that, like waves, incessantly wash up against a

  central non-place, where the Muselmann lives. In camp jargon, the extreme limit

  of this non-place is called Selektion, the selection procedure for the gas chamber.

  This is why the prisoner’s most pressing concern was to hide his sickness and his

  exhaustion, to constantly cover over the Muselmann who at every moment was

  emerging in him. The entire population of the camp is, indeed, nothing other

  than an immense whirlpool obsessively spinning around a faceless center. But

  like the mystical rose of Dante’s Paradiso, this anonymous vortex is “painted in our image” ( pinta della nostra effige); it bears the true likeness of man. According to the law that what man despises is also what he fears resembles him, the Muselmann is universally avoided because everyone in the camp recognizes himself in

  his disfigured face.

  It is a striking fact that although all witnesses speak of him as a central experi-

  ence, the Muselmann is barely named in the historical studies on the destruction

  of European Jewry. Perhaps only now, almost fifty years later, is the Muselmann

  becoming visible; perhaps only now may we draw the consequences of this vis-

  ibility. For this visibility implies that the paradigm of extermination, which has

  until now exclusively oriented interpretations of the concentration camp, is not

  replaced by, but rather accompanied by, another paradigm, a paradigm that casts

 

‹ Prev