Book Read Free

The Omnibus Homo Sacer

Page 163

by Giorgio Agamben


  seeks to define the meaning of chresthai, with considerations not very different

  from what we have already seen in connection with Redard’s mémoire.

  Of course, chraomai means: I use, I utilize (an instrument, a tool). But equally

  chraomai may designate my behavior or my attitude. For example, in the ex-

  pression ubrikhos chresthai, the meaning is: behaving violently (as when we say,

  “using violence,” when “using” does not mean utilizing, but rather behaving

  violently). So chraomai is also a certain attitude. Chresthai also designates a certain type of relationship with other people. When one says, for example, theois

  chresthai (using the gods), this does not mean that one utilizes the gods for any

  end whatever. It means having appropriate and legitimate relationships with the

  gods. . . . Chraomai, chresthai also designate a certain attitude towards oneself.

  In the expression epithumiais chresthai, the meaning is not “to use one’s passions for something” but quite simply “to give way to one’s passions.” (Foucault 1,

  pp. 55–56/56)

  1056

  THE USE OF BODIES

  1057

  The insistence on the specification of the semantic sphere of chresthai is not by

  chance. According to Foucault, in fact, this verb develops a strategic function in

  Plato’s argumentation, insofar as Socrates makes use of it to respond to the ques-

  tion of what this “oneself” is that is the object of care-of-oneself (“in what way

  will it be possible to find the self itself”— auto tauto, a technical formula for the expression of the idea: the “itself in itself”; 129b). By concentrating his examples

  on the verb chresthai, that is to say, Plato intends to suggest that taking care of the self means, in reality, to concern oneself with the subject of a series of “uses.”

  And here the attempt to define the meaning of chresthai shows its full perti-

  nence. When Plato—Foucault suggests—makes use of the notion of chresthai/

  chresis to identify the heauton in the expression “to take care of oneself,” in reality he intends to designate “not an instrumental relationship of the soul to the rest

  of the world or to the body, but rather the subject’s singular, transcendent po-

  sition, as it were, with regard to what surrounds him, to the objects available to

  him, but also to other people with whom he has a relationship, to his body itself,

  and finally to himself” (Foucault 1, p. 56/56–57). What Plato discovers in this

  way is not, that is to say, “the soul-substance” but “the soul-subject”:

  Taking care of oneself will be to take care of the self insofar as it is the “subject

  of” a certain number of things: the subject of instrumental action, of relation-

  ships with other people, of behavior and attitudes in general, and the subject

  also of relationships to oneself. It is insofar as one is this subject who uses, who

  has certain attitudes, and who has certain relationships, etc., that one must take

  care of oneself. It is a question of taking care of oneself as subject of chresis (with all that word’s polysemy: subject of actions, behavior, relationships, attitudes).

  (Ibid., p. 56/57)

  3.2. Anyone who has any familiarity with the investigations of the late Fou-

  cault will have recognized in this passage one of the essential characteristics of

  the ethical subjectivity that they seek to define. If Foucault returns so insistently

  in his courses to Plato’s Alcibiades, it is not only because one of the central

  themes of the dialogue is care-of-oneself, with which he was very concerned

  in those years. In the Foucauldian laboratory, the Alcibiades above all furnishes

  the occasion to articulate in all its complexity and in all its aporias that notion

  of the subject with which, according to his testimony, he had never ceased to

  concern himself.

  Just as the subject is not a substance for Foucault but a process, so also does

  the ethical dimension—care-of-oneself—not have an autonomous substance:

  it has no other place and no other consistency than the relation of use between

  the human being and the world. Care-of-oneself presupposes chresis, and the self

  1058

  HOMO SACER IV, 2

  that names the ethical subject is not something other with respect to the subject

  of use but remains immanent to it. For this reason Foucault, in his reading of the

  Alcibiades, insists on the distinction between soul-substance and soul-subject,

  and for this reason he can write, in the notes published by Frédéric Gros at the

  end of the course, that “the self with which one has the relationship is nothing

  other than the relationship itself . . . it is in short the immanence, or better, the

  ontology adequation of the self to the relationship” (ibid., p. 514/533).

  The difficulty with which these feverish remarks seek to settle accounts is

  decisive: if that of which one takes care is the very subject of relations of use with

  others, the risk here is that the active subject of care will be configured in its turn

  in a transcendent position as subject with respect to an object or that, in any case,

  ethical subjectivity will be drawn into a regressio ad infinitum (the one that takes care of the subject of use will demand in its turn another subject that takes care

  of it, etc.).

  The question is all the more urgent and delicate insofar as it is precisely here

  that we see the reappearance of that problem of governmentality that constitutes

  the privileged object of Foucault’s courses beginning from the mid-1970s. The

  theme of care-of-oneself in this way risks resolving itself entirely into that of the

  governance of the self and of others, just as, in the passage from the Alcibiades, the theme of the use of the body on the part of the soul is resolved at a certain

  point into that of the command ( archè) of the soul over the body (130a).

  What is crucial here is the way in which one thinks the relationship between

  care and use, between care-of-oneself and use-of-oneself. As we have seen, in

  connection with use, Foucault evokes the relationship with oneself, but while

  the concept of care-of-oneself remains at the center of his analyses, that of “use-

  of-oneself” is almost never thematized as such. The relation of use, which consti-

  tutes precisely the primary dimension in which subjectivity is constituted, thus

  remains in the shadows and gives way to a primacy of care over use that seems

  to repeat the Platonic gesture in which chresis was resolved into care ( epimeleia) and command ( archè). This is all the more fraught with consequences insofar as

  the separation between care-of-oneself and use-of-oneself is at the root of that

  between ethics and politics, which is as alien to classical thought at least up to

  Aristotle as it is to the preoccupations of the late Foucault.

  3.3. The relation between care and use seems to entail something like a circle.

  The formula “to concern oneself with oneself as subject of chresis” suggests, in

  fact, a genetico-chronological primacy of the relations of use over care-of- oneself.

  It is only insofar as a human being is introduced as subject into a series of relations

  THE USE OF BODIES

  1059

  of use that a care-of-oneself may perhaps become possible. On the other hand, if

  “the self with which one has a relationship is nothing other than the relationship

&nb
sp; itself,” the subject of chresis and that of care are the same subject. It is this coincidence that the enigmatic expression “the immanence or ontological adequation

  of the self to the relationship” seems to want to express (Foucault 1, p. 514/533).

  The subject of use must take care of itself insofar as it is in a relationship of use

  with things or persons: that is to say, it must put itself into relationship with the

  self insofar as it is in a relationship of use with another. But a relationship with

  the self—or an affection of the self—is already implicit, as we have seen, in the

  middle-voice meaning of the verb chresthai, and this seems to call into question

  the very possibility of distinguishing between care-of-oneself and use. If “to use”

  means “to enter into a relationship with the self insofar as one is in relationship

  with another,” in what way could something like a care-of-oneself legitimately

  claim to define a dimension other than use? That is to say, how would ethics dis-

  tinguish itself from use and obtain a primacy over it? And why and how has use

  been transformed into care? This is all the more the case given that, as Foucault

  suggests many times, the subject of chresis can enter into a relationship of use also with itself, can constitute a “use-of-oneself.”

  It is perhaps out of awareness of these aporias that, alongside the theme

  of care-of-oneself, we see the appearance in the late Foucault of the at least

  apparently contrary motif that he designates with the formula: se déprendre de

  soi-même. Care-of-oneself here gives place to a dispossession and abandonment

  of the self, where it again becomes mixed up with use.

  3.4. It is from this perspective that Foucault’s interest in sadomasochistic

  practices can be properly situated. It is not only a matter of the fact that here,

  as Foucault emphasizes many times, the slave can in the end find himself in the

  position of the master, and vice versa: rather, what defines sadomasochism is the

  very structure of subjectivation, its ethos, insofar as the one whose body is (or

  seems to be) used is actually constituted to the same extent as subject of its being

  used, assumes it and experiences pleasure in it (even here what is in question, in

  the terms of the course on L’herméneutique du sujet, is the relationship that one

  has with the self as subject of one’s own sexual relations). Vice versa, the one who

  seems to use the body of the other can in some way be used by the other for his

  own pleasure. Master and slave, sadist and masochist here are not two incommu-

  nicable substances, but in being taken up into the reciprocal use of their bodies,

  they pass into one another and are incessantly indeterminated. As the language

  expresses so well, the masochist “causes to be done to him” what he suffers, is

  1060

  HOMO SACER IV, 2

  active in his very passivity. That is to say, sadomasochism exhibits the truth of use, which does not know subject and object, agent and patient. And in being taken up

  in this indetermination, pleasure is also made non-despotic and common.

  It is striking that the analyses of sadomasochism from the Freudian per-

  spective, despite noting the inversion of roles between the two subjects, do

  not mention the master/slave relation. Thus, in the by-now classic monograph

  that he dedicated to masochism, Theodor Reik notes many times the reciprocal

  transformation of the active element into the passive element and the reversal

  toward the ego of what is originally a sadistic tendency; but the terms “master”

  and “slave” never appear. By contrast, Foucault not only makes use of these

  terms but seems to suggest that it is precisely the assumption of these two roles

  that allows for a new and more enjoyable relation to the body. “I think it’s a

  kind of creation,” he writes in connection with his experience in California

  bathhouses, “a creative enterprise, which has as one of its main features what I

  call the desexualization of pleasure. . . .” (Foucault 2, p. 738/Rabinow, p. 165);

  “. . . wouldn’t it be marvelous . . . to encounter bodies that are both present and fleeting? Places where you desubjectivize and desexualize yourself . . . ?” (Foucault and Le Bitoux, p. 399).

  It is possible, then, that what is in question in sadomasochism is a ritual-

  ized re-creation of the master/slave relation, insofar as this relation paradoxically

  seems to allow access to a freer and fuller use of bodies. By means of this, the

  subject pursues the traces of a “use of the body” beyond the subject/object and

  active/passive scissions: in the words of Foucault, he has an experience of his

  own desubjectivation.

  And if it is true, as Deleuze observed, that masochism always entails a neu-

  tralization of the juridical order by means of its parodic exaggeration, then one

  can form the hypothesis that the master/slave relation as we know it represents

  the capture in the juridical order of the use of bodies as an originary prejurid-

  ical relation, on whose exclusive inclusion the juridical order finds its proper

  foundation. In use, the subjects whom we call master and slave are in such a

  “community of life” that the juridical definition of their relationship in terms

  of property is rendered necessary, almost as if otherwise they would slide into a

  confusion and a kononia tes zoes that the juridical order cannot admit except in

  the striking and despotic intimacy between master and slave. And what seems so

  scandalous to us moderns—namely, property rights over persons—could in fact

  be the originary form of property, the capture (the ex-ceptio) of the use of bodies in the juridical order.

  THE USE OF BODIES

  1061

  א The ancient world knew of festivals in which the originary indetermination that

  defines the use of bodies reemerged into the light by means of the role reversal between

  master and slave. Thus, during the Saturnalia, which was celebrated on December 17, not

  only did masters serve the slaves, but the entire order of social life was transformed and subverted. It is possible to see in these anomic festivals not only a state of suspension of the law that characterizes certain archaic juridical institutions but also, by means of this suspension, the reemergence of a sphere of human action in which not only master and

  slave but also subject and object, agent and patient are indeterminated.

  3.5. One can therefore understand why in the Phenomenology of Spirit, the

  dialectic between master and slave and the recognition that is in question in it

  has a constitutive anthropological function. What is decisive here is not only, as

  Hegel never stops reminding us, that the recognition of self-consciousness can

  happen only by means of another self-consciousness but also that, in the rela-

  tionship between master and slave, what is at stake is what Hegel unreservedly

  calls enjoyment ( der Genuss):

  The master relates himself mediately to the thing through the slave; the slave,

  qua self-consciousness in general, also relates himself negatively to the thing and abolishes it [ hebt es auf ]; but at the same time the thing is independent vis-à-

  vis the slave, whose negating of it, therefore, cannot go to the length of being

  altogether done with it to the point of annihilation; in other words, he only

  works on it. For the master, on the other hand, the
immediate relation becomes

  through this mediation the sheer negation of the thing, or the enjoyment of it.

  What desire failed to achieve, he succeeds in doing, viz., to have done with the

  thing altogether, and to achieve satisfaction in the enjoyment of it. Desire failed

  to do this because of the thing’s independence; but the master, who has interposed

  the slave between it and himself, takes to himself only the dependent aspect of

  the thing and has the pure enjoyment of it. . . .

  In both of these moments [ scil. the slave’s labor and the enjoyment that it

  renders possible] the master achieves his recognition through another conscious-

  ness. . . . (Hegel, pp. 115–116)

  Hegel sees the intimate relation between master and slave that we have sought

  to define as use of the body; however, while in the koinonia tes zoes that is here in question, the body of the master and that of the slave, distinct in the juridical

  order, tend to become undecidable. Hegel dwells upon precisely what makes it

  possible to separate and recognize the two positions: the distinction between

  the labor of the slave and the enjoyment of the master. Naturally, as in sado-

  masochism according to Foucault, the two roles tend to be reversed, and, in

  the end, since “the truth of the master’s consciousness is servile consciousness”

  1062

  HOMO SACER IV, 2

  (Hegel, p. 117), the labor of the servant, as “desire held in check and fleetingness

  staved off ” (p. 118), acquires its independence with respect to the fleeting enjoy-

  ment of the master.

  Even in this dialectical reversal, what is nonetheless lost is the possibility

  of another figure of human praxis, in which enjoyment and labor (which is

  restrained desire) are in the last analysis unassignable. From this perspective,

  sadomasochism appears as an insufficient attempt to render inoperative the dia-

  lectic between master and slave by parodically finding in it the traces of that use

  of bodies to which modernity seems to have lost all access.

  4

  The Use of the World

  4.1. Despite his boutade on not reading Being and Time, it is difficult

  to imagine that Foucault was not familiar with the chapter that

  bears the significant title “Dasein’s Being as Care [ die Sorge],” which concludes

 

‹ Prev