Islam and Pakistan’s Political Culture

Home > Other > Islam and Pakistan’s Political Culture > Page 6
Islam and Pakistan’s Political Culture Page 6

by Farhan Mujahid Chak


  education that imparts self-awareness. Of course, throughout history there

  have been those rare epochal paradigm shifts that alter the values of a people.

  Still, that rarity involves a competition between the old and the new, in which

  Downloaded by [University of Connecticut] at 18:26 09 January 2017

  victory depends on how thoroughly the new paradigm, with its values,

  addresses the shortcomings in society. For that reason, Letwin critiques

  Mathew Arnold’s book Culture and Anarchy for its emphasis on ‘tribal unity’

  as the highest civic achievement in a modern, urban metropolis.7 Tribal unity, for Arnold, is represented as an ideal to be ‘handed down’ or aspired to, due

  to the sense of togetherness it inculcates. Yet she dismisses that as a romantic

  illusion, since it ceases to be relevant, as a set of precise commands that gives

  every member an assigned role, in a contemporary city. In other words, she

  criticizes Arnold for romanticising a concept of tribal camaraderie without

  recognizing its absence from the culture meant to sustain it. Tribal customs

  16

  Islam and Pakistan’s Political Culture

  are by definition unchanging, with assigned roles, and they could not manifest

  themselves in today’s modern cities in which the structure for designation of

  responsibilities is different. 8 Traditions remain coherent not through changelessness but through continuity, which must emanate from something within

  that particular culture. One could only hope for continuity of a tradition if it

  is present in the cultural fabric of society, not by simply wishing it so. Hence,

  the continuity of tradition is dependent on the teaching skills of the ‘master’

  who recognizes the embeddedness of certain values, but does not require mere

  imitations of his performance or style. Every pupil must make something new

  of what he learns, for a tradition lives through a stream of individual inter-

  pretations and reinvention of what has gone before. 9 Whether invented tradition or rigid imitation, both, far from maintaining tradition, kill it.

  The process of continuity that permits political orientations to be handed

  down and effectively reinvented from generation to generation needs to be

  substantiated from within a culture. If this process of reinvention and reim-

  plementation of values and tradition is acceptable to the populace at large,

  then, the result will be widespread legitimacy. Here Letwin cites Palladian

  architecture: ‘it is said that Palladio’s buildings are the perfect embodiment of

  what is called the classic tradition’. Undoubtedly, they contain direct echoes

  of ancient buildings, but in fact those ‘echoes are fairly superficial and what is

  much more important is a certain sense of order, a certain relationship of

  parts among themselves and to the whole’.10 Of course, Palladio learned a classical theory of proportion through his studies of Trissino, and he acquired the

  architectural vocabulary of the ancients through making pedantic drawings. 11

  However, she attributes Palladio’s expertise to his studies and reformulation

  of other architects. ‘Palladio read Alvise Cornoro … the Bolognese theorist,

  Sebastino Serlio … and great Italian designers like Brunelleschi and Miche-

  langelo, but also from the Byzantine fantasy and Venetian lightness’.12 What this implies is that Palladio absorbed information from many diverse sources and

  then produced buildings that look as if they had grown out of the ground on

  which they stand. Explaining, Letwin insists that though there is ‘good reason

  to describe Palladio as classical, he was not classical in the same way as

  Bramante, Sangallo, Sansovino, or Raphael. He had created a style of his

  own, the Palladian building’. 13 And so it is with political culture; it grows by seeking continuity with established traditions and deep-seated societal values

  Downloaded by [University of Connecticut] at 18:26 09 January 2017

  in order to seem as if it ‘grows out of the ground on which it is meant to

  stand’. Of course, this is not merely to mirror what has transpired, or ignore

  influence, but to present an alternative that is at once relevant, in that it is

  connected to tradition, and contextual. Certainly, institutions transferred

  from outside, without precedent in the society that it means to perform, will

  find difficulty in acceptance, thereby causing instability.

  The process of continuity, substantiated on local values, and progressively

  moved forward by apprenticeship, requires both deference and individuality.

  Letwin states that it is a ‘false understanding of individuality that had led to the disdain of deference and apprenticeship that produces the horrible confidence of

  Deconstructing political culture

  17

  the parvenu and has made the call for organic unity beguiling to cultured

  people’.14 In other words, every apprentice must start by imitating or heeding his master in the fashion of a disciple, yet will see such a relationship as a prelude to another sort of relationship and another sort of learning and teaching that

  accepts personal initiative in knowledge reconstruction. Blind adherence to

  custom stifles inventiveness; it certainly cannot tolerate it. If societies are

  expected to mature, live and change in line with cherished values, then the

  individuals collectively comprising a society must permit new applications

  and consider contextual nuances. The failure to do so is bound to kill tradition

  by reducing it to custom, or by provoking rebellion among those who rightly

  value their independence.

  In essence, the importance of political culture is that it ultimately deals with

  values, which shapes the direction of political life. Examining it, though,

  raises the following critical questions: How do we decipher what those values

  are in a given polity? Indeed, even if we can convincingly reveal those values, what is the process by which they are passed down from generation to generation,

  namely apprenticeship? By what standard does reinvention occur without

  becoming illegitimate? These and many other questions are important; however,

  prior to resolving them this study will discuss the exceptional difficulties in

  defining political culture.

  Defining political culture

  Few concepts have bedevilled description as much as ‘political culture’. An

  increasingly trendy and illusory designation, it obscures far more than it

  illuminates. Perplexing and thorny, it has become quite widespread ‘among

  journalists, television commentators, policy analysts, governmental officials,

  peoples of all walks of life, and, in its most worrying development, to advertising

  copywriters’.15 Of course, due to its breadth, the idea of political culture is attractive, often serving the purpose of the final word. And, for ‘political scientists, historians, and pundits, like the early anthropological idea of culture itself, it threatens to absorb everything in its vicinity’. 16 For that reason, though, it has sometimes been avoided because of the danger of tautology: ‘petition

  principii: the thing that has to be explained is used itself as the main

  explaining factor’.17 Other objections to the term ‘political culture’ include it Downloaded by [University of Connecticut] at 18:26 09 January 2017

  being used in too fixed a way due to its reliance on consensus in society. As if

  all society would have accept
ed the values and rules of a singular political

  culture. Still, notwithstanding its widespread use, we don’t really understand

  this term; it has become a convenient shorthand for a variety of factors

  embedded within it, and is frequently misrepresented, leading to misconceptions

  about how to understand it. Commonly, pertinent questions of usage and

  intent are ignored, and it is assumed that people from different cultures think

  and act the same way, or are motivated by similar goals.

  First, a description of ‘political culture’, with its value propensity, group

  formation and impact on the political environment, was Ibn Khaldun’s

  18

  Islam and Pakistan’s Political Culture

  conceptualization. 18 But it was J.G. Herder’s eighteenth-century insight that coined the term and brought it into to the accounts of modern academic consciousness. 19 It was, however, not until Gabriel Almond described it ‘as the particular pattern of orientations to political action’ wherein ‘every political

  system is embedded’ that it became recognized.20 Since then, scholars have continued to define political culture in a multiplicity of ways. Macridis, for

  instance, argues that it is ‘commonly shared goals and commonly accepted

  rules’.21 Similarly, Kim described it as orientations toward national political institutions, including values, beliefs, and emotional attitudes about how a

  government ought to conduct itself. 22 For Pye, the indicators of a nation’s political culture include its political scope, how the ends and means in politics

  are related, standards for the evaluation of political action, and what values are

  salient for political action.23 Kavanaugh, comparably, stresses that political culture has much to do with orientations that arise, in a particular sense, from

  a subculture, influenced by general culture. 24 As is evident, the multiplicities in definitions of political culture are not necessarily in disagreement, even

  while focusing on different social aspects of its impact. However, this does

  inform us that its definition is largely shaped by the context under investigation.

  Clearly, the aspects that define political culture, in any context, are changing

  phenomena and that partially explains the differing definitions of the term. This,

  conversely, points to serious drawbacks in attempting to define it – namely,

  methodology and usage.

  For Rosenbaum, the multiplicity of definitions of political culture, although

  insightful, led to the necessity of describing the methodologies to study it. He

  suggests there are, essentially, two major approaches: first, the ‘individual-centric’

  approach, with a strongly psychological basis that entails all the important ways

  in which a person is subjectively orientated toward the essential elements in

  his political system; and second, a ‘system-level’ approach that refers to the

  collective orientation of people toward the basic elements in their political

  system.25 Here, he is interested in the manner in which citizens, individually or collectively, evaluate their political institutions and officials. To say, for instance, that a nation’s political culture is largely cohesive implies that most people within the system have similar, or like-minded, political culture orientations, which are

  agreeable to the political institutions within which they live. Hence, when political culture is discussed, it usually refers to these mass political orientations across

  Downloaded by [University of Connecticut] at 18:26 09 January 2017

  the whole political system.

  Rosenbaum, suitably, recognizes that divergent methodologies influence

  political culture definitions. Yet there is, still, a broad consensus that political culture denotes the emotional and attitudinal environment within which a

  political system operates. Be it his individual or system-centric approach,

  political culture, to put it plainly, is the underlying value-based, psychological

  climate in which politics takes place. The tendency, then, by political scientists, is to emphasize cultural and/or structural factors when trying to define it and

  explain the nature and performance of political systems. Parsons, who

  believes in an inherent interconnectedness in societies’ social systems, both

  Deconstructing political culture

  19

  cultural and structural, takes this standpoint.26 Undoubtedly, a rich explanation of political phenomena will draw on both cultural and structural factors, but

  will primarily be concerned with orientations toward political objects that

  emanate from their values. Orientations, here, means predispositions to political

  action; they are determined by religion, traditions, historical memories, motives,

  norms, myths, emotions, and symbols. Wilson breaks down these orientations

  into their constituent parts as follows: ‘thoughts – knowledge and awareness of

  the political system; influence – emotional disposition to the political system;

  and assessment – judgment about the system’.27 Political objects, or institutions, also need explanation. That would include the functioning of the executive,

  judiciary and legislative processes, political parties, pressure groups, and the

  individual’s view of himself as a political actor, as well as his views of other

  citizens. Political culture, then, may be seen as the overall distribution of

  citizens’ orientations to political objects. Thereafter, we are encouraged to

  think in terms of what kind of orientations are held by people toward political

  objects. Herein is the most significant challenge: how to accurately describe

  those orientations towards political objects, and, thereafter, describe the political culture of a given polity?

  Here, let’s examine Almond and Verba’s renowned book, The Civic Culture,

  which uses a definition of political culture associated with democracy.28 For them, a ‘civic culture’ includes a dualistic orientation to political authority – a

  balance of directive and acquiescent, participant and passive, attitudes. It is this mixed political culture, taken as ‘ideal’, which allows elites the freedom to take

  decisions that can be countered by participant orientations. Consequently, this

  makes the elites sensitive to popular preferences. The problem, however, is

  that this definition of political culture justifies a particular type of orientation, or ‘civic culture’, that presupposes a close affinity to West European/North

  American liberal democratic political traditions.29 And, by doing so, it does not assist us in deciphering a given country’s political culture, only how far

  along it is in relation to the democratic standard set.

  Admittedly, Almond and Verba have cleverly drawn on the cognitive, affective

  and evaluative dimensions of attitudes about political objects to develop their

  typology of political cultures: participant, subject and parochial. 30 Where orientations are positive to all the objects, they articulate a ‘participant’ political culture. If citizens assume a passive or obedient relationship to the system,

  Downloaded by [University of Connecticut] at 18:26 09 January 2017

  perceiving themselves as hardly affecting the political apparatus, though being

  affected by it, the political culture is ‘subject’. Where the individual hardly

  relates to the political system and has only a dim awareness and knowledge of

  it, they classify the political culture as ‘parochial’.

  To explain further, a ‘parochial’ political culture is pre-political in nature.

  Individuals belonging
to this typology are characterized as being apolitical or

  insular in attitude. For instance, tribal societies often reflect a parochial type

  of political culture. Inhabitants of tribal societies commonly manifest a distinct

  inability to relate to the relevance of societal structures, authority sources, and

  polities beyond their immediate family or tribe.31 Individuals in parochial

  20

  Islam and Pakistan’s Political Culture

  polities are often unaware of – and also unconcerned about – matters that do

  not pertain to their immediate kinship group.

  Second, the ‘subject’ political culture is distinct from the parochial type

  apropos the peoples’ awareness of the sociopolitical setting that exists beyond

  their immediate familial ties and kinship affiliations. Being cognizant of a

  broader political setting, inhabitants of a subject political culture reasonably

  comprehend the manner in which the political structures affect them, and

  may even accept the legitimacy of these structures. However, the individual’s

  role is principally a passive one, and is confined primarily to obeying decisions

  made by political leaders.

  Third, the ‘participant’ political culture type provides for an explicit and

  distinct political role for the individual member. In fact, input from the

  masses is actively promoted. The populace is accorded a high-profile status and

  is considered vital for the successful maintenance, management and stability of

  the polity. A participant political culture, in other words, operates on the

  premise that individuals should be masters of their own destiny and should

  have a direct hand in shaping this destiny. 32 This type of political culture allows for disgruntled citizenry to express discontent within the confines of

  the political environment. It intends to manage conflict within its political

  apparatus and to avoid the only recourse to dissent being violence.

  The democratic culture, as suggested by Almond and Verba, is a mixture of

  parochial, subject and participatory types. 33 It is suggested that excessive amounts of participatory, parochial or subject mentality in the culture of a

  given polity would be detrimental to the sustenance of democracy. The concept

 

‹ Prev