Book Read Free

Revolution and the Republic

Page 2

by Jeremy Jennings


  To that extent, Higonnet rightly states, ‘the actions of the nobles had little to do

  with their fate’. Rather, what mattered was the evolution of the attitude of the

  bourgeoisie towards the nobility. This passed through various stages. Armed with

  12 Guy Chaussinand-Nogaret, La Noblesse au XVIIIe siècle: De la féodalité aux lumières (1976).

  13 See also Daniel Roche, France in the Enlightenment (Cambridge, Mass., 1998), 418. Of the

  debate concerning the so-called ‘commercial nobility’ Roche writes: ‘The controversy reveals a society

  in which the highest levels of the bourgeoisie and the highest levels of the aristocracy tended, in terms

  of economic practice and social relations, to break the legal framework of orders and classes in such a

  way as to form a single existential group that can be seen as the predecessor of the notables in

  nineteenth-century bourgeois society. At the same time, however, a substantial segment of the

  society was unwilling to give up existing privileges.’

  14 William Doyle, Aristocracy and its Enemies in the Age of Revolution (Oxford, 2009). See also Jay

  M. Smith, Nobility Reimagined: The Patriotic Nation in Eighteenth-Century France (Ithaca, NY, 2005).

  15 Patrice Higonnet, Class, Ideology and the Rights of Nobles during the French Revolution (Oxford:

  1981).

  4

  Introduction: Revolution and the Republic

  the ‘hopelessly unrealistic’ expectation that ‘the gift of citizenship would transform

  potentially selfish individuals and make them good’, the view in 1789 was that, if the

  nobility was to be abolished, then the nobles themselves could be transformed (as,

  indeed, some of them set out to demonstrate). After 1791, in an atmosphere of what

  Higonnet describes as ‘opportunistic anti-nobilism’, the nobility were increasingly

  seen as being both corrupt and treacherous, and therefore to be excluded from the

  nation. Next came the ‘ideological anti-nobilism’ of the Jacobins. It was at this point

  that the physical eradication of the nobility through the Terror became ‘the symbolic

  representation of social regeneration’. ‘Only in 1799’, Higonnet concludes, ‘did the

  bourgeoisie finally understand that all property owners should make common cause’.

  Again this argument receives support from Doyle. ‘The less threatening nobles

  became’, he writes, ‘the more ferociously they were threatened.’16

  To that extent the bourgeoisie, contrary to what for many years was the prevailing

  Marxist account of the Revolution, actually acted against their own economic

  interests, allying themselves with the urban poor and the peasantry in defence of

  what Higonnet terms an ‘abhorrent economic and social levelling’. Why was this so?

  As Furet pointed out, as early as August 1789 the leaders of the Revolution began to

  believe that it was time to ‘stop’ the Revolution, but ‘each of these successive rallyings

  took place only after its leaders had taken the Revolution a step further in order to

  keep control of the mass movement and to discredit rival factions’. At each moment,

  in other words, those who wished to bring the Revolution to a close found themselves

  extending it in order to defeat their opponents. In consequence, the leaders of the

  Revolution came to embrace ever more radical positions and, with each new phase,

  the attachment to, first, constitutional monarchy and, then, constitutional govern-

  ment itself became ever weaker.

  Here we arrive at the heart of the drama of the Revolution. How could a series of

  reforms which had set out to abolish privilege and to establish legal and civil liberty

  lead to a decade of bloody turmoil and produce a new form of revolutionary

  government?17 To find an answer to this conundrum we need to provide responses

  to three questions.

  To begin: what, if any, was the connection between 1789, the Revolution that

  produced the Déclaration des Droits de l’Homme et du Citoyen, and 1793, the

  Revolution that produced the Reign of Terror? As summarized by Patrice Gueniffey,

  there have been three answers to this question.18 The ‘counter-revolutionary’ answer,

  articulated first during the Revolution itself, saw 1793 as the ‘necessary outcome’ of

  1789, as the moment which revealed its awful and bloody truth. The ‘revolutionary’

  answer, given its clearest expression in the mid-nineteenth century, saw 1793 as an

  accident, as the product of civil war and foreign invasion, and therefore as having ‘no

  connection whatsoever with the principles of the Revolution’. The third answer is of

  more recent origin. This sees the Terror, 1793, as a ‘contingent’ product of ‘the

  16 Doyle, Aristocracy, 309.

  17 See Keith Michael Baker, ‘Transformations of Classical Republicanism in Eighteenth-Century

  France’, Journal of Modern History, 73 (2001), 32–53.

  18 Patrice Gueniffey, La Politique de la Terreur (2000), 199.

  Introduction: Revolution and the Republic

  5

  culture of the Revolution’. It was there in embryo in 1789 but needed the circum-

  stances of foreign invasion and civil war to bring to the fore ‘passions and ideas

  which were not easily compatible with the establishment of political liberty’.19 ‘There

  were no revolutionary circumstances’, Furet wrote, ‘there was a Revolution that fed

  on circumstances’.20

  Second, what was the Terror?21 This is not easily answered as even the revolu-

  tionaries themselves were far from agreeing about what it was. At a minimum,

  however, it took three different forms. There was, first of all, the spontaneous and

  collective violence associated with the punitive (and usually savage) acts of the

  people directed against their opponents. Prison massacres and mob lynchings were

  two of its forms. This was violence with no particular aim but vengeance. It both

  preceded and post-dated the Revolution and was not specific to it. Jean-Paul Marat,

  from the moment he published the first issue of L’Ami du peuple on 12 September

  1789, was its most tireless advocate. As Gueniffey indicates, Marat’s view was that

  the enemies of the Revolution should be stoned to death, stabbed, shot, hanged,

  burnt, impaled, or torn to pieces. Next there was Terror as the calculated, premed-

  itated, rational, and strategic use of violence as an instrument and as a means

  designed to develop what might be termed a logic of example. The execution

  of Louis XVI would fall into this category. The aim was to terrorize the ‘enemies’

  of the Revolution into silence. There was, next, Terror as extermination, the use of

  violence to eradicate the enemies of people through their systematic execution. It

  was not a question of punishment but of annihilation. The ultimate symbol of this

  last stage was la Sainte Guillotine, an instrument of execution capable of beheading

  the twenty-two leaders of the Girondin faction (one of whom was already dead) in

  twenty-five minutes.22 In terms of chronology, the Revolution went from the first

  form of Terror to the third, the definition of the Revolution’s enemies being

  gradually extended to include ever greater numbers of people. The actual figures

  involved were relatively small, with approximately 16,000 people being guillotined

  in a nine-month period covering 1793–4. However, these increased
dramatically

  with the war against the Revolution’s opponents in the Vendée and the Revolu-

  tion’s felt need to come up with more inventive and thorough means to dispatch its

  opponents.23

  Let us look at two examples of how the Terror worked. The first is the famous

  ‘Law of Suspects’ passed on 17 September 1793, eleven days after the Convention

  declared that Terror was ‘the order of the day’. This piece of legislation empowered

  the State to arrest anyone who ‘either by their conduct, their contacts, their words

  or their writings, showed themselves to be supporters of tyranny, federalism or the

  enemies of the people’. This included those who could have been said to have either

  ‘misled’ or ‘discouraged’ the people. Virtually anybody could have fallen foul of

  19 Furet, quoted ibid. 200.

  20 Furet, Interpreting the Revolution, 62.

  21 See Gueniffey, La Politique de la Terreur.

  22 See Daniel Arasse, La Guillotine et l’imaginaire de la Terreur (1987).

  23 Amongst the many attempts to secure a speedier process of execution were plans to build a

  guillotine capable of the simultaneous execution of several victims.

  6

  Introduction: Revolution and the Republic

  such a law, especially as the only evidence required to establish guilt was denuncia-

  tion by a loyal patriot. The sole punishment for those found guilty was death.24

  The second example illustrates how Terror operated against groups or regions

  which opposed the Revolution. We will pass over the systematic massacre of the

  people of the Vendée in western France by the so-called colonnes infernales in

  January 1794 and mention only the fate of the city of Lyons after it had rallied

  to the cause of counter-Revolution. When it finally surrendered, the Committee of

  Public Safety decreed that the entire city was to be destroyed in an act of collective

  punishment, its very name was to disappear and was to be replaced by that of Ville-

  Affranchie. There was too much work for the guillotine to do, so condemned men

  were blown into open graves by cannon and gunfire.

  The truth is that the Terror developed a logic of its own, threatening or

  punishing people not for what they did but for what they were or represented.

  This is why the category of ‘suspect’ was at its heart. Moreover, it was a ‘system’ that

  perpetuated itself. Its defenders liked to portray the Terror as a temporary measure

  designed to meet exceptional circumstances. However, once installed, it operated

  not just as a system of arbitrary and absolute power but as something that could not

  be stopped or even slowed down. Rather the pace of its operation accelerated, in the

  end engulfing most of the revolutionaries themselves, including Robespierre, his

  own crime being the ‘suspicion’ or ‘rumour’ that he intended to marry the daughter

  of Louis XVI and have himself crowned as king.

  The third question is: who were the Jacobins? It would be a mistake to see the

  Jacobins as a single homogeneous bloc or party. Initially they took the title of the

  Société des Amis de la Constitution, later becoming the Société des Amis de la

  Liberté et de l’Égalité. Members of this society were so called for the reason that

  they originally met in a former convent of Dominican or ‘Jacobin’ monks. Whilst

  its leadership was concentrated in Paris, with Robespierre and those who later

  constituted the Committee of Public Safety at its heart, there also existed a network

  of provincial clubs which, at their height, brought together between 100,000 and

  200,000 activists who saw their task as that of supporting and implementing the

  policies of the new regime. Initially the Jacobins were not clearly distinguishable

  from the other groups that aspired to lead the Revolution, but by 1793 they had

  distanced themselves from the moderates, such that the Terror of 1793–4 was very

  much their affair. Not only did the Jacobins implement it but they also provided its

  political and moral justification.

  It is the question of what the Jacobins stood for (and, more generally, what was

  their significance) that has generated the most controversy. As Patrice Gueniffey has

  observed: ‘through their capacity to embody what was most radical in the French

  Revolution, and consequently to embody the Revolution itself, the Jacobins passed

  into the two centuries which followed as legend, history, tradition, heritage, theory

  24 At first substantial numbers of suspects were acquitted but over time this number was

  dramatically reduced as a percentage of those placed on trial. See Gérard Walter, Actes du Tribunal

  Révolutionnaire (1986).

  Introduction: Revolution and the Republic

  7

  and practice’.25 As for Robespierre himself, 26 as Furet remarked, he had ‘the strange

  privilege of becoming an embodiment’. ‘Robespierre’, he wrote, ‘is an immortal figure

  not because he reigned supreme over the Revolution for a few months, but because

  he was the mouthpiece of its purest and most tragic discourse.’27

  Above all, this was a discourse that assigned a new goal to the Revolution: that of

  attaining the reign of virtue and of bringing about a return to a natural, prelapsarian

  order.28 ‘Considering’, Robespierre declared, ‘the extent to which the human race

  has been degraded by the vice of our former social system, I am convinced of the

  need to bring about a complete regeneration . . . to create a new people.’29 How did

  the Jacobins envision their model of virtue? At its core was a quest for simplicity and

  a rejection of what were seen as the imperfections, the shallowness, and false

  appearances of the corrupt present. Robespierre, who gloried in his mythical status

  as the ‘Incorruptible’, was its very incarnation. Immune from ordinary passions

  (there is no evidence that Robespierre engaged in any sexual activity),30 he above all

  others was best placed to denounce the failings and prejudices of ordinary mortals.

  No one could better tear away the ‘masks’ behind which were hidden depravity,

  avarice, and ambition.

  This can be illustrated by citing one example of Robespierre’s rhetoric. Robe-

  spierre detested the theatre. He did so because, of all the arts, it more than any other

  was a world of appearance, and therefore was capable of corrupting an innocent

  people. ‘The princesses of the theatre’, Robespierre announced, ‘are no better than

  the princesses of Austria. Both are equally depraved and both should be treated with

  equal severity.’31 Actors, and especially pretty actresses, were to be denied access

  to the ranks of the people. Moreover, Robespierre extended this argument to

  politics itself. In a remarkable tirade delivered before the Jacobins on 8 January

  1794 Robespierre compared the opponents of the Revolution to actors, where

  the politically and morally corrupt followed each other in a succession of different

  ‘masks’.32 ‘It is always’, Robespierre declared, ‘the same scene, the same theatrical

  action’. Conversely, it was his sense of his own moral purity that provided the

  Jacobins with the audacity first to denounce and then to physically destroy their

  opponents, repeating with hypnotic regularity the denunciation of their moral

  turpi
tude and crimes. ‘I sometimes fear’, Robespierre announced shortly before

  25 Patrice Gueniffey, ‘Jacobinisme’, in François Furet and Mona Ozouf, Dictionnaire critique de la

  Révolution française: Idées (1992), 243. See also Patrice Gueniffey, ‘Robespierre’, ibid., Acteurs, 247–71.

  26 See Ruth Scurr, Fatal Purity: Robespierre and the French Revolution (London, 2007).

  27 Furet, Interpreting the Revolution, 56, 61. For a selection of Robespierre’s speeches in English: see

  Slavoj Žižek (ed.), Robespierre: Virtue and Terror (London, 2007).

  28 See Lucien Jaume, Le Discours Jacobin et la démocratie (1989) and Mona Ozouf, ‘“Jacobin”:

  Fortune et infortunes d’un mot’, L’École de la France: Essais sur la Révolution, l’utopie et l’enseignement

  (1984), 74–90.

  29 Œuvres de Maximilien Robespierre, x. Discours de 27 juillet 1793–27 juillet 1794 (1967), 12.

  30 Scurr, Fatal Purity, 102, indicates that upon his arrival in Paris Robespierre acquired a mistress.

  The evidence is not conclusive.

  31 Œuvres de Maximilien Robespierre, x. 101.

  32 See Paul Friedland, Political Actors: Representative Bodies and Theatricality in the French

  Revolution (Ithaca, NY, 2002).

  8

  Introduction: Revolution and the Republic

  his own fall from power, ‘that in the eyes of posterity I will be sullied by the impure

  proximity of wicked men’.33

  The second point of reference for the Jacobin model of virtue was the classical

  world of Greece and Rome. Turning their backs on the Christian tradition, it was

  Solon, Lycurgus, and Brutus who were their heroes, with a clear preference being

  expressed for Sparta over Athens. As Robespierre’s most loyal supporter, Saint-Just,

  was to remark, the world had been empty since the Romans. Here was fertile terrain

  for the florid imaginations of the revolutionaries, as they dwelt upon a world where

  there was no industry, no commerce, no luxury, no big cities, only the rustic

  simplicity of peasant farmers and the sublime heroism of citizen-soldiers. It was also

  an exclusively male world, public space being reserved only for the activities of men

  and for supposedly male virtues.

  Most of all, it was a world which saw public participation in the communal

  affairs of the State as the source of moral worth. The good individual was the good

 

‹ Prev