Book Read Free

Revolution and the Republic

Page 8

by Jeremy Jennings

jettisoned without recall.

  The most persuasive and eloquent exponent of a constitution and a declara-

  tion designed to protect the natural and civil rights of the citizen was undoubt-

  edly Emmanuel Sieyès.19 Having announced the advent of the Revolution with

  an attack on privilege and a defence of the claims of the Third Estate, in his

  famous phrase, ‘to be something’, Sieyès next provided the National Assembly

  with a carefully crafted and detailed document entitled Préliminaire de la

  Constitution: Réconnaissance et exposition raisonnée des droits de l’homme et du

  12 See Keith Michael Baker, ‘The Idea of a Declaration of Rights’, in Van Kley, French Idea of

  Freedom, 154–96.

  13 Arnaud Gouges-Cartou, ‘Projet des Déclaration des droits’, in Fauré, Les Déclarations, 203–17.

  14 Cte d’Antraigues, ‘Au Sujet de la Déclaration des droits de l’homme et du citoyen’, in Fauré, Les

  Déclarations, 172.

  15 Cte de Castellane, ‘Sur la Déclaration des droits’, in Fauré, Les Déclarations, 134.

  16 Archives Parlementaires, 8 (1875), 453.

  17 Jean-Louis Seconds, ‘Essai sur les droits des hommes, des citoyens et des nations; ou addresse au

  roi sur les états généraux et les principes d’une bonne constitution’, in Fauré, Les Déclarations, 60.

  18 Pierre-Toussaint Durand de Maillane, ‘Opinion sur les divers plans de Constitution, et la

  Déclaration des droits de l’homme et du citoyen’, in Fauré, Les Déclarations, 140–1.

  19 See Jean-Denis Bredin, Sieyès: La Clé de la Révolution française (1988); Murray Forsyth, Reason

  and Revolution: The Political Thought of the Abbé Sieyès (Leicester, 1987); William H. Sewell Jr,

  A Rhetoric of Bourgeois Revolution: The Abbé Sieyes and What is the Third Estate? (Durham, NC, and

  London, 1994); and Pasquale Pasquino, Sieyès et l’invention de la constitution en France (1998).

  Rights, Liberty, and Equality

  33

  citoyen,20 a text premised upon the belief that the primary purpose of any

  constitution was to protect and extend the rights of man and the citizen. Thus

  Sieyès’s introductory remarks led him to the initial conclusion that ‘the social

  state does not establish an unjust inequality of rights by the side of a natural

  inequality of means: on the contrary, it protects the equality of rights against

  the natural and harmful inequality of means’.21

  Sieyès then felt able to assert that the first of man’s rights was the ‘ownership of

  his person’ and to argue from this that it followed that man also had the right to

  ownership of his own actions and labour. When combined with the Lockean

  maxim that the mixing of one’s labour with an object provided an entitlement to

  ownership this produced a definition of liberty in terms of the enjoyment of one’s

  ‘personal’ and ‘territorial’ property and the overall conclusion that ‘every citizen had

  the right to remain, to go, to think, to speak, to write, to print, to publish, to work,

  to produce, to protect, to transport, to exchange and to consume’.22 The only

  limitation to the exercise of these rights was infringement upon the rights of others

  and as such, in Sieyès’s view, was a matter to be settled by law. The principal threats

  to their enjoyment were deemed to come in the form of ‘malevolent citizens’,

  abuses by the ‘public power’, and external attack.

  Where Sieyès moved beyond the Lockean position was in his argument that, in

  addition to the legitimate expectation that a citizen’s rights and liberties would be

  protected, the citizen had a ‘right’ to the benefits of association, amongst which he

  included public works, poor relief, and a system of education. Eschewing the details

  of their provision, Sieyès nevertheless commented that ‘it is sufficient here to say

  that the citizenry as a whole have a right to everything that the State can do in their

  favour’.23

  All of the above rights were categorized by Sieyès as natural and civil rights,

  with the latter appearing, not without ambiguity, to be distinguishable from the

  former by their more obvious social origin. Both categories, however, were to be

  differentiated from political rights. If all citizens enjoyed natural and civil

  rights––everyone, Sieyès affirmed, had a right to the protection of their person,

  property, and liberty––only a restricted number, the so-called ‘active’ citizens,

  had a right to participate in the affairs of the public power. ‘The difference

  between these two types of rights’, Sieyès explained, ‘is that natural and civil

  rights are those for the maintenance and development of which society is formed

  whilst political rights are those by which society is formed’.24 Explicitly excluded

  from the possession of political rights were women (‘in their present condition’),

  children, foreigners and those not contributing financially to the support of the

  ‘public establishment’. For those described by Sieyès as ‘the real shareholders of

  the great social enterprise’, on the other hand, equality of political rights was to be

  a fundamental principle.

  20 Three versions of this document exist. The version cited here is the one read before the National

  Assembly on 20–21 July 1789: see Fauré, Les Déclarations, 91–107.

  21 Ibid. 95.

  22 Ibid. 96.

  23 Ibid. 99.

  24 Ibid. 101.

  34

  Rights, Liberty, and Equality

  The outline déclaration which followed––with thirty-two articles, later amended to

  thirty-seven25––was intended to summarize these ‘eternal rights’ in a codified and

  easily accessible form. It is interesting to note, therefore, that if Sieyès concentrated

  upon emphasizing the rights to liberty, property, and security, the specifics of the

  déclaration included the right to free speech, freedom of the press, the right to travel,

  and the inviolability of letters. All citizens were to be equally subject to the law and

  no one could be arrested or imprisoned without just cause. Moreover, it was,

  according to Marcel Gauchet,26 this déclaration and not that presented by Lafayette,

  nor indeed that of the sixième Bureau (which on 19 August had received by far the

  highest number of votes), that played the decisive role in shaping the final document

  approved on 26 August.27 Starting from the premise that ‘ignorance, forgetfulness or

  contempt of the rights of man are the sole causes of public misfortune and the

  corruption of government’, the Déclaration des Droits de l’Homme et du Citoyen

  went on inter alia to assert that natural rights existed prior to the formation of society,

  that the only legitimate limitation upon their enjoyment was the rights of others, and

  that these limits could only be established by legislation. In this way, with both

  astonishing speed and audacity, the members of the National Assembly established

  rights as the basic language of the new politics.

  Why then when, as Jeremy Waldron has observed,28 the belief in universally

  applicable principles of justice and right had lost all ‘philosophical respectability’

  did the language of the rights of man occupy such a central place in the delibera-

  tions of the National Assembly during the months of July and August 1789? In

 
part (although this must not be exaggerated)29 the explanation lies in the immense

  prestige accorded to the American precedent, a prestige given greater force by the

  strong personal relationships that existed between such figures as Jefferson and

  Franklin and those who initially led the Revolution. For example, the philosopher

  and mathematician Condorcet, who in 1789 was one of the most tireless advocates

  of the need for a declaration of rights, did not hesitate to cite with approval the

  simplicity and wisdom of the American declaration of 1776 and of Virginia’s Bill of

  Rights or to draw attention to the numerous commercial and moral benefits which

  had resulted from their application.30 ‘The spectacle of a great nation where the

  rights of man are respected’, he wrote in 1787, ‘is of use to all the others, despite

  differences in climate, morals and constitutions.’31 A further influence was the

  25 ‘Déclaration des droits du citoyen français’, ibid. 219–24.

  26 Gauchet, ‘Droits de l’homme’.

  27 ‘Motion de M. le Mquis de La Fayette relativement à la Déclaration des droits de l’homme’, in

  Fauré, Les Déclarations, 87; ‘Projet de Déclaration des Droits de l’homme et du citoyen, discuté dans le

  sixième Bureau de l’Assemblée nationale’, ibid. 231–4.

  28 Jeremy Waldron, Nonsense upon Stilts (London, 1987), 18.

  29 See François Furet, ‘From Savage Man to Historical Man: The American Experience in

  Eighteenth-Century French Culture’, in Furet, In the Workshop of History (Chicago, 1984), 153–66,

  and Marcel Thomann, ‘Origines et sources doctrinales de la déclaration des droits’, Droits, 8 (1988),

  55–70.

  30 Jean-Antoine-Nicolas Caritat, marquise de Condorcet, ‘De l’Influence de la Révolution

  d’Amérique sur l’Europe’, Œuvres de Condorcet (1847), viii. 3–113.

  31 Ibid. 13.

  Rights, Liberty, and Equality

  35

  remonstrances of the French law courts, the parlements.32 As J. H. Shennan has

  shown, starting out from conservative premises the vocabulary of the magistrates of

  Paris shifted ground dramatically during the eighteenth century, with new implica-

  tions and meanings being attached to such words as ‘man’, ‘humanity’, and

  ‘society’. ‘The concept of specific rights for legally constituted groups’, he writes,

  faded ‘before that of the universal rights of man’.33

  More generally, if the Déclaration des Droits de l’Homme et du Citoyen was not

  a direct product or expression of the Enlightenment, the members of the National

  Assembly were nevertheless able to turn to the philosophes for inspiration as part of

  what Alexis de Tocqueville was later to describe as their ‘revolutionary education’.34

  Locke, Rousseau, the physiocrats, and others, misinterpreted and radicalized,

  provided, in Cheryl Welch’s words, ‘a ready-made vocabulary of revolution’ and

  one that was imbued with the language of natural rights.35 Despite the criticisms

  directed against arguments from ‘nature’ during the eighteenth century by writers

  such as David Hume and d’Alembert such formulations, as Dan Edelstein has

  shown,36 continued to be commonplace and to retain their credibility. To para-

  phrase Diderot, many were those who believed that the best legislation was that

  which conformed most closely to nature. To take but one example: Condorcet,

  using a sensationalist epistemology that in the hands of Helvétius had produced a

  crude utilitarianism, insisted that the facts of human nature logically gave rise to

  principles of universal rights and justice.37 ‘We call these rights natural’, Condorcet

  wrote in 1787, ‘because they derive from the nature of man, because from the

  moment that a sensate being capable of reasoning and of having moral ideas exists,

  it follows as an obvious and necessary consequence that he must enjoy these rights,

  that he cannot be deprived of them without injustice.’38 Such was the unproblem-

  atic character of these rights, according to Condorcet, that only the right to equality

  needed explanation.39

  32 See William Doyle, ‘The Parlements’, in Keith Baker (ed.), The French Revolution and the

  Creation of Modern Political Culture, i. The Political Culture of the Old Regime (Oxford, 1987), 157–68.

  33 J. H. Shennan, ‘The Political Vocabulary of the Parlement of Paris in the Eighteenth Century’,

  Società italiana di storia del diritto: Atti del IV congresso internazionale, 951–64. Of less importance were

  the cahiers de doléances prepared for the meeting of the Estates-General; see George V. Taylor,

  ‘Revolutionary and Nonrevolutionary Content in the Cahiers of 1789: An Interim Report’, French

  Historical Studies, 7 (1971–2), 479–502. See Lucien Jaume (ed.), Les Déclarations des droits de l’homme

  (1989), 75–91.

  34 See Wolfgang Schmale, ‘Les Droits de l’homme dans la pensée politique des Lumières’, in

  Antoine de Baecque, L’An 1 des droits de l’homme (1988), 332–53.

  35 Cheryl Welch, Liberty and Utility: The French Ideologues and the Transformation of Liberalism

  (New York, 1984), 7. See also André Jardin, Histoire du Libéralisme politique: De la crise de l’absolutisme

  à la constitution de 1875 (1985), 94–112.

  36 The Terror of Natural Right: Republicanism, the Cult of Nature and the French Revolution

  (Chicago, 2009).

  37 See Keith M. Baker, Condorcet: From Natural Philosophy to Social Mathematics (Chicago, 1975),

  195–263.

  38 Condorcet, ‘Lettres d’un bourgeois de New-Haven à un citoyen de Virginie’, Œuvres de

  Condorcet, ix. 14.

  39 Condorcet, ‘Idées sur le despotisme: à l’usage de ceux qui prononcent ce mot sans entendre’,

  ibid. 166.

  36

  Rights, Liberty, and Equality

  Thus the language of rights, for all its philosophical frailty, retained a definite

  plausibility and amongst France’s political representatives in the summer of 1789

  attained almost the status of a common linguistic currency. Ironically, however, the

  limitations to its popularity were immediately visible, even in the debates within the

  National Assembly that surrounded the actual formulation of the Déclaration des

  Droits de l’Homme et du Citoyen. For men such as Sieyès the recent American

  experience provided not so much an example to be followed as something that

  France, imbued with a universalistic spirit, could improve upon. Such a belief

  implicitly assumed that the situations faced by the two nations were not necessarily

  comparable. This was made explicit by Rabaut Saint-Étienne on 18 August when

  he stated categorically that ‘the circumstances are not the same: [America] was

  breaking with a distant parent State; it was the case of a new people destroying

  everything in order to renew everything’.40 It was this theme that was repeatedly

  developed by Lally-Tollendal when he argued that the differences between a

  colonized people freeing itself from a far-away government and an ‘ancient’ people

  which had experienced the same form of government for fourteen centuries and

  been ruled by the same dynasty for eight centuries were immense, and so much so

  that any statement of natural rights in France had of necessity to be accompanied

  by the immediate disclosure of ‘positive’ rig
hts in a written constitution. ‘I ask’,

  Lally-Tollendal stated, ‘that this declaration of rights should be as short, as clear

  and as concise as possible; that, having established the principle, its correct

  application is speedily carried out in order that others might not be able to apply

  it incorrectly; that, having transported man to the forests, he is brought back at

  once to the midst of France.’41

  In short, whilst Lally-Tollendal remained committed to a declaration of rights,

  he recognized that unless these rights could be quickly located in a precisely

  defined, concrete context they ran the risk of unleashing excess and disorder.

  Others amongst the monarchiens or moderates were not slow to take up and to

  amplify this theme.42 ‘We will never abandon our rights’, Jean-Joseph Mounier

  declared, ‘but we should not exaggerate them. We must not forget that the French

  are not a new people, recently emerged from the depths of the forest in order to

  form an association, but a society of 24 million men which wishes to strengthen the

  ties between its various parts, which wishes to regenerate the kingdom so that the

  principles of a true monarchy might be forever sacred.’43 The French people,

  having freed itself from servitude, now needed to establish the empire of law.

  It was initially the Comte de Mirabeau who most forcefully expressed what

  were perceived to be the dangers and absurdity of undue abstraction. As early as

  15 June 1789 when opposing the proposal of the citoyen-philosophe Sieyès to

  40 Archives Parlementaires, 8 (1875), 452.

  41 Ibid. 222–3, 458.

  42 See Robert Griffiths, Le Centre perdu: Malouet et les « monarchiens » dans la Révolution française

  (Grenoble, 1988).

  43 Archives parlementaires, 8 (1875), 214.

  Rights, Liberty, and Equality

  37

  rename the Estates-General as the ‘Assemblée des représentants connus et verifiés

  de la nation française’, he commented that

  it is not always expedient, it is not always appropriate to consult only what is right

  without regard to the circumstances . . . The metaphysician, travelling on a map of the

  world, crosses everything without difficulty, has no trouble either with mountains or

  deserts or rivers or chasms; but when he wishes to make a journey, when he wishes to

 

‹ Prev