Revolution and the Republic

Home > Other > Revolution and the Republic > Page 13
Revolution and the Republic Page 13

by Jeremy Jennings


  where Christianity was repeatedly characterized as conveying the same message as the

  revolutionary triptych of ‘Liberty, Equality, and Fraternity’.127

  No one gave clearer expression of this republican attachment to equality than

  socialist Louis Blanc. Liberty, ‘without equality and fraternity, its two immortal

  sisters’, Blanc wrote, would only produce ‘the liberty of the savage condition’.128

  This was what existed under the capitalist system of unbridled competition. Blanc’s

  response, set out famously in L’Organisation du travail,129 was to recommend the

  establishment of ateliers sociaux, workshops for which funds would be put forward

  by government. This was not to be a system of enforced collectivization or of state-

  imposed equality but one where equality would emerge through the principle and

  practice of association. The end to be pursued was unambiguous. It was one where

  ‘all men have an equal right to the full development of their unequal faculties, the

  instruments of production belonging to everyone like the air and the sun’.130

  From this perspective, liberty was seen not just as a ‘right’ but as the ‘ability’ to

  exercise our faculties to the full. If, therefore, Blanc recognized the importance

  of those liberties that he himself listed as liberty of the press, of conscience, and of

  association, he believed that our conception of liberty had to be extended so as to

  embrace a range of liberties that would abolish the servitude arising from poverty

  and hunger. These he described as the liberty to life, to pursue one’s aptitudes, to

  choose a job, and the liberty that would arise from physical abundance. Only when

  the latter had been satisfied would it be possible to speak of ‘l’homme libre’.131 By

  liberty, then, was meant not just the narrow conception of the absence of restraint

  but something tied to a different vision of society: the social Republic.

  With the Revolution of February 1848 and the fall of the July Monarchy,

  republicans for the first time saw the opportunity of establishing a Republic that

  would embody not just the political equality of the ballot box but also the social

  and economic demands they had campaigned for over the last decade.132 The

  former goal was attained (almost without debate) through the proclamation of

  direct and universal male suffrage but on the latter questions there proved to be no

  126 See Marcel David, Le Printemps de la fraternité: Genèse et vicissitudes 1830–1851 (1992). See also

  Michel Borgetto, La Devise ‘Liberté, Egalité, Fraternité’ (1997) and Mona Ozouf, ‘La Révolution française

  et l’idée de fraternité’, in L’Homme régénéré: Essais sur la Révolution française (1989), 158–82.

  127 Pierre Leroux, De l’Égalité (Boussac, 1848). This text was first published in 1838.

  128 Louis Blanc, ‘La Liberté’, Le Nouveau monde: Journal historique et politique, 8 (1850), 1–12.

  129 Blanc, L’Organisation du travail (1840).

  130 Blanc, ‘La Liberté’, 3.

  131 Ibid. 5–6.

  132 See Maurice Agulhon, 1848 ou l’apprentissage de la République 1848–1852 (1973).

  Rights, Liberty, and Equality

  57

  agreement. Work for some 100,000 people was created through the establishment

  of national workshops but these, despite popular protest in support of them, were

  quickly closed. At the heart of the question were the newly formulated claims to

  ‘the right to work’ and ‘the right to assistance’. As on previous occasions, the

  passions aroused and arguments deployed over these issues were clearly visible in

  the debates of the National Assembly as its members sought to define the principles

  of the new constitution.133

  Let us note that the deputies began by discussing whether the constitution

  should be preceded by a preamble outlining general principles and rights. Despite

  the familiar arguments that such a preamble would be ‘vague’, ‘obscure’, ‘theatri-

  cal’, and ‘metaphysical’, serving no useful purpose, it was the proponents of a

  preamble, bolstered by the rhetorical power of poet Alphonse de Lamartine, who

  carried the day.134 Next, the deputies turned their attention to the content of the

  preamble and specifically to the question of whether it should include the right to

  work. Discussion was nothing if not animated, as all those involved recognized that

  the outcome would define the character of the February Revolution itself. ‘The

  rights which you have declared to date’, argued the socialist Victor Considérant,

  ‘are old rights, those that can be called bourgeois rights; the right to work is a new

  right, it is the right of the workers.’135 If it were not granted the workers would

  conclude that the revolution was over. Other speakers, such as parliamentary

  deputies Ledru-Rollin and Crémieux, continued this theme, locating demands

  for a recognition of the right to work within the tradition of ‘the great revolution’.

  More typical was the measured response of the deputy for the Indre, Rollinat.

  Responding to Alexis de Tocqueville’s charge that the February Revolution ran the

  risk of making the State ‘the master of every man’, he countered that 1848 was ‘a

  social revolution in the sense that it sought to secure the continuous and progressive

  improvement of the physical and mental state of the people through means

  consistent with the sacred right of property’.136 The workers therefore had to

  accept that work was both a right and a duty and, if they did so, the State would

  help them within ‘the limits of the possible’. The State, in short, would recognize

  ‘the right not to die of hunger’.

  As the political tide turned against the radicals––in June 1848 an uprising by

  Parisian workers was ruthlessly crushed by the army led by General Cavaignac––it

  was the arguments of Adolphe Thiers against the right to work that secured the

  greater audience.137 A reluctant supporter of the Republic,138 Thiers’s contention

  was that all societies rested upon three fundamental principles: property, liberty,

  133 See François Luchaire, Naissance d’une constitution: 1848 (1998); Piero Craveri, Genesi di une

  constituzione: Libertà et socialismo nel dibattito constituzionale del 1848 in Francia (Naples, 1985).

  134 Le Moniteur Universel: Journal Officiel de la République Française, 251 (6 Sept. 1848), 2333.

  135 Craveri, Genesi di une constituzione, 123–4.

  136 Le Moniteur Universel, 258 (14 Sept. 1848), 2458.

  137 Adolphe Thiers, Discours de M. Thiers, prononcés à l’Assemblée nationale dans la discussion de la

  constitution, septembre et octobre 1848 (1848): repr. in Discours parlementaires de M. Thiers (1880), viii.

  57–106.

  138 Adolphe Thiers (1797–1877) was one of the major intellectual and political figures of 19th-

  cent. France. A liberal conservative, he later became the Third Republic’s first head of government.

  58

  Rights, Liberty, and Equality

  and competition. It was through work that one acquired property. It was though

  work that one expressed one’s liberty. It was through work that one attempted to do

  better than one’s neighbour. Everyone, Thiers argued, benefited from these prin-

  ciples, including the worker, whose standard of living had risen steadily over the
/>   past forty to fifty years. To codify the right to work, however, would encourage

  laziness and idleness; it would bankrupt industry and bankrupt the State. Even

  more seriously, it was an invitation to insurrection. Have you, Thiers asked his

  fellow deputies in the phrase reminiscent of Rivarol’s argument in the 1790s,

  thought of ‘the danger in which you will find yourselves when [the unemployed]

  present themselves before you, armed not just with the imposing demands that

  arise from their misery but also with an article of your constitution?’139 For the

  State to offer help, as it should do, was not the same thing as to grant a right.140

  Louis Blanc’s reply was spirited to say the least.141 Accepting that the right to

  property derived from work, he insisted that the ownership of property when not a

  consequence of work was ‘illegitimate’ and that work which did not result in the

  ownership of property was ‘oppressive’. More to the point, he argued that if ‘man

  has the right to life, by the same token he should have the right to the means to

  preserve it’.142 At the level of the individual this entailed a recognition of the right

  to work; at the level of society it demanded the replacement of a system of

  competition by a system of association: socialism

  Nevertheless, it was the argument against the right to work that carried the day,

  leaving the preamble to the Constitution with no more than a recognition of the

  obligation of the Republic, ‘through fraternal assistance, to secure the existence of

  those citizens in need, either by providing them with work within the limits of its

  resources or, for want of a family, by giving help to those who are not in a position

  to work’.143

  Where did this now place discussion of rights, liberty, and equality within

  republican discourse? For guidance we can turn to Charles Renouvier’s Manuel

  Républicain de l’Homme et du Citoyen, written in 1848 and commissioned by the

  Ministry of Public Instruction as a civic catechism for the new Republic.144 If the text

  itself betrays both the heated debates of the period as well as Renouvier’s conviction

  that the Republic should embody ‘justice’ and ‘fraternity’, it also relied upon a formal,

  legalistic definition of liberty as ‘the power to do everything that does not harm

  others, everything that does not infringe upon the rights of others’.145 The ‘principal

  139 Discours de M. Thiers, 50. A similar statement was made by Duvergier de Hauranne: ‘Let us

  imagine that, in a situation of crisis, a million workers, or 500,000 if you wish, arrive with the article of

  your constitution in their hands and ask you for work and for a wage when the coffers of the State are

  empty, when taxes are not being paid, when there is no credit left: what would you do?’ Le Moniteur

  Universel, 257 (13 Sept. 1848), 2419.

  140 See also Thiers, De la propriété (1848).

  141 Louis Blanc, Le Socialisme: Droit au Travail: Réponse à M. Thiers (1848).

  142 Ibid. 78.

  143 See Luchaire, Naissance d’une constitution, 219–20.

  144 Charles Renouvier, Manuel Républicain de l’Homme et du Citoyen (1848). Quotations are from

  the 1904 edn. See Marie-Claude Blais, Au principe de la République: Le Cas Renouvier (2000).

  145 Renouvier, Manuel Républicain, 145.

  Rights, Liberty, and Equality

  59

  liberties’ that were ‘natural’ and that it was the responsibility of the Republic to

  guarantee for its citizens were taken to be ‘the liberty of conscience, the liberty of

  speech, the liberty to write and to publish’. To these were then added three more

  liberties: ‘individual liberty’, defined as the right not to be accused, arrested, or

  detained without proper authority; ‘political liberty’, described as the right of the

  citizen to obey only those laws authorized by his representatives and to pay only those

  taxes to which he had consented; ‘the liberty to assemble and to associate’, where

  special mention was made of the activities of religion and politics.

  The complications began to arise when Renouvier considered liberties associated

  with the right to property. ‘The most important outcome of a well-ordered

  Republic’, he wrote, ‘is to guarantee for each citizen the protection of his person,

  of his rights and of everything that belongs to him.’146 This included a citizen’s

  property, described as ‘the fruits of a man’s work’. Accordingly, Renouvier con-

  cluded that a law taking away the right to property ‘would very much diminish the

  liberty of man, would place the citizen in a position of too great a dependence upon

  the Republic’.147 Property was a stimulant to work and a cause of material progress.

  What did this mean for an understanding of equality? Renouvier’s starting point

  was that all men were ‘born equal in rights’ and that this was affirmed through ‘the

  empire of law’. The emphasis therefore fell upon the civil equalities declared in

  1789: ‘The law of the Republic does not accept any distinction between citizens

  based upon birth or any hereditary possession of power. Civil and political func-

  tions can never be held as property.’148 The law, in terms of both protection and

  punishment, was the same for all. Equality of conditions, however, was to be

  rejected because ‘it could be established only by depriving citizens of their liberty’.

  How, then, could equality be made compatible with liberty? Renouvier’s answer,

  in true quarante-huitard fashion, was to call upon the sentiment of fraternity. ‘It is’,

  he wrote, ‘fraternity that leads citizens, brought together through their representa-

  tives in parliament, to reconcile all their rights, in such a way that they remain free

  men whilst, as far as possible, becoming equals.’149

  What substance could be given to this aspiration? Renouvier was clear that the

  rights of property were not without limits and that industry and commerce could,

  to an extent, be subject to public regulation. Unfettered competition had led to

  abuses and exploitation. He therefore specifically recommended that the State

  should provide cheap credit, that associations of workers should be allowed to run

  factories and workshops, and that land should be redistributed more equally. The

  interesting part of Renouvier’s argument, however, lay elsewhere. If Renouvier

  went further by embracing what he termed ‘the right to work and to subsistence

  through work’, he gave a similarly prominent place to what was to become one of

  the great republican leit-motifs of the future: ‘the right to receive an education’.150

  This education was to be the same for all. It was to be not merely a technical

  education but also a moral and civic education. Its aim was ‘to elevate the soul’.

  Henceforth, it was to be education, rather than the pursuit and implementation

  146 Ibid. 161.

  147 Ibid. 169.

  148 Ibid. 203–4.

  149 Ibid. 206.

  150 Ibid. 207.

  60

  Rights, Liberty, and Equality

  of demands for economic equality, that would be the motor of republican

  equality.151

  Renouvier’s text, therefore, tried its best to produce a synthesis of republican

  thinking that would preserve the radical aspiration
towards greater equality

  whilst seeking to avoid the rhetorical excesses of those who challenged the very

  right to property. It is intriguing to note that, when faced with the hypothetical

  situation of there being too many people for the number of jobs available,

  Renouvier’s response was not to contemplate further assaults upon the right of

  property but rather to suggest that the Republic should establish a colonial empire.

  ‘The earth’, he wrote, ‘is vast and still largely unpopulated. Could we not, if the need

  arose, create new Frances overseas?’152 Similarly, Renouvier’s text was imbued with

  the desire to reconcile Christianity with the cause of the Republic: fraternity was

  nothing but ‘the application to society of the doctrine of Christ’. In this his position

  was not much different from that of such liberals as Alexis de Tocqueville who, while

  opposing the right to work, regarded the act of helping the poor as ‘Christianity

  applied to politics’.153 Moreover, the descent of the Second Republic into a revived

  and modernized form of Bonapartism left Renouvier bitterly disillusioned and

  recognizing that the philosophy of the Republic had to be grounded on more than

  vague humanitarian sentiment. On this project, beginning with the Essais de critique

  générale and ending with Science et la morale, he was to spend the best part of the next

  twenty years.154

  Nor was Renouvier to be alone in this, as there can be no doubt that a significant

  transformation in the thinking of republicans took place during the years of

  Napoleon III’s Second Empire. Moreover, that transformation was diverse in

  both content and intellectual inspiration, republicanism drawing upon a wide

  variety of ideological and political influences.155 By way of illumination, we can

  turn our attention to the writings of Jules Barni as a guide to what arguably became

  the dominant republican position on the related issues of rights, liberty, and

  equality.156

  Like Renouvier, Barni spent a significant proportion of these years engrossed in

  the study of Immanuel Kant, producing a series of commentaries and translations

  of his major works. He did much of this during the 1850s in what amounted to

  self-imposed internal exile––having resigned from his teaching position following

 

‹ Prev