Revolution and the Republic

Home > Other > Revolution and the Republic > Page 14
Revolution and the Republic Page 14

by Jeremy Jennings

151 Recognition of the right to a free education (as well as the surveillance of all educational

  institutions by the State) was accepted through Article 9 of the 1848 Constitution. It was a source

  of immediate controversy. The liberal Catholic Comte de Montalembert described it as a form of

  ‘intellectual communism’: Le Moniteur Universel, 263 (19 Sept. 1848), 2497.

  152 Renouvier, Manuel Républicain, 214.

  153 Le Moniteur Universel, 257 (13 Sept. 1848), 2418.

  154 See Blais, Au principe de la République. See Charles Renouvier and François Pillon, ‘La doctrine

  républicaine, ou ce que nous sommes, ce que nous voulons’, La Critique philosophique, politique,

  scientifique, littéraire, 1 (1872); repr. in Stéphane Douailler et al., Philosophie, France, XIXe siècle

  (1994), 727–53.

  155 See Philip Nord, The Republican Moment: Struggles for Democracy in Nineteenth-Century France

  (Cambridge, Mass., 1995).

  156 On Barni, see Sudhir Hazareesingh, Intellectual Founders of the Republic: Five Studies in

  Nineteenth-Century French Political Thought (Oxford, 2001), 227–80.

  Rights, Liberty, and Equality

  61

  Louis Napoleon’s coup d’état in 1851––and then during the following decade in

  Switzerland, where he held an academic post. With the fall of the Second Empire

  he returned to France, later to secure election as a parliamentary representative for

  the Somme in 1872, and again in 1876. He died in 1878 and, despite his major

  contribution to republican thinking, was quickly forgotten, even by his fellow

  republicans.

  The similarity with Renouvier was not limited to their mutual admiration for

  Kantian philosophy, however. Like the latter, in 1872 Barni published his own

  Manuel Républicain.157 This text built upon Barni’s earlier La Morale dans la

  démocratie,158 published in 1868. Barni did not disguise his desire to escape from

  the misplaced equation of politics with the pursuit of virtue. This, he announced,

  ‘had been the error of the republics and the philosophers of antiquity’.159 More-

  over, it had been perpetuated by such eminent eighteenth-century philosophers as

  Rousseau, Mably, and ‘even Montesquieu’. Each, in Barni’s view, had not em-

  braced ‘the modern spirit’ which, he argued, ‘gives greater autonomy and liberty to

  the individual conscience, frees it from the intemperate yoke of politics and

  encloses the latter within the limits of the law’.160 It followed that the first duty

  of the State was to respect and protect the ‘natural rights’ of all citizens and

  therefore that liberty should be defined in terms of the absence of arbitrary restraint

  and interference upon the actions of individuals.161 ‘Liberty in its essence’, Barni

  wrote, ‘consists of the faculty that allows man to direct and to organize himself, in a

  word to be his own master, and not to be the property of someone else.’162 He gave

  this definition of liberty further description by specifying that it included the ability

  of each person ‘to think and to speak freely, to work freely and to make free use of

  the fruits of his labour’.163 Displaying the distance separating him from the Jacobin

  tradition, he commented that to curtail liberty in order to protect it was just an

  excuse for arbitrary power. ‘It is time’, Barni wrote, ‘to finish with these theories

  which, in the name of securing liberty in the future, only serve the interests of

  tyranny today or of despotism tomorrow.’164 The proper role of government was

  not to govern men but to teach them to govern themselves.

  There are at least three features of Barni’s account of republican liberty that merit

  further comment. Each tells us something about how republicanism was to develop

  in the years following the establishment of the Third Republic in 1870. The first is

  Barni’s oft-repeated conviction that liberty must not be confused with either

  ‘licence’ or ‘fanaticism’. ‘There is no republic worthy of its name and that will

  last without the proper habits of liberty’, he wrote.165 Liberty, in other words, had

  to be informed by a comprehensive set of republican values, values that obliged

  every citizen to seek personal moral improvement and to respect the dignity of

  others. The conservative, not to say bourgeois, character of this moralized vision of

  157 Jules Barni, Manuel Républicain (1872).

  158 Jules Barni, La Morale dans la démocratie (1868). See also Jules Barni, Ce que doit être la République

  (Amiens, 1872).

  159 Barni, La Morale, 13.

  160 Ibid. 14–15.

  161 Ibid. 143.

  162 Barni, Manuel Républicain, 2.

  163 Ibid.

  164 Barni, La Morale, 166.

  165 Barni, Manuel Républicain, 103.

  62

  Rights, Liberty, and Equality

  liberty was shown in the central place allotted to hard work, sobriety, chastity,

  the sanctity of the family, and respect for the law. Next, rejecting the arguments

  of Pierre-Joseph Proudhon, Barni unequivocally included the right to property as

  one of the fundamental rights of the individual. ‘Not only has a man the right to

  make use of his own physical person’, he wrote, ‘but he also has that of working as he

  wishes, as long as he respects the same right in others.’166 The right of the individual

  to own property, Barni contended, was the condition and source of the prosperity of

  society and it must be respected by government. Charity and self-help, rather than

  ‘the organization of work by the State’, would provide the best solutions to the misery

  of the poor. Recognition of the right to work would only lead society to ‘despotism

  and ruin’. Thirdly, Barni extended his definition of liberty of thought to include

  ‘liberty of conscience’ and from this concluded that a state religion was an affront

  to such a liberty. Two things followed from this. Most obviously, Barni endorsed

  the call for a complete separation of Church and State. Next, he placed renewed

  emphasis on the importance of the provision of primary (and, where appropriate,

  secondary) education by the Republic. Taking up the theme announced by

  Renouvier, the first obligation of the Republic was to provide instruction for the

  people. Without this––as the disastrous experience of the Second Empire of

  Napoleon III all-too-vividly demonstrated––the liberty granted the people through

  universal suffrage would become an instrument of domination and despotism.167

  How did these arguments have an impact upon Barni’s views on equality?

  If liberty was ‘the first principle of republican government’, then equality was its

  ‘necessary corollary’.168 What this entailed, he argued, was equality before the law,

  civil equality, and political equality. It meant ‘no more privileges, no more distinc-

  tions, no more castes, and no more classes’ but it did not necessitate ‘the strict

  levelling of all wealth’, as this would denote the end of liberty.169 The first duty of

  the citizen was to respect the law and this was to be accompanied by a willingness to

  subordinate personal self-interest before the common good. The good citizen was

  to display ‘the virtue of abnegation’. As Barni commented, ‘the love of equality does

  not denote a hatred of all superiority’. It was not d
riven by envy.170 Not once in

  this analysis, as Barni acknowledged, was the word socialism mentioned, although

  ‘the social question’ was not forgotten. The aim was to ensure that ‘the workers and

  the bosses, the poor and the rich, no longer form two antagonistic classes in society,

  as too often occurs today’.171 The solution lay in ‘good will’, ‘individual effort and a

  sense of solidarity’. The amelioration of the condition of the workers, in other

  words, rested less upon the actions of the State than upon the sentiment of

  fraternity, of belonging to the same family and loving each other as brothers.

  ‘Citizens’, Barni proclaimed, ‘be human towards each other; the observance of

  this simple maxim will smooth out many difficulties and, better than the army, will

  secure social peace.’172

  166 Barni, La Morale, 150.

  167 See Barni, Ce que doit être la République.

  168 Barni, Manuel Républicain, 3.

  169 Ibid. 5.

  170 Ibid. 103.

  171 Ibid. 112.

  172 Ibid. 105.

  Rights, Liberty, and Equality

  63

  Yet the most telling example of Barni’s willingness to accommodate his under-

  standing of equality to the forces of social conservatism was shown in his statement

  that equal political rights should be denied to women. As he explained: women

  were the equal of men ‘as moral beings’ and everything should be done ‘to

  emancipate women from all degrading tutelage’. This meant removing the ‘injus-

  tices’ of the Napoleonic Civil Code. However, Barni went on, ‘in general the life

  appropriate to women is not political life but private life’. ‘Their proper place’, he

  explained, ‘is not in the public forum but in the domestic home’, supporting their

  husbands and caring for their children. In any case, direct involvement in politics was

  unnecessary as women possessed their ‘natural representatives and deputies in the

  form of their fathers, their brothers, their husbands and their sons’.173

  Here then was a definition of rights, liberty, and equality that would come to

  predominate amongst republicans from the 1870s onwards. How can this long

  process of evolution be summarized? Republicans like Barni sought to detach the

  language of rights and of liberty from the threat of tyranny and dictatorship (in

  the shape of Jacobinism and Bonapartism) and thus to ally it to a stable, property-

  owning democracy. It provided republicans with a political programme that could

  appeal to an emerging new middle class and to a conservative peasantry. Just as

  importantly, it sought to delegitimize radical and socialist understandings of liberty

  within republicanism. Within this discourse, equality came to mean an equality

  of rights and (in theory at least) an equality of opportunity but not an equality of

  outcome. It was understood as civil equality (principally equality before the law)

  rather than as an equality of wealth. In the key area of schooling, it meant that all

  pupils, irrespective of their beliefs, were to be treated in an equal manner and,

  increasingly, that education was to be perceived as the primary route to personal

  emancipation and autonomy. Having removed all property qualifications from the

  franchise, political equality existed in the form of universal male suffrage. Women

  were not to enjoy rights equal to those of men. Despite this grave anomaly, the

  State was under an obligation to treat all citizens equally. Inequalities of treatment

  could only be justified in terms of the general interest.

  What followed in the final decades of the nineteenth century were a set of

  measures intended to turn this vision into a reality. The republicans, once they had

  secured political control of the Republic after 1879, introduced a series of reforms

  designed to enhance the liberty of the individual citizen and to extend social justice.

  These covered such areas as freedom of speech and of the press, the right to hold

  public meetings, as well as the key reforms granting the right to join a trade union

  and the right to strike.174 These measures were accompanied by legislation reform-

  ing the labour code, regulating hours of work, introducing industrial injuries

  insurance, and encouraging arbitration in industrial disputes. Legislation enacted

  173 Barni, La Morale, 33–49, 126–38. Philip Nord shows how republicans reacted against the

  infamous immorality and corruption associated with the imperial court: ‘To the wiles of the

  imperial coquette, republicans counterposed the virtues of the femme de foyer’, Nord, Republican

  Moment, 229.

  174 See Jean-Marie Mayeur, Les Débuts de la IIIe République 1871–1898 (1973), 108–110.

  64

  Rights, Liberty, and Equality

  in the early 1880s introduced free and compulsory secular education in state

  schools. For these reasons this period has sometimes been regarded as the ‘golden

  age’ of republican liberties.

  A less glowing picture is revealed in Jean-Pierre Machelon’s La République contre

  les libertés?175 In his account, the pursuit of stability and order meant that striking

  workers, protesting anarchists, religious congregations, and civil servants felt the full

  force of state repression as the fundamental liberties of certain categories of

  individuals were disregarded in the name of social peace. The result was growing

  disillusionment and discontent amongst the working-class movement as well as

  renewed hostility towards the Republic from the Catholic Church.

  The preoccupation with social peace also produced its quintessential ideological

  expression in the shape of the doctrine of solidarité.176 As one of the doctrine’s

  supporters, the philosopher Célestin Bouglé, was to comment: solidarisme was, in

  effect, to become ‘the official philosophy of the Third Republic’.177 Seeking to steer

  a mid-way course between free-market liberalism and collectivist socialism, its

  emphasis fell upon encouraging the practices of association, cooperation, and

  mutuality. Fiercely secular in orientation, it saw an education freed from the

  influence of the Catholic Church as the best means of developing both the moral

  and civic conscience of the individual citizen.178

  The most famous exponent of the doctrine of solidarité was Léon Bourgeois.179

  Bourgeois was no minor figure. Amongst his many public offices, he was minister

  for public instruction between 1890 and 1892 and again in 1898. In 1896, the year

  in which he published Solidarité, he formed his own short-lived government.

  He later went on to be president of both the Chamber of Deputies and the Senate.

  Drawing upon the work of philosopher Alfred Fouillée and in particular his

  La Science sociale contemporaine,180 Bourgeois’s resolutely scientific argument

  was that the concept of solidarité should replace that of fraternité in republican

  thinking, for the simple reason that, while the latter was abstract and meta-

  physical, the former could be empirically grounded. The ‘law of solidarity’, he

  believed, demonstrated the ‘reciprocal dependence’ that existed between human

  beings, and as such was ‘universal’. Accordingly, from an observation of situations

  of reciprocity it would be possible to establish a ‘theory of right
s and duties’ that

  was ‘neither abstract nor subjective but concrete, objective, in line with the

  175 Jean-Pierre Machelon, La République contre les libertés? (1976). This is not a view fully shared by

  Philip Nord. ‘[T]he Third Republic’, he argues, was ‘a democratic regime that sprang from and then

  nurtured a resurrected civil society’: see Nord, Republican Moment, 246–53. See also Pierre

  Rosanvallon, La Démocratie inachevée: Histoire de la souveraineté du peuple on France (2000), 313–35.

  176 See Jean-Fabian Spitz, Le Moment républicain en France (2005) and Marie-Claude Blais, La

  Solidarité: Histoire d’une idée (2007).

  177 Le Solidarisme (1907), 1. See also Alfred Croiset (ed.), Essai d’une philosophie de la solidarité:

  Conférences et discussions (1902).

  178 See Ferdinand Buisson, La Foi laïque: Extraits de discours et d’écrits (1878–1911) (1912).

  179 Léon Bourgeois, Solidarité (1896).

  180 (1880). See also Fouillée, La Propriété sociale et la démocratie (1884) and Les Éléments

  sociologiques de la moralité (1905).

  Rights, Liberty, and Equality

  65

  necessities of nature, and thus definitive’.181 All individuals would come to recog-

  nize the mutual debt they owed towards each other and through this it would be

  possible to secure an ‘equitable distribution’ of benefits and costs, advantages and

  obligations. Thus, Bourgeois concluded, ‘the doctrine of solidarity appears as the

  development of the philosophy of the eighteenth century and as the culmination of

  the social and political theory of the French Revolution’.182

  What this meant, as he subsequently made clear on numerous occasions, would

  have greatly pleased all those who in the 1790s had voiced their doubts about the

  political wisdom of using the language of rights. The Revolution, Bourgeois argued,

  had given men their liberty and had made them equal in rights but it had taken a

  further century for people to realize that ‘this liberty would not be assured to all

  if everyone, not recognizing a limit to their own liberty and profiting from the

  personal strength and advantages given to them by chance, made use of liberty in a

  selfish fashion’. It was therefore necessary, Bourgeois declared, ‘to complete the

  declaration of the rights of man by adding a declaration of duties’.183

 

‹ Prev