Book Read Free

Revolution and the Republic

Page 26

by Jeremy Jennings


  their decline into ‘a savage state’, a war made more destructive by the fact that men

  were not born, as philosophy proclaimed, equal in rights but unequal in strength.

  ‘The necessary effect’, Bonald wrote, ‘of the increase of the human race is to bring

  men closer together; the necessary effect of the unleashing of their wills and their

  strength is to destroy them’.

  How, then, could these conflicting and opposed wills be brought into harmony

  so as to ensure the predominance of what Bonald termed ‘the general will of

  society’? That general will, he insisted, could not be interpreted as either the

  36 Louis de Bonald, ‘Théorie du pouvoir politique et religieux dans la société civile, démontrée par

  le raisonnement et par l’histoire’, in Œuvres complètes de M. de Bonald (1864), i. 121–954.

  37 Ibid. 121.

  38 Ibid. 142.

  Sovereignty, Social Contract, and Luxury

  119

  particular will of one man, or indeed as ‘the will of all men taken together’. Nor

  should the general will be mistaken for ‘the will of the people’. ‘The will of a people

  in their entirety, even if it is unanimous’, Bonald continued, ‘is only the sum of

  its particular wills’, each of which was necessarily selfish and destructive. The truth

  of this distinction between ‘the will of all’ and ‘the general will’, Bonald twice

  contended, had even been recognized, if only to be ignored, by Rousseau himself. It

  represented ‘the most complete refutation of his work’.

  Rousseau was thus charged with deploying a rhetoric of constant self-contradic-

  tion. But it was precisely this rhetoric that had been deployed by the revolutionaries

  as they set out to create a republic. Under such a regime, Bonald argued, society

  became nothing more than a collection of individuals and accordingly the general

  will was dissolved into the sum of individual and particular wills, with individual

  pleasure and happiness, not general well-being, becoming its goal. In these circum-

  stances, society progressively disintegrated, reverting back to its ‘primitive state’

  where men sought only to secure their own dominance. To such a state had France

  been reduced during the Revolution, with ‘hunger, misery, and death’ everywhere

  made visible.

  Indeed, in Bonald’s eyes, France had become the very ‘negation’ of a properly

  constituted society. ‘There arose’, he proclaimed,

  a single power and a constitution came into existence. But, by God, what a power and

  what a constitution! It has its fundamental laws and its public religion: it is the cult of

  Marat. It has its single and general power: it is death. It has its social superiors: they are

  the Jacobins, the priests of this cult and the agents of this power. This power has a

  representative: it is the instrument of torture. This monarch has its ministers: they are

  its executioners. It has its subjects: they are its victims. Nothing like it has ever been

  seen on the earth before.39

  Here, then, was the result of the philosophical confusion sown by Rousseau’s

  theory of the general will. But the sting in the tale of Bonald’s case against Rousseau

  was that if the popular will could not be said to constitute the general will, then the

  will of the monarch certainly could. ‘It is clear’, Bonald wrote, ‘that, in a constituted

  society, the monarch is the law, since the law is the expression of the general will

  which he in turn dispenses and represents: in his capacity as monarch therefore he

  could not wish to violate the law, that is to say, to wish to destroy what the general

  will of society wishes to preserve’. Rousseauian logic was thus turned on its head,

  with the monarch, rather than the people, embodying a general will which

  seemingly could not err.

  Thus, Bonald’s overall assessment of Rousseau’s achievements was disarmingly

  straightforward. He had, Bonald declared, ‘sacrificed society for man, history for his

  own opinions, and the universe for Geneva’.40 Was it, however, as simple as that?

  Bonald began his Théorie du pouvoir politique et religieux dans la société civile by

  stating unapologetically that his text frequently cited the works of both Montes-

  quieu and Rousseau. How, he asked, could one write about politics without

  39 Ibid. 304.

  40 Ibid. 129.

  120

  Sovereignty, Social Contract, and Luxury

  referring to De l’Esprit des lois and Du Contrat social, when, even if both were full of

  errors, they presented ‘a synthesis of all past and present politics’? For all Bonald’s

  desire to see an atheistic revolution brought to an end and a hereditary monarchy

  restored, in other words, he nevertheless reluctantly had to acknowledge the scale of

  Rousseau’s achievement.

  As might be clear, Bonald associated philosophy in general with the desire to

  destroy religion. The doctrine of the sovereignty of the people, on this view, by

  ‘dethroning God’, led inevitably to atheism. Writing after the Restoration of the

  monarchy, and thus after the tide of revolutionary change appeared to have turned,

  the young Félicité de Lamennais was to adopt a strikingly similar attitude. To those

  unfamiliar with the details of Lamennais’s religious and political itinerary this might

  seem surprising because, if Lamennais is now remembered, it is almost always as the

  disciple of democracy and the defender of the oppressed, as the excommunicated

  priest whose radicalism was voiced under the banner of ‘Dieu et la liberté’. Yet for

  the royalist Lamennais of the Essai sur l’indifférence en matière de la religion, published

  in 1817,41 everything was clear: the Reformation had given birth to Descartes,

  who himself had engendered the philosophy of the eighteenth century, which in

  turn had produced 1789, 1793, and the Revolution’s catalogue of crimes. In this

  woeful sequence, the atheistic doctrines of Rousseau––described by Lamennais as the

  ‘Genevan sophist’––had played a very significant role.

  The opening sentence of Lamennais’s text made the message plain. The unhappiest

  of centuries was not one that was attracted by error but one which neglected and

  scorned the truth. The real enemy was indifference because this ultimately was

  ‘incompatible with order and the very existence of society’. Locke, Kant, and Descartes

  were in turn taken to task for their contribution to our scepticism whilst our salvation

  was deemed to lie in a divinely inspired sensus communis embodying our collective

  certitudes. Philosophy, by denying the mysteries of Christianity, destroyed morality

  and undermined the bases of religious and political authority in society. Rousseau,

  Lamennais conceded, was not an atheist but the force of his argument was that all

  religions were equally good and equally true, thus relegating faith to a matter of climate

  and degrees of latitude. The way was then open for an acceptance of all vices and all

  crimes and what Lamennais described as ‘a vast shipwreck of all truths and all virtues’.

  It is here that we again see the near-obligatory recognition of Rousseau’s literary

  talents––‘Never’, Lamennais wrote, ‘did anyone make such skilful use of words’––but

  the result nevertheless was ‘
a shapeless assemblage of incoherencies, absurdities, and

  contradictions’.42

  Rousseau the deist, in other words, had led us unerringly towards uncertainty and

  indifference and thence to the destruction of society itself. But the same disastrous

  results were also obtained by another dimension of Rousseau’s philosophy: contract

  theory. ‘Never’, Lamennais commented, ‘was there a doctrine so absurd, so deadly

  and so degrading as this.’43 What were the grounds of Lamennais’s dissent?

  41 Félicité de Lamennais, Essai sur l’indifférence en matière de la religion (1817).

  42 Ibid. 95.

  43 Ibid. 328.

  Sovereignty, Social Contract, and Luxury

  121

  In the first instance, no society had been seen to originate in this way and it was a

  ridiculous idea to imagine that society owed its existence to a random collection of

  individuals meeting by chance ‘in the woods’! Second, every pact implied sanctions

  to ensure that it was observed but where in Rousseau’s writings was a convincing

  description of these sanctions to be found? There was nothing, Lamennais argued,

  to stop people from reclaiming their sovereignty. Far from creating the ‘tranquillity

  of order’ the contract would only establish a conflict between particular wills and

  between sovereign and subject, with force alone as the final arbiter. ‘When the force

  of the sovereign prevails,’ Lamennais wrote, ‘one has despotism; when the force of

  the people carries the day, one has anarchy.’44 Nor was Lamennais convinced that

  anything changed with the signing of the social contract. Each individual remained

  as he was before, sovereign of himself and independent of all wills but his own,

  and therefore subject to nothing else but the will of the strongest. Moreover,

  Rousseau could come up with no better reason for adhering to the contract than

  self-interest. On this fragile basis, Lamennais contended, did philosophy seek to

  ground society.

  The criticism did not stop there. Once the doctrine of the social contract had

  been accepted by the people it had turned society into one vast arena where only

  private interests dominated. What Rousseau understood by liberty was in reality

  only a form of servitude, characterized by a hatred of ‘all institutions, all laws, and

  all social distinctions’. Governments acted solely upon the basis of self-preservation

  and self-aggrandizement and much the same was true of the masses. ‘If ’, Lamennais

  wrote, the latter ‘are allowed for one minute to sense their power they will abuse it

  in order to destroy everything and will run headlong towards anarchy believing all

  the time that they are marching towards liberty’. Armed with the theory of the

  general will and the belief that it was always right, ‘the people had no need to justify

  their acts; they could legitimately do whatever they wished, even destroy or

  annihilate themselves’.45 In short, the same doctrine which had dethroned God

  and had dethroned kings, had in turn dethroned man and reduced him to the level

  of an animal. Turmoil followed turmoil, revolution followed revolution, and a

  country which had been the ‘ornament’ and the ‘queen’ of Europe had been

  reduced to providing the human race with ‘a great and terrible lesson’.

  Lamennais’s conclusion was unambiguous and placed Rousseau at the heart of

  the century’s ills. Once philosophy had told man that his reason was the source

  of truth and that his will was the source of power, truth became nothing more than

  what appealed to his inclinations and power was reduced to naked force. The

  members of society, with their equal rights and their contrary interests, would

  destroy themselves down to the last man were it not for the fact that the strongest

  would enslave the weakest and would make his will the sole law and the sole

  standard of justice. ‘Such’, Lamennais wrote, ‘is the necessary result of the absurd

  social contract thought up by philosophy, and which is in reality only a blasphemy

  declaring war against society and against God.’46 Upon the ruins of religion, society

  44 Ibid. 330.

  45 Ibid. 354.

  46 Ibid. 345.

  122

  Sovereignty, Social Contract, and Luxury

  would be consumed by divorce, adultery, selfishness, corruption, barbarism, luxury,

  and cupidity, descending into nothingness.

  The sadness in all of this is that, as the papacy remained true to its conception

  of the unity of throne and altar and as it allied itself increasingly with Europe’s

  temporal powers, Lamennais found himself ever more drawn to the sufferings

  of Europe’s Catholic peoples and from this onwards to a defence of liberty of

  conscience, liberty of the press, and liberty of education. He supported the Revolu-

  tion of 1830, only then (as we shall see later) to be quickly disillusioned by the July

  Monarchy’s failure to support similar uprisings across Europe. He was then to find

  himself in the liberal and republican camp. This should not lead us to forget the

  sustained ferocity of his assault upon Rousseau.

  The response of those who most forcefully articulated the counter-revolutionary

  rejoinder to Rousseau’s writings was therefore not without ambivalence. They too

  felt the power and persuasiveness of his ideas, even though they had no doubts

  about what had been their profoundly destabilizing consequences for France. If

  they thought that the idea of a social contract was a ridiculous invention, they could

  most of all not forgive Rousseau for stealing sovereignty from God and giving it to

  the people. Like Rousseau, however, they believed that sovereignty should be

  neither limited nor divided. Was the response of the writers of French liberalism

  any less ambivalent?

  Liberalism in France was a multifaceted affair.47 Stated simply, with the out-

  break of the Revolution there were those who were prepared to clothe their calls for

  reform within the doctrine of natural rights and with this came a willingness to

  speak of a pact or contract as the origin of civil society. One example of this was

  Pierre Daunou’s Essai sur la constitution,48 published in 1793. Another was Pierre-

  Louis Roederer’s imposing Cours d’organisation sociale, published in the same

  year.49 If anything the prevailing influence in both cases was Lockean rather than

  Rousseauian, the emphasis falling upon the contract as a means of protecting pre-

  existing rights (and especially the right to property). Roederer, for example, stated

  that: ‘When the needs of men have made known their natural rights to them and

  led them to unite together, they enter a contract of union and this is the social pact;

  they subsequently draw up the conditions of their union and from this civil law is

  born. The social pact and civil law are therefore only guarantees . . . of the natural

  rights of man.’50 Moreover, with time––and specifically with the radicalization of

  the language of rights which accompanied the rise of the Jacobins––the enthusiasm

  for such a style of argument waned considerably. Writers such as Daunou and

  Roederer, as we saw earlier, became associated with the group known as the

  Idéologues, and with this, along with their colleagues Cabanis and Destutt de


  Tracy, became increasingly preoccupied with the need to establish and preserve

  47 See Lucien Jaume, L’Individu effacé: Ou le paradoxe du libéralisme français (1997).

  48 Pierre Daunou, Essai sur la constitution (1793).

  49 Pierre-Louis Roederer, ‘Cours d’organisation sociale’, in Œuvres complètes (1859), viii. 129–305.

  50 Ibid. 137.

  Sovereignty, Social Contract, and Luxury

  123

  social peace and order. For men such as these it was to be the maxim of utility,

  rather than anything to be found in the writings of Rousseau, that was to act as their

  guide.

  This is not to say that Rousseau now ceased to trouble the consciences of those

  who sought, against the odds, to keep alive the flame of French liberal opinion.

  Rousseau continued to do so and this was primarily because of the principal

  theoretical presupposition upon which the social contract was thought to rest:

  popular sovereignty. Here we can again turn to the arguments provided by

  Rousseau’s fellow Swiss Protestant, Benjamin Constant. Writing in De l’esprit de

  conquête et de l’usurpation, published in 1814, Constant commented: ‘It will be

  apparent, I believe, that the subtle metaphysics of Du Contrat social can only serve

  today to supply weapons and pretexts to all kinds of tyranny, that of one man,

  that of several or that of all, to oppression either organized under legal forms

  or exercised through popular violence.’51 In the later Commentaire sur l’ouvrage

  de Filangieri he spoke of the ‘terrible consequences and incalculable dangers’ of

  Rousseau’s theories.52 The unpublished text, written between 1806 and 1810 and

  which like Constant’s famous work of 1815 carried the title Principes de politique,

  was even more specific, attributing ‘all the misfortunes of the French Revolution’

  to ‘his eloquent and absurd theory’. ‘It would be only too easy to show’, Constant

  wrote, ‘that the most erroneous sophisms of the most ardent apostles of the Terror

  were nothing else than perfectly legitimate conclusions drawn from the principles

  of Rousseau.’53 Nevertheless, he was quick to add: ‘I do not wish to join Rousseau’s

  detractors. At present they are numerous enough . . . He was the first to make a

  sense of our rights popular; his voice has awakened generous hearts and indepen-

 

‹ Prev