Book Read Free

Revolution and the Republic

Page 51

by Jeremy Jennings


  amounts to the same thing.’ The philosophes, on this view, were all monks: they had

  neither affections, nor fathers, nor children.

  As previously observed, in the ideas of Antoine de Rivarol (and, as we now see, of

  his less famous brother) can be distinguished prefigurations of what were to become

  central themes raised by theorists of counter-revolution in France from the early

  1790s onwards. From this perspective, there was much to be admired in Burke’s

  account of the Revolution. Above all, he had perceived the frightening originality of

  the events that were unfolding and, from the outset, had seen the spirit of

  innovation and of philosophy that would drive the Revolution forward towards

  its cataclysmic and destructive conclusion.

  Yet, for all the popularity and commercial success of Burke’s account, there were

  limits to the admiration felt by the French counter-revolutionaries for Burke, limits

  that were to become most obvious in the writings of Joseph de Maistre and Louis de

  Bonald. Despite their agreement on the pernicious influence of the atheistic and

  fanatical philosophe sect, they did not share Burke’s appreciation of traditional

  English liberties nor his attachment to representative institutions. Least of all

  were they prepared to accept the exemplary character and role that Burke attributed

  to English history. This position was to be held by France as the eldest daughter of

  the Church. So Burke was largely to fade from view in subsequent counter-

  revolutionary histories. Indeed, Burke was to be absent from most French histories

  of the Revolution written in the nineteenth and twentieth centuries.4 The prevail-

  ing view was simply that Burke had misunderstood the nature of the French

  Revolution. Jules Michelet, for example, referred to ‘his infamous book, wild

  with rage, full of lies and cheap insults’.5 Although more measured in tone, Alexis

  de Tocqueville was of a similar opinion. Burke, he believed, had been mesmerized

  by events and, as a consequence, had failed to see what was before his very eyes. The

  monarchy had sealed its own fate. Thus, Burke’s unapologetic defence of the old

  order, of its institutions and its manners, could have no purchase upon a French

  society long accustomed to the uniformity and administrative centralization of the

  absolute monarchy.6

  Nevertheless, Burke himself (and not without good cause) clearly felt that his

  views chimed with those of some of the Revolution’s very first opponents in France.

  In May 1797, for example, he wrote a short letter to the exiled Abbé Augustin

  4 Furet, ‘Burke ou la fin d’une seule histoire de l’Europe’, in Furet, La Révolution française (2007),

  902.

  5 Histoire de la Révolution française (1979), i. 341–2.

  6 See Robert T. Gannett, jun., Tocqueville Unveiled: The Historian and his Sources for the Old Regime

  and the Revolution (Chicago, 2003), 57–77.

  240

  History, Revolution, and Terror

  Barruel.7 ‘I cannot easily express to you’, Burke commented, ‘how much I am

  instructed and delighted by the first Volume of your History of Jacobinism. The

  whole of the wonderful narrative is supported by documents and proofs with

  the most juridical regularity and exactness.’ It was admirable in every way, Burke

  continued, and, to the extent that he could judge French style, ‘the language is of the

  first water’. He also testified from personal experience to the veracity of Barruel’s

  argument, reporting that he had known ‘five of your principal conspirators’.

  Born in 1741, Barruel was a Jesuit priest and was now serving as chaplain to the

  Princess de Conti in England. He had left France in 1792, shortly before the

  September massacres, having denounced the Revolution as early as 1789 in a text

  entitled Le Patriote véridique, ou Discours sur les vrais causes de la Révolution actuelle.

  Whilst in England he had collected material for his Histoire du clergé pendant la

  Révolution française, and there attacked the Civil Constitution of the Clergy as

  being blasphemous and heretical and as a prelude to the ‘persecution, massacres and

  deportation of the French clergy’. In both works could be discerned the lineaments

  of an explanation of the Revolution which he was to develop at greater length in the

  book referred to by Burke, his Mémoires pour servir à l’histoire du jacobinisme:8 the

  Revolution was the product of a conspiracy led by the philosophes against both

  throne and altar.9

  The opening paragraphs clearly stated Barruel’s thesis and purpose. It was an

  error, he contended, to believe that the Revolution was the result of a set of

  unforeseen and unpredictable circumstances. Rather, ‘supported by facts and

  armed with proofs’, he believed that it could be shown that ‘everything in this

  French Revolution, including its most heinous crimes, was planned, premeditated,

  coordinated, resolved, decided upon. Everything was the result of the darkest

  villainy, since everything had been prepared and led by men who for long had

  hatched conspiracies in secret societies and who knew how to choose and hasten

  those moments most propitious for plots’.10 Circumstances had provided a pretext,

  as ‘the great cause’ of the Revolution, of its crimes and atrocities, was to be found in

  ‘plots hatched well beforehand’. Barruel’s intention, therefore, was to unmask this

  conspiracy. In broad outline, he believed that it had come in three forms. First, long

  before the Revolution, had been the conspiracy of the philosophers against God

  and against Christianity in all its forms. It had been a conspiracy led by the ‘sophists

  of unbelief and impiety’. Next had come a conspiracy led by ‘the sophists of

  rebellion’ directed against all kings. Finally, there had emerged a conspiracy of

  anarchy combined against all religion and all government, against society, and

  against property. It was, Barruel concluded, ‘this coalition of the adepts of impiety,

  7 The Correspondence of Edmund Burke, ed. R. B. McDowell and John A. Woods (Cambridge,

  1970), ix. 319–20.

  8 Barruel’s text was originally publ. in London and Hamburg; references are to the 1973 edn.,

  2 vols.

  9 See e.g. Le Patriote véridique (1789), 20–1 and Histoire du clergé (London, 1793), 3. For a

  refutation of Barruel’s position see J. J. Mounier, De l’Influence attribuée aux Philosophes, aux Francs-

  maçons et aux Illuminés sur la Révolution de France (Tubingen, 1801).

  10 Barruel, Mémoires, i. 42.

  History, Revolution, and Terror

  241

  of the adepts of rebellion, of the adepts of anarchy, which had formed the Jacobin

  clubs’.11

  The details of Barruel’s account of this philosophical conspiracy are intriguing.

  For the philosophes to attain their ends, it had been necessary for public opinion to

  be corrupted: only then could the altar fall beneath the axe. This had been achieved

  in a series of stages. It began with ‘the most infallible of means’: the Encyclopédie.

  Then came the eradication of the Jesuits and, after this, of all religious orders. There

  next emerged ‘Voltaire’s colony’, the group of like-minded people who had con-

  gregated around Voltaire in exile. More influenti
al still had been the corruption of

  France’s literary establishment, paving the way for a ‘general apostasy’. This was

  followed by a ‘flood of anti-Christian books’ and the successful attempt to hide the

  conspiracy in the ‘name of toleration’. Liberty of the press, Barruel contended, was

  especially dangerous in France, as even the simplest bourgeois wished to have his

  library. In consequence there appeared a new generation equipped only to mouth

  the platitudes of Voltaire and Rousseau and ready to articulate their enthusiasm for

  revolution. ‘Men of letters without religion’, Barruel observed, ‘are the most

  depraved and dangerous group of citizens.’12

  To impiety towards religion was adjoined the spirit of rebellion towards the king.

  Here, somewhat unusually, Barruel laid much of the blame at the feet of Mon-

  tesquieu. It had been Montesquieu who had taught the French that the guiding

  principle of republics was virtue and that monarchies were despotic and arbitrary.

  Similarly, he had encouraged the French to admire the constitution of England and

  to see France’s own government as a ‘painful and shameful slavery’. His greatest

  error, however, was to fail to see that, if the principle of representation could lead in

  one country to liberty, in another—as the calling of the Estates-General had

  demonstrated—it could produce anarchy and despotism. ‘It is to Montesquieu’,

  Barruel concluded, ‘that the French owe the entire system based upon the necessity

  of dividing up the sceptre of the king, of making the monarch dependent upon the

  multitude’ and therefore of turning Louis XVI into ‘un roi de théâtre’. Rousseau, by

  doing away with Montesquieu’s aristocratic intermediaries and by proclaiming the

  people to be both sovereign and infallible, had only completed the process,

  breaking ‘absolutely’ the sceptre of kings, nobles, and the rich.13 If, Barruel

  believed, the consequences of these doctrines were obvious to anyone who took

  the trouble to look, it had taken the conspiracy of the philosophes and their followers

  to put them into practice.

  The final, key ingredient of Barruel’s account focused upon the Freemasons, the

  friends and allies of the philosophical sect. With the Revolution of 1789, the

  Freemasons had poured out of their lodges and into the revolutionary sections

  and committees, determined to deliver the world from the ‘twin plagues’ of

  religious credulity and political tyranny. Yet, it had taken the emergence of the

  Jacobins—‘this monstrous association’ always insatiable for blood—to bring the

  conspiracy to its conclusion and to proclaim its zeal to change the face of the entire

  11 Ibid. 47.

  12 Ibid. 217.

  13 In Histoire du clergé, 139, Barruel refers to Rousseau as ‘the Hercules of the sophists’.

  242

  History, Revolution, and Terror

  universe. From this, Barruel believed, the following lesson should be learnt: the

  French Revolution was nothing but the product of a ‘fixed, steadfast, and unshak-

  able determination to everywhere overturn altar, throne, and society’.14

  A second, important theme underpinned Barruel’s account. Even as the Revolu-

  tion got under way there were those prepared to see France’s misfortunes as the

  work of a vengeful God and as the punishment of a sinful people.15 Barruel shared

  this providential perspective. For all that he recounted in vivid detail the murder

  and imprisonment of refractory priests, he readily recognized that the Church had

  become subject to abuse and corruption16 and that it had shown itself incapable of

  preventing the decline of public morals and of turning back the tide of impious

  philosophy. The Church too had its traitors, idlers, intriguers, and hypocrites, and

  for this France was being punished by an angry God. Deployed by Barruel (and

  others) as a prophetic warning of the calamities to come if France continued her

  sinful ways, divine retribution came subsequently to occupy a central place in

  explanations of the terrible events that had taken place.

  No one gave clearer voice to this fundamental part of the rhetoric of counter-

  revolution than Joseph de Maistre. He was born in 1753 in Savoy, then part of the

  kingdom of Piedmont-Sardinia. Despite professing a devout Catholic faith, for

  many years he was a Freemason and initially welcomed the Revolution in France as

  a partisan of moderate reform. He supported the campaign for the calling of the

  Estates-General but from the summer of 1789 came to have growing doubts about

  the course taken by events in what he described as the ‘warm mud’ of Paris.

  Certainly, the invasion (and subsequent annexation) of Savoy by France in Sep-

  tember 1792 convinced him of the need to rally to the royalist cause and it was

  from his exile in Switzerland that, with consummate rigour, he began to articulate

  the principles of monarchical and religious restoration. Nevertheless, in his first

  published writings he did not explore the possibilities of a providential explanation

  of the Revolution. In his Lettres d’un royaliste savoisien à ses compatriots,17 for

  example, he was content to suggest that the Revolution was not only ‘a unique

  event’ but that it was a consequence of the ‘rottenness’ of the monarchy and a

  mistaken ‘universal enchantment’ with the possibility of the regeneration of society.

  However, by the time Maistre published Considérations sur la France in 1797, he

  made no attempt to explain the Revolution in terms of political, social, or economic

  causes. ‘Never’, he averred, ‘has the Divinity shown itself so clearly in any human

  event.’18 The moral to be learnt was a simple one: since France had ‘used her

  influence to contradict her vocation and to demoralize Europe, we should not be

  surprised if she is brought back to her mission by terrible means’.19

  14 Barruel, Mémoires, ii. 526.

  15 Darrin M. McMahon, Enemies of the Enlightenment: The French Counter-Enlightenment and the

  Making of Modernity (Oxford, 2001), 56–8.

  16 See Barruel, Le Patriote véridique, 37–89.

  17 (Lyons and Paris, 1872): 1st publ. in 1793.

  18 Maistre, Considérations sur la France (1980), 34.

  19 Ibid.

  History, Revolution, and Terror

  243

  The opening sentence proclaimed a clear doctrine of political theodicy. ‘We are

  all’, Maistre announced, ‘attached to the throne of the Supreme Being by a supple

  chain which restrains us without enslaving us.’20 Men acted voluntarily and

  necessarily at the same time and nothing they did could disturb the ‘general

  plans’ of a God whose power was exercised effortlessly and irresistibly. Thus the

  most striking thing about the Revolution was that it was not men who led the

  Revolution but ‘the Revolution that uses men’. Each of the ‘rascals’ and ‘detestable

  tyrants’ who sought to direct its path were merely its ‘simple instruments’, men

  swept to power by what Maistre called the ‘revolutionary chariot’, only to be

  discarded ‘ignobly’ once they had ‘completed the measure of crime necessary to

  that phase of the Revolution’. Remarkably, Maistre extended this argument even to

  include the Jacobins, who alone had been able
to save France from dismemberment

  and annihilation by her enemies. ‘All life, all wealth, all power’, Maistre exclaimed,

  ‘was in the hands of the revolutionary authority, and this monstrous power, drunk

  with blood and success, the most frightful phenomenon that has ever been seen and

  the like of which will never be seen again, was both a horrible punishment for the

  French and the sole means of saving France.’21

  At no point did Maistre seek to diminish the extent of the sacrificial punishment

  that would be entailed by ‘this horrible effusion of human blood’. All those who

  willed the Revolution would justly become its victims and few were those who had

  not ‘willed all the follies, all the injustices, all the outrages that led up to the

  catastrophe [of Louis XVI’s execution] of 21 January [1793]’.22 Never before had

  so many people shared in such a sinful deed and each drop of blood would be repaid

  in torrents. ‘Perhaps four million Frenchmen’, Maistre wrote, ‘will pay with their

  heads for this great national crime of an anti-religious and anti-social insurrection

  crowned by a regicide.’23 Few would be innocent victims.

  Despite its ‘satanic’ and ‘diabolical’ character, order could be discerned in the

  disorder of the Revolution. With France’s enemies defeated and peace returned, the

  monarchy would be restored and the king would reascend to his throne ‘with all his

  pomp and power’. Purified by the travails of injustice and tyranny, the clergy would

  be regenerated and freed from the temptations of luxury and moral laxity. More-

  over, it was with absolute certainty that Maistre asserted that the Republic could

  not last, as divine sanction alone could establish durable institutions. Thus, if

  France had nothing to fear from counter-revolution—the king’s most pressing

  interest would be to ‘unite justice and mercy’—so also it was inevitable, as ‘all the

  monsters born of the Revolution have, apparently, laboured only for the monar-

  chy’.24 Maistre’s view, therefore, was that the Revolution was ‘one of the most

  astonishing spectacles that humanity has ever seen’. Through it would be secured

  the redemption not only of France but of European civilization more generally.

  Legitimist opinion was never in total agreement about the causes and character

 

‹ Prev