Revolution and the Republic

Home > Other > Revolution and the Republic > Page 53
Revolution and the Republic Page 53

by Jeremy Jennings


  chamber. The result was an ‘ill-fated constitution’, ‘good in its foundation’ but ‘bad

  in its superstructure’, and one incapable of protecting ‘the blessings of civil

  liberty’.48 How could this be explained? According to Madame de Staël, the

  National Assembly had been seized by ‘philosophical enthusiasm’, by a passion

  for abstract thinking at the expense of practical common sense. The deputies had

  shown themselves to be vain and cowardly, devoid of a sense of public duty.

  Consequently, they had been mistaken in 1791 to believe that the Revolution

  was finished and that liberty had been established. Rather, an abyss was about to

  open up beneath their feet.

  The logic of the next stage of the Revolution was all too clear. Arbitrary power

  was given new strength by the Revolution itself. The revolutionaries, in serving the

  people, sacrificed the happiness of each in the name of the common interest and the

  demands of equality. ‘To the animosity against the nobles and the priests’, Madame

  de Staël wrote, ‘succeeded a feeling of irritation against the landowners, next,

  47 Considérations sur la Révolution française (1983), 70.

  48 Ibid. 249.

  History, Revolution, and Terror

  249

  against talents, then even against personal beauty; finally against whatever was to be

  found of greatness or generosity in human nature.’49 Persecution led to the need for

  further persecution, the Terror driven forward by a monstrous frenzy of political

  fanaticism that, in taking away all restraints from the people, placed them in a

  position to commit every crime. It was a mistake, she believed, to imagine that the

  Jacobins had reduced government to a state of anarchy. ‘Never’, Madame de Staël

  observed, ‘has a stronger authority reigned over France, but it was a strange sort of

  power; springing from popular fanaticism it inspired dread in the very persons who

  commanded in its name, for they always feared being proscribed in turn by men

  who would go further than they in the daring boldness of persecution.’50 Not even

  Robespierre—whom Madame de Staël portrayed as a hypocrite interested only in

  power—felt entirely secure. It was ‘the most horrible period’ in French history.

  How had such violent behaviour been possible? How could the people of France

  have been so depraved? The answer, in Madame de Staël’s opinion, was to be found

  in centuries of superstition and arbitrary power. The French were what bad

  government had made them. They had acquired few ideas of justice and still

  believed that an enemy was not entitled to the protection of the law. Nevertheless,

  she argued, all countries and all peoples, including France and the French, were fit

  for liberty, and all, she believed, would attain it in their own way.

  This was where England figured in Madame de Staël’s argument, for, as she

  wrote, ‘we cannot believe that Providence should have placed this fine monument

  of social order so near to France merely to inspire in us the regret of never being able

  to equal it’.51 If she added little to the familiar litany of praise for English

  institutions and morals, the depth of Madame de Staël’s admiration for England

  needs to be recognized. It drew upon her father’s Anglophilia, her visits to England,

  her reading, and her conversations with many English friends. Above all, she

  believed that England’s power, prosperity, and tranquillity derived from its long-

  established freedoms, its commercial spirit, its Protestantism, and its political

  institutions. Needless to say, she turned a blind eye to many, although not all, of

  England’s faults, singling out for praise the rule of law, a decentralized administra-

  tion, an exemplary public spirit, and a vigorous, open aristocracy. Her point was

  that the England of today could be the France of tomorrow.

  Yet France had not pursued the course taken by England and, as a consequence,

  she languished in a state of despotism. For Madame de Staël, Napoleon Bonaparte

  had arisen naturally and almost inevitably out of the chaos of the Revolution. The

  two principal causes of his power, she observed, were that he had given France

  military glory rather than liberty and had restored order without attacking selfish

  passions. From personal experience she knew that he was no ordinary man, that he

  had a desire to astonish the human race, but not content with being a master he had

  49 Ibid. 303.

  50 Ibid. 305.

  51 Ibid. 530. See Robert Escarpit, L’Angleterre dans l’œuvre de Madame de Staël (1954) and V. de

  Pange, ‘Le Rêve anglais de Madame de Staël’, in Colloque de Coppet, Madame de Staël et l’Europe

  (1970), 173–92.

  250

  History, Revolution, and Terror

  wished to be a tyrant. In words that echoed those of Montesquieu, she described a

  regime based upon corruption and immorality, where the will of a single man

  decided everything, where all liberties were suppressed, where opponents were

  banished without trial, and which daily displayed contempt for humanity. Napo-

  leon’s despotism was one of conquest and of continuous wars. No one dared to tell

  him the truth.

  Madame de Staël recorded that she met the emperor’s fall with mixed emotions.

  It seemed, she wrote, as if Burke’s prediction had been accomplished: France had

  fallen into the abyss. However, she was not eager to see a return of the Bourbon

  monarchy. Nor, unlike Benjamin Constant, was she fooled by the returning

  Napoleon’s conversion to constitutional government. The friends of liberty, she

  observed, needed to separate their cause entirely from his and should never confuse

  the principles of the Revolution with those of imperial government. Indeed, this

  stance embodied the fundamental political message of her text: liberty could only

  ever be attained through liberty and never through coercion. And nothing but

  liberty could arouse the soul and ennoble our character. This was a lesson that

  French liberals were to seek to build upon during the nineteenth century.

  In historiographical terms, Madame de Staël’s legacy was no less important. Not

  only was she the first to examine the course and aftermath of the Revolution in any

  detail, but her lasting contribution lay in her characterization of the Revolution as

  the culmination of a thousand-year struggle for liberty by the people of France.

  Moreover, that this aspiration had been betrayed by the leaders of the Revolution

  did not, for her, diminish the achievement of overturning centuries of injustice and

  oppression. She thereby established the distinction between 1789 and 1793. The

  Terror was not the logical consequence of the principles of 1789 and Napoleon was

  not the necessary solution.

  Published in the early years of the Restoration period, Considérations sur les

  principaux évènemens de la Révolution française evoked a series of immediate and

  varied responses.52 Many simply asserted that Madame de Staël’s affection for her

  father had blinded her to the true nature of the Revolution. Others saw her book as

  anti-French and unpatriotic. Three commentaries merit particular attention. The

  first was penned by royalist Louis de Bonald.53 It disputed the virtues attributed to />
  Jacques Necker. It denied that the Revolution had been inevitable and that its cause

  lay in the misery of the people. It challenged the description of absolute monarchy

  as arbitrary government, contending that France had had a constitution and that it

  had resided in her ‘religion, royalty, and justice’.54 It contradicted the claim that

  England was a free polity, placing little or no value in its much-vaunted liberties

  such as freedom of the press or trial by jury and characterizing the English as

  52 See G. E. Gwynne, Madame de Staël et la Révolution française (1969), 262–71, and Ezio

  Cappadocia, ‘The Liberals and Madame de Staël in 1818’, in Richard Herr and Harold T. Parker

  (eds.), Ideas in History: Essays Presented to Louis Gottschalk by his Former Students (Durham, NC, 1965),

  182–97.

  53 Observations sur l’ouvrage de Mme la Baronne de Staël, ayant pour titre: Considérations sur les

  principaux évenéments de la révolution française (1818).

  54 Ibid. 37.

  History, Revolution, and Terror

  251

  ‘morose, irritable, unhappy, selfish’.55 It suggested that liberals such as Madame de

  Staël despised Napoleon not because he had oppressed France but because he had

  oppressed the Revolution. Finally, it argued that the veracity of Madame de Staël’s

  entire account was undermined by her Protestantism. The royalist and theocratic

  reply, in short, remained that the Revolution was misconceived from the outset and

  that its ‘inevitable’ and ‘natural’ quality was crime.56 In the decades that followed,

  conservative writers were to seek to remind the French of this reality.57

  The second commentary, published in 1818, amounted to a two-volume,

  chapter-by-chapter, refutation of Madame de Staël’s argument running to over

  900 pages. Its author was Jacques-Charles Bailleul.58 He was a former Girondin

  and member of the Convention who had narrowly escaped death thanks to the fall

  of Robespierre. He too had fallen foul of Napoleon Bonaparte. Yet he viewed the

  Revolution in an entirely different light from Madame de Staël. Naturally, Bailleul

  disparaged Madame de Staël’s eulogy of her father and was thoroughly dismissive of

  her praise of England, suggesting that it was the French and not the English who

  were made for liberty. More substantively, Bailleul characterized the period of

  French history from Richelieu onwards not in terms of a loss of liberty but as the

  time when it was possible to speak of the deliverance of the people, the setting free

  of the nation. By the nation, Bailleul clearly intended the Third Estate and thus, on

  this account, 1789 was the moment when, for the first time, the nation came fully

  into existence, when, equal before the same laws, Gascons and Normans became

  French. Crucially, he then suggested that the derailing of the Revolution arose not

  from anything intrinsic to the Revolution itself but as a consequence of the actions

  of an ‘antinational party’ composed of the forces of privilege and, all importantly,

  from the exigencies of a foreign-imposed war. In other words, it was the opponents

  of the Revolution who were responsible for the chaos and external threats that made

  resort to Terror into a political and military necessity. ‘The Jacobin party’, Bailleul

  wrote, ‘did not wish to exercise despotism; it wished only to defend the homeland

  and liberty.’59 Robespierre was not a hypocrite but a principled man seeking to

  bring about the reign of virtue. Forced by events to push the logic of virtue to its

  extreme, he became a ‘monster’ and France under the Jacobins lapsed into arbitrary

  government, but the fault for this lay unambiguously with the ‘conspiracy of the

  privileged’. In brief, it was circumstances, rather than revolutionary doctrine, that

  explained the Terror. Here were powerful arguments that later historians of the

  Revolution were to deploy with great effectiveness.

  A far kinder assessment of Madame de Staël’s achievement came from Benjamin

  Constant.60 Her book, he wrote, was more than a simple apology for Jacques

  55 Ibid. 26.

  56 Ibid. 129–31.

  57 See Stanley Mellon, The Political Uses of History (Stanford, Calif., 1958), 58–100.

  58 Examen Critique des Considérations de Mme la Baronne de Staël sur les principaux événements de la

  Révolution française, 2 vols. (1822).

  59 Ibid. ii. 215.

  60 ‘Considérations sur les principaux événements de la Révolution française’, in Ephraïm Harpaz

  (ed.), Benjamin Constant: Receuil d’Articles. Le Mercure de France et la Rénommée (1972), i. 407–12,

  450–9, 469–78.

  252

  History, Revolution, and Terror

  Necker. In it, he continued, were to be observed all the principles that had inspired

  Madame de Staël throughout her life: an attachment to liberty, a profound sense of

  the dignity of the human race, a respect for the application of morality to politics,

  and, he insisted, a love of France. Moreover, it was ‘the best history of our

  revolution that has appeared so far’.

  Liberalism in Restoration France was an amorphous doctrine.61 All the same, the

  liberals had three main political tasks: to preserve the civil acquisitions of 1789, to

  deny their responsibility for the Terror, and to outline a political programme for

  power. As Stanley Mellon observed: ‘The Revolution was lurking beneath every

  political issue: it had to be explained and defended, right up to the day that the

  revolution of 1830 successfully enshrined it.’62 Madame de Staël provided some of

  the armoury required for these tasks but more would be needed if liberals were to

  win their bitter political battles with their royalist opponents. In the first instance, a

  response had to be made to the thesis expounded by the Comte de Montlosier in

  his De la monarchie française.63

  Montlosier’s text had a curious history, the count having been asked by Napoleon

  Bonaparte to write a history of France which would establish the legitimacy of the

  Empire by establishing its continuity with the monarchy of the ancien régime.

  When no such book was forthcoming, it was sent back to its author, only to be

  published in 1814, at the very moment when the restored Bourbon monarchy itself

  was impatient to re-establish its own historical credentials. At the core of Montlosier’s

  account was a reworking of what had become a familiar theme of eighteenth-century

  polemic: namely, that the history of France could be summarized as a struggle

  between two races, the Franks and the Gauls.64 In its most famous formulation,

  Henri de Boulainvilliers had retold the history of the victory of the noble Franks over

  the Gauls in order, first, to celebrate an ideal of feudal liberty and, second, to reassert

  the ancient right of the Franks to participate in government. On this account, by

  excluding the nobility, the rise of royal absolutism had destroyed feudal liberty. Just

  as importantly, Boulainvilliers affirmed that the subject Gauls had been excluded

  from government. Montlosier recast this argument in terms of the gradual under-

  mining of aristocracy of the Franks by the Gauls of the Third Estate, a process

  which culminated in the Revolution of 1789. Read in the context of the Restoration,

&nbs
p; Montlosier not only seemed to be suggesting that the struggle between these two

  races was never ending but also that the returning émigré aristocracy had good

  grounds for affirming its supremacy anew. For those of a liberal disposition wishing

  to establish that the Charte granted to the French people in 1814 had an altogether

  61 See Laurence Jacobs, ‘Le Moment Libéral: The Distinctive Character of Restoration Liberalism’,

  Historical Journal, 31 (1988), 479–92.

  62 Mellon, Political Uses, 193.

  63 See Furet, Revolutionary France, 307–8, and Sarah Maza, The Myth of the French Bourgeoisie

  (Cambridge, Mass., 2003), 150–2. The argument developed in the next section of the text draws upon

  Shirley M. Gruner, ‘Political Historiography in Restoration France’, History and Theory, 8 (1969),

  346–65.

  64 See Claude Nicolet, La Fabrique d’une nation: La France entre Rome et les Germains (2006),

  107–37.

  History, Revolution, and Terror

  253

  different message, the stakes could hardly have been higher. They had to show that

  history was on the side of the Third Estate. In brief, the bourgeoisie needed to get a

  history, and it needed to get one quickly.

  By general agreement this history was largely provided by Augustin Thierry in

  his Lettres sur l’histoire de France of 182065 and by François Guizot in his Essais sur

  l’histoire de France of 1823. Although different in tone and substance, each turned

  Montlosier’s argument on its head in order not only to describe the Third Estate as

  the driving force of French history, but also to portray its role in a positive light.

  The claim was that the facts of French history had been ‘perverted’ by a series of

  ‘arbitrary’ accounts intended to reduce ‘a free people’ to mere ‘subjects standing

  before a master who alone speaks and who no one could contradict’. It was not in

  the recent past, Thierry countered, but seven hundred years before that France had

  first seen men deploy their courage and their convictions ‘to create for themselves

  and for their children an existence that was at once free and benign’. This, he

  affirmed, could be clearly seen among those former serfs who had ‘built the walls

  and the civilization of the ancient Gallic cities’. According to Thierry, therefore, the

  ‘difficult’ but ‘glorious’ task of writing a ‘truthful history’ of France would restore

 

‹ Prev