Revolution and the Republic

Home > Other > Revolution and the Republic > Page 60
Revolution and the Republic Page 60

by Jeremy Jennings


  changeable, so routine-bound, and so capable of coming above or below the

  ‘common norms of humanity’. France alone, Tocqueville wrote, ‘could give birth

  to a revolution so sudden, so radical, so impetuous in its course and yet so full of

  reverses, contradictory facts and contrary examples’.240 But the reality, as he himself

  acknowledged, was that, for all its frequent revival in new and unexpected forms,

  the desire for liberty quickly succumbed before a love of equality that remained

  234 Ibid. 232.

  235 Ibid. 235.

  236 Ibid. 243.

  237 Ibid. 248.

  238 Ibid.

  239 Ibid.

  240 Ibid. 250.

  282

  History, Revolution, and Terror

  constant. Such, at least, was how it appeared to Tocqueville from deep within the

  Second Empire of Napoleon III.

  Tocqueville, like so many of his fellow historians, could not resist asserting the

  unique and exceptional character of the Revolution. He was, on the other hand,

  immune from the commonly held faith in the virtues of the people and plainly saw

  little evidence of the Revolution as the dawn of a new religion of justice and

  fraternity. Indeed, with the notable exception of the summer of 1789, Tocqueville

  appears to have discerned few signs of political innovation among the momentous

  events that shook France to her very foundations. However, Tocqueville was to be

  by no means alone in stressing the theme of continuity. As we have seen, Quinet,

  under the influence of Tocqueville, was to rework the idea in order to suggest that

  the Revolution marked a revival of monarchical absolutism. Another person to

  develop this theme was the diplomatic historian Albert Sorel. 241 ‘The fact is’, Sorel

  wrote, almost three decades later, ‘that the Revolution did not, as has too often been

  said, break the chain of French history.’242 Although probably the most remarkable

  of episodes, it was nonetheless only ‘one episode’ in that history. Indeed, Sorel

  ended the introduction to his L’Europe et la Révolution française by emphasizing

  that this was the very point of his eight-volume study. ‘I should consider my work

  not to have been useless’, he observed, ‘if I had attained the following result: to have

  shown the French Revolution, which to some has appeared as the subversion and to

  others as the regeneration of the old European world, to be the natural and

  necessary consequence of the history of Europe and to have established that this

  Revolution produced no consequence, not even the most surprising, that does not

  flow from this history and is not explicable by the precedents of the ancien

  régime.’243

  With regard to the internal dynamics of the Revolution, Sorel’s argument built

  upon a set of insights gleaned from Tocqueville. In 1789, he believed, everything

  was ready for revolution. The ancien régime was in decay; the government was

  bankrupt and powerless; men of letters displayed a mixture of fanaticism and

  doctrinal infatuation; and ‘a wild frenzy was brewing among the masses’. Above

  all, Sorel wrote, ‘the spirit of the Third Estate was that of the lawyers’.244 It was they

  who were to turn the ideas of the philosophes into legislation and by choosing its

  representatives from among this group ‘the people were appropriating and

  continuing the traditions of the crown’.245 True to these traditions, if sovereignty

  passed from the monarch to the people, the lawyers attributed to the new sovereign

  all the qualities of the old one. ‘At bottom’, Sorel commented, ‘things returned to

  the point from which they had started.’246 The State remained what it had always

  241 On Albert Sorel, see L’Europe et la Révolution française: Discours prononcés le 29 mars 1905 à la

  fête en l’honneur de M. Albert Sorel (1905). Of particular interest are the texts by Emile Boutmy and

  Gabriel Hanotaux: ibid. 23–61.

  242 L’Europe et la Révolution française (1885), i. 238.

  243 Ibid. 8.

  244 Ibid. 221.

  245 Ibid.

  246 Ibid. 222.

  History, Revolution, and Terror

  283

  been and ‘the spirit of the old government reappeared in the very institutions

  intended to destroy it’.247 Thus, the National Assembly ‘promptly’ set about

  concentrating all power in its own hands; and when, through ‘force of circum-

  stances’, abstract ideals were abandoned, ‘traditional forms of behaviour and ideas

  prevailed’. None were on the side of liberty and they provided countless precedents

  for despotism. ‘Thus’, Sorel wrote, ‘in the guise of expedients all the procedures of

  the ancien régime insinuated themselves into the Revolution.’248 Once returned,

  they remained uncontested, and power came to be concentrated in ever fewer

  hands, from a Committee of twelve to a Directory of five, from a Consulate of three

  to an Empire of one.

  Sorel gave many examples of the continuities in practice that this entailed. Two

  might be cited here. The first concerned the Revolution’s treatment of the Church.

  Despite the appearance of innovation the Revolution ‘quite simply applied to the

  clergy and to recalcitrant Catholics measures which the monarchy had employed

  against heretics’.249 Revolutionary legislation merely copied the edicts of Louis XIV

  against the Protestants. The second example related to the Terror. It could not be

  said that the abuses and excesses of the ancien régime produced the Terror but they

  did ‘all derive from the same source’. The ‘terrorists’ had had no intention of

  avenging the victims of Louis XIV but ‘the same fanaticism produced the same

  results’. ‘Considered in this way’, Sorel wrote, ‘the Terror is stripped of the

  sophistical prestige with which its retrospective apologists have tried to surround

  it. The only striking thing that remains is the extent of its plagiarism.’250

  Given that the ancien régime had no pretensions to liberty and that the Revolu-

  tion had so readily aped its customs and practices, it would have been ‘truly

  extraordinary’, Sorel concluded, if the Revolution had marked the ‘triumph of

  liberty’. The cause for regret was that, if the ancien régime had been ‘self-consistent’

  in its despotism, the ‘terrorists’ had been ‘humanitarian and sentimental’ in theory

  and ‘barbarous’ in practice.251 It was this contradiction that the world had seen.

  However, Sorel’s exploration of the theme of continuity merits particular atten-

  tion because his primary focus was upon foreign policy. His fundamental point was

  that ‘for external as well as internal affairs there had existed permanent historical

  necessities’ and that these had been played out during the Revolution.252 This

  argument was developed by Sorel in the first of his eight volumes and then

  summarized in a conclusion which, in his words, provided ‘the basic structure of

  this history’.253 Sorel’s thesis was that French foreign policy was determined by

  geography and, therefore, by the need to establish secure frontiers. This was a

  constant from the Capetian monarchs onwards and it produced what Sorel termed

  the ‘classic system’ of French diplomacy. Its essential principle was moderation and

&nbs
p; compromise and a recognition that in foreign undertakings there were certain limits

  beyond which it was unwise to go and which would not be tolerated by her

  neighbours. Henri IV and Richelieu were the primary exemplars of this tradition.

  Alongside this, on the other hand, were a set of contrary instincts, described by

  247 Ibid. 223.

  248 Ibid. 225.

  249 Ibid. 230.

  250 Ibid. 232–3.

  251 Ibid. 233.

  252 Ibid. 242.

  253 Ibid. 537–52.

  284

  History, Revolution, and Terror

  Sorel as ‘gusts of romantic ambition, an intoxication with conquest and a capricious

  taste for glory and adventure’.254 This ‘craving for the impossible’ was best

  exemplified (with disastrous results) by the military excesses of Louis XIV. Sorel’s

  point was that these two instincts had coexisted over the centuries and that the

  Revolution brought each of them into operation in turn.

  In essence, Sorel’s claim was the National Assembly of 1789 sought to continue

  the policies of moderation and that there was nothing in the new political principles

  of the Revolution that was not compatible with peace across Europe. The Revolu-

  tion had renounced the right of conquest for the reasons which ‘self-interest rightly

  understood, prudence and reflection had suggested to the most far-seeing diplomats

  of the ancien régime’.255 Moreover, if ‘honestly applied’, the ‘one basic principle of

  the Revolution’, sovereignty of the people, would have prevented ‘all the abuses of

  conquest’. Every nation would have had the right to determine its own fate.

  Sorel next suggested, however, that neither France nor Europe were ready for

  such a radical reform of political habits and thus ‘the spirit of proselytism quickly

  came to dominate the Revolution; the idea of conquest continued to prevail in

  Europe; and a bitter war followed’.256 By the time that peace again became possible

  in 1795 those who now ruled had ‘transferred to the people all the qualities that

  their predecessors had attributed to the majesty of the king: they incited them to

  pursue glory, urged them to war, and founded on their passions the power they

  exercised in their name’.257 In short, by embarking upon a war of conquest the

  Revolution deviated from ‘the true French tradition’ and recklessly endangered

  France’s permanent interests. If this signified that the revolutionaries were follow-

  ing ‘impulses as old as French history’, it also meant that the Republic was handed

  over to the generals and that France committed herself to an expansion that she was

  incapable of supporting. As Sorel concluded, the result could only ever have been

  self-destruction. The sole remedy, therefore, was for France ‘to revive the policies

  drawn up by the wisest of her ministers on the eve of the Revolution’ and it was this

  that had been done ‘after twenty-two years of relentless struggle’ and when France

  had been ‘defeated by the enemies allied against her’.

  Many nineteenth-century histories of the Revolution devoted considerable space

  to the wars engaged upon by the Republic and the Empire. In these accounts, the

  achievement of military glory frequently figured as a compensation for domestic

  failure and the abandonment of revolutionary ideals. To an extent, Sorel mirrored

  this perspective, stating that it was in war that the Revolution ‘secured its most

  astonishing achievements’. But, he added, ‘this was its greatness and its ruin’.258 In

  the main body of his history, therefore, Sorel displayed no sympathy for the view

  that the Terror had saved France from her external enemies nor did he countenance

  a justification of revolutionary war as a means of defeating counter-revolutionary

  forces. Rather, what he emphasized repeatedly was that the vices of the Revolution

  were a legacy of the past. So, for Sorel, it was not only the internal causes leading to

  the degeneration of France into ‘bloody anarchy’ that had existed before 1789: the

  254 L’Europe et la Révolution française (1885), 242–3.

  255 Ibid. 318.

  256 Ibid. 318–19.

  257 Ibid. 319.

  258 Ibid. 242.

  History, Revolution, and Terror

  285

  same was true of the tendency to despotism and conquest in foreign affairs. ‘The

  Revolution of 1789’, Sorel wrote, ‘was easily reconcilable with policy of Henri IV

  and Richelieu but not that of Louis XIV.’ Such, however, had been the ‘strange

  destiny’ of the Revolution.259

  Albert Sorel had been exceptionally well placed to undertake his study of the

  international dimensions of the Revolution. From 1866 to 1875 he had held an

  appointment in the Ministry of Foreign Affairs, after which he obtained a teaching

  post at the newly established École Libre des Sciences Politiques. Early in his

  academic career he wrote several works of diplomatic history, most notably studies

  of the partition of Poland and of the Franco-Prussian war, before embarking upon

  his history of the Revolution, a task completed only in 1904. Sorel also wrote book-

  length studies of both Montesquieu and Madame de Staël. The political views he

  espoused, as might be surmised, were those of a conservative and moderate

  republicanism, and as such mirrored those of his academic colleagues in Paris.

  That same institution, founded by Émile Boutmy, also remained deeply indebt-

  ed to the influence of Alexis de Tocqueville. This merits comment because in this

  period both Tocqueville’s work and his reputation were quickly consigned to

  oblivion.260 In truth, this fate befell De la Démocratie en Amérique long before it

  did L’Ancien Régime et la Révolution, but the institutionalization of the study of the

  Revolution—symbolized through the creation of a chair in the history of Revolu-

  tion at the Sorbonne in 1891 and the founding of the Société de l’Histoire de la

  Révolution française—engendered a method of inquiry and perspective widely at

  odds with that exemplified by Tocqueville. University lecture courses on the

  Revolution were now deemed permissible because the Third Republic believed

  itself to have been established upon sound institutional and political foundations.

  Moreover, as Françoise Mélonio remarks, ‘teaching revolutionary history was part

  of a republican strategy to give the Republic the halo of a glorious birth’.261

  Michelet, and not Tocqueville, was to provide the republican textbook.262

  V

  The first holder of the chair in the history of the Revolution was Alphonse Aulard

  and it was to be him, more than any one else, who provided the Third Republic

  with the history it required. To achieve that end, however, he had to remove the

  towering figure of Hippolyte Taine from the field of revolutionary historiography.

  Taine was the author of the monumental Les Origines de la France contemporaine.

  Its eleven volumes were subdivided into three parts. Two volumes devoted to

  L’Ancien Régime appeared in 1875. This was followed by six volumes on La

  259 Ibid. 552.

  260 Mélonio, ‘Introduction’ 149–88.

  261 Ibid. 171.

  262 For the centenary celebrations in 1889 a government subsidy was provided to republish

&nb
sp; Michelet’s history of the Revolution. On the emergence of this distinctively Third Republic analysis

  of the Revolution see Paul Farmer, France Reviews its Revolutionary Origins (1944), 37–45.

  286

  History, Revolution, and Terror

  Révolution, published in 1878–84 and three concluding volumes, La France mo-

  derne, in 1891 and 1893. At the very moment of the Third Republic’s triumph,

  Taine painted an unforgettable picture of the Revolution as nothing else but

  bloodthirsty anarchy and horror.

  As the controversy surrounding the publication of Quinet’s La Révolution

  indicates, the 1860s saw no diminution in the importance attached to rival

  interpretations of the Revolution. The year of the publication of Quinet’s history

  also saw the appearance of the first volume of Ernest Hamel’s Histoire de Robespierre

  d’après des papiers de famille, les sources originales et des documents entièrement

  inédits.263 Claiming to be guided by a spirit of ‘impartiality’ and to be the first

  study that provided a ‘day-by-day’ account of Robespierre’s life, its conclusion was

  that posterity would one day place Robespierre ‘amongst the martyrs of humanity’.

  In marked contrast, the middle years of the decade saw the publication of the first

  volumes of Mortimer-Ternaux’s anti-revolutionary Histoire de la Terreur264 and of

  Jules Sauzay’s heartfelt account of the Revolution’s attack upon the Church,

  Histoire de la Persécution Révolutionnaire dans le département du Doubs de 1789 à

  1801.265 Both were to be read by Taine. Then, in the aftermath of military defeat

  and humiliation, came the Paris Commune, an event which, for some (including

  Taine), bore a very unwelcome resemblance to the events of 1793. What this

  violent and destructive episode revealed, Henri Wallon wrote in La Terreur, Études

  critiques sur l’histoire (1873), was that the Terror required only a propitious

  moment to make its return and that the ‘sinister’ people associated with it were

  not ‘phantasms of the past’. Émile Montégut, writing in the prestigious Revue des

  Deux Mondes,266 argued that the Commune demonstrated that ‘the bankruptcy of

  the French Revolution’ was ‘an irrevocable and established fact’. Taine was to be of

  a very similar opinion.

  Any hope that the debate might diminish in intensity was dispelled as France

 

‹ Prev