Revolution and the Republic

Home > Other > Revolution and the Republic > Page 61
Revolution and the Republic Page 61

by Jeremy Jennings


  began its preparations for the commemoration of the centenary of 1789. If the

  central parts of Taine’s history were now in print, the period 1886–90 saw the

  publication of over 100 new books on the Revolution.267 Dated 1 January, the first

  to appear in 1889 was a work by the Bishop of Angers which, having dissected the

  errors of revolutionary ideology, denounced the Revolution as ‘the most disastrous

  event in our national history’.268 By way of response, a veritable deluge of articles,

  brochures, reviews, biographies, and books sought to popularize the official message

  that, despite regrettable excesses, the achievements of the Revolution were to be

  celebrated and its heritage defended. Nevertheless, there was some very thin ice to

  263 (1865). The next 2 vols. were publ. in 1866 and 1867.

  264 7 vols. (1862–91). The message was that France had been saved despite the Terror.

  265 6 vols. (1867–73).

  266 ‘Où en est la Révolution française: simples notes sur la situation actuelle’, Revue des Deux

  Mondes, 41 (5 Aug. 1871), 872–98.

  267 For reviews of a selection of the books publ. during 1889 see ‘Bibliographie du centenaire’, La

  Réforme sociale et le Centenaire de la Révolution (1889), 173–85.

  268 Mgr Charles Freppel, La Révolution française à propos du centenaire de 1789 (1889), 139. Some

  nine years earlier Mgr Freppel had written a preface to a remarkable book by P. Ubald de Chanday, Les

  Trois Frances (1880). The France of the Revolution was categorized as ‘la France satanique’.

  History, Revolution, and Terror

  287

  be skated over269 and, regardless of the statues unveiled, dinners enjoyed, ceremo-

  nies held, and an Eiffel Tower built, the experience was by no means an unalloyed

  success. The admirers of the revanchist General Boulanger could not be dissuaded

  from describing the Republic as a ‘Bastille parlementaire’ that needed to be stormed

  anew and the emerging socialist press complained repeatedly about a Revolution

  betrayed by the bourgeoisie.270

  Nor did calm return with the ending of the centenary. On 24 January 1891 the

  Comédie-Française, the very pinnacle of the French theatrical establishment, gave

  its first performance of a play by Victorien Sardou titled Thermidor. It told a simple

  but controversial tale. The action took place on the eve of the fall of Robespierre

  and brought together two old friends, Labussière and Martial Hugon, the former

  recounting how, as a minor official in the bureau des détenus, he had sought to save

  those who were innocent from execution. Recently returned from the front, Martial

  was seeking to find his lover. As the action unfolds we see that neither man can save

  her from the guillotine. Martial dies in the process and Labussière is reduced to

  despair. At the heart of the play is a conversation between the two men that reveals

  the gulf separating sincere and courageous republicans prepared to defend their

  country from the Parisian and Jacobin world of denunciations, suspicion, and

  cruelty. The question posed was whether such a world was worth fighting for?

  For his pains Sardou was roundly denounced as a reactionary who had written a

  reactionary play.271 However, the most significant (and subsequently famous)

  response came only five days later when the radical parliamentary deputy Georges

  Clemenceau stood before the parliamentary Chamber of Deputies and there

  denounced those on the right who, in his view, sought to mutilate the legacy of

  the Revolution. ‘Messieurs’, he proclaimed, ‘whether we wish it or not, whether it

  pleases or shocks us, the French Revolution is a block, a block from which nothing

  can be severed because historical truth does not permit it.’272 In brief, to support

  the Third Republic was to accept the Revolution, to endorse the principles of 1789,

  and to sanction the Terror. To do otherwise was to support the Revolution’s

  enemies and to challenge the republican message that the Revolution constituted

  the founding moment of modern France. In that same year, Taine expressed the

  contrary view that it was Napoleon Bonaparte who had made modern France.273

  Hippolyte Taine was one of the great literary figures of the second half of the

  nineteenth century.274 Born in 1828, in the years before the Paris Commune he

  269 It proved difficult to come to an agreement about which dates were to be celebrated.

  270 See Marc Angenot, Le Centenaire de la révolution: 1889 (1989) and Pascal Ory, ‘Le Centenaire

  de la Révolution française’, in Pierre Nora (ed.), Les Lieux de mémoire (1984), i. 465–92.

  271 See e.g. Edmond Bourgeois, Thermidor: Réponse à la pièce de Victorien Sardou (1891). For a

  contrary view see Ernest Desmarest, Thermidor et la pièce de M. Sardou (1891). Sardou’s play was

  quickly removed from the stage.

  272 Quoted in Bétourné and Hartig, Penser l’histoire de la Révolution (1989), 94 n. 1.

  273 Taine, Les Origines de la France contemporaine (1900–2), i. 4.

  274 Given the precipitous decline in Taine’s reputation relatively little recent scholarship has been

  devoted to him: however, see Susanna Barrows, ‘Hippolyte Taine and the Spectre of the Commune’,

  Distorting Mirrors: Visions of the Crowd in Late Nineteenth-Century France (New Haven, Conn., 1981),

  73–92, and Eric Gasparini, La Pensée politique d’Hippolyte Taine: Entre traditionalisme et libéralisme

  (Aix-en-Provence, 1993).

  288

  History, Revolution, and Terror

  published works on English literature,275 Italian, Flemish, and Greek art, French

  philosophy,276 and human psychology.277 For good measure, he also published a

  novel and accounts of his travels. Elected a member of the Académie Française,

  Taine was appointed professor of aesthetics at the École des Beaux-Arts. Like

  Tocqueville, Taine turned late to the writing of history and he too failed to

  complete the masterpiece that, for good or ill, was to define his reputation.278

  Like Tocqueville, he studied the past primarily to understand the present and its

  many discontents.

  No republican, Taine greeted the Franco-Prussian war with ill-disguised fore-

  boding. This turned to horror and despair with the inauguration of the Paris

  Commune on 17 March 1871. ‘I am very sad and very discouraged’, he wrote to

  his mother four days later; ‘the future looks very black, but what is worse, it is

  impossible to know what lays hidden beneath this darkness’.279 Not long after-

  wards he concluded that it was to be ‘a return to barbarism and the dangers of

  primitive anarchy’, describing Paris as ‘a pandemonium’.280 In May 1871 Taine

  left for England and it was in the Oxford University library that he learnt of the

  fighting in Paris. The defeated Communards, he wrote to his wife, were miserable

  wretches, savage wolves, brigands who placed themselves beyond the pale of

  humanity.281 No sooner was he back in Paris than he began the long and laborious

  research for Les Origines de la France contemporaine, convinced that to comprehend

  the current disorder it was necessary to return to the crisis of the ancien régime and

  to the Revolution. This was the issue that was to preoccupy him for the best part of

  the next twenty years until his death in 1893.

  Taine
had made his reputation through the application of scientific method to

  fields previously dominated by the traditions of classical studies. His most famous

  statement of this commitment came in the introduction to his Histoire de la

  littérature anglaise of 1863.282 He there argued that, in the course of the previous

  century, the writing of history had been revolutionized, first through the extension

  of historical imagination,283 and then through the use of observation and experi-

  ment to understand the inner psychology of human beings. According to this

  methodology, the actions of individuals or groups of persons were as amenable to

  causal explanation as any event in the natural world. As Taine famously remarked:

  ‘No matter if the facts be physical or moral: they all have their causes; there is a

  cause for ambition, for courage, for truth, as there is for digestion, for muscular

  movement, for animal heat. Vice and virtue are products just like vitriol and

  275 Histoire de la littérature anglaise, 4 vols. (1863–4).

  276 Les Philosophes français du XXe siècle (1857).

  277 De l’Intelligence, 2 vols. (1870).

  278 Alfred Cobban said of Taine that he was ‘perhaps the greatest of bad historians’: ‘Hippolyte

  Taine, Historian of the French Revolution’, History, 53 (1968), 331.

  279 H. Taine: Sa vie et correspondance (1905), iii. 68.

  280 Ibid. 75.

  281 Ibid. 128–9.

  282 Histoire de la littérature anglaise, i, pp. i–xlviii. See also the Preface to Taine’s Essais de Critique et

  d’Histoire (1858), pp. i–xv.

  283 By way of example, Taine cited Lessing, Walter Scott, Chateaubriand, Thierry, and Michelet.

  History, Revolution, and Terror

  289

  sugar.’284 Taine further specified that the three primary determinants of human

  behaviour were ‘la race, le milieu, le moment’285 and that these provided the key to

  an understanding of the mental habits of a people. The writing of history, therefore,

  was not primarily narration but a form of applied psychology.286

  Upon their appearance in 1875, the first volumes of Les Origines de la France

  contemporaine greatly displeased monarchist opinion for there was described a

  venal Church, an ornamental nobility, and a vain and arbitrary monarchy. They

  also provided a portrayal of a people brutalized by misery and ignorance, prone to

  displays of blind rage, and of limited political capacity. ‘Every object’, Taine

  wrote, ‘appears to them in a false light. They are like children who, at every turn

  of the road, see in each tree or bush, some frightful apparition.’287 However,

  those same volumes also began the description of a ‘spirit and doctrine’ which

  Taine took to be distinctively French and which, in his view, provided the

  ideological driving force of the Revolution. While the esprit classique that had

  underpinned French civilization had been held in check by religious belief and by

  the authority of the monarchy, Taine argued, it had produced such wonders as

  the gardens of Versailles, but, set free from these restraints, as the eighteenth

  century progressed it had generated an entirely abstract and rational conception

  of man and, from this, a vision of politics based upon mathematical models. The

  philosophy of the eighteenth century, Taine wrote, resembled a religion: it had

  ‘the same impetus of faith, hope, and enthusiasm, the same spirit of propaganda

  and domination, the same severity and intolerance, the same ambition to recast

  man and to remodel all human life according to a preconceived plan’.288

  Taine’s rejoinder to this simplified logic, to what he termed ‘la raison raison-

  nante’, was to outline an entirely different vision of the human condition. ‘Not

  only’, Taine wrote, ‘is reason not natural to man or universal in humanity, but in

  the conduct of man its influence is small.’289 In most cases, our actions were guided

  by ‘physical temperament, bodily needs, animal instinct, hereditary prejudice,

  imagination’ and, above all, ‘personal self-interest’.290 Nor was it correct to imagine

  that people were naturally good. In human beings there was ‘an enduring substra-

  tum of brutality and ferocity, of violent and destructive instincts’.291 Given the

  paucity of resources provided by an ‘intractable earth’, our constant preoccupation

  was ‘to acquire, to amass, to possess’. Finally, our fertile minds were such as to turn

  our incessant dreams into ‘monstrous chimeras’ and to exaggerate our ‘fears, hopes,

  and desires’. From this arose, ‘especially if he were French’, sudden outbursts of

  emotion, irresistible passions, epidemics of credulity and suspicion, enthusiasm and

  panic.292 These, Taine argued, were the ‘brute forces which governed human life’.

  In normal circumstances they remained hidden but the truth was that, like a flood,

  the havoc and destruction they caused were only restrained by an equal force. ‘To

  control and limit their blows’, Taine wrote, ‘various mechanisms are employed: a

  284 Histoire de la littérature anglaise, i, p. xv.

  285 Ibid., pp. xxii–xxiii.

  286 Ibid., p. xliii.

  287 Origines de la France contemporaine, ii. 277.

  288 Ibid. 2.

  289 Ibid. 59.

  290 Ibid. 60.

  291 Ibid.

  292 Ibid. 61.

  290

  History, Revolution, and Terror

  pre-established constitution, the division of powers, a code of laws, tribunals and

  legal formalities. Behind all these wheels of government always appears the final

  appeal, the efficient instrument, namely the gendarme armed against the savage, the

  brigand, the madman that each of us conceals, asleep or enchained, but always

  alive, in the recesses of his own breast.’293

  The problem with the ‘new theory’, Taine continued, was that all its principles

  and precepts were directed against the gendarme. In the name of the sovereignty

  of the people, government was deprived of all authority, initiative, and power.

  Yet, by the same token, it also led to ‘the unlimited dictatorship of the State’.294

  A new contract, agreed upon by perfectly free and equal individuals, was deemed

  to supersede all other contracts and all other claims to rights—be they those

  of property, family, or Church—were as naught before the new State. In the

  ‘democratic convent’ modelled on Sparta and Rome, ‘the individual is noth-

  ing’.295 What would this mean when theory was put into practice? ‘The dogma

  of the sovereignty of the people, when interpreted by the crowd’, Taine wrote,

  ‘will produce perfect anarchy, until such point when, interpreted by its leaders,

  it will produce a perfect despotism.’296 This, in Taine’s view, was exactly what

  had occurred in the Revolution.

  In the most marvellously expressive prose, Taine described the descent of France

  into ‘spontaneous anarchy’. What began in 1789 was the very dissolution of

  society. The craving for bread degenerated into murder and incendiarism, the

  people acting like a ‘blind colossus’. As the fermentation increased, the agitators

  sat in permanent session, the ‘dictatorship of the mob’ striking out at anything that

  resisted it. The dregs of society came to the surface. ‘Like a tame el
ephant which

  suddenly becomes wild again’, Taine wrote, ‘in a flourish the people throw off their

  ordinary keeper and the new guides that it tolerates perched on its neck are there

  simply for show; henceforth, it will move along as it pleases, freed from their

  control, and guided by its own feelings, instincts, and appetites.’297 The storming

  of the Bastille was nothing else but an example of how popular insurrection turned

  frenzy into ferocity. Scarcely had the gates been entered than the work of destruc-

  tion began. ‘Suddenly’, Taine announced, ‘we see spring forth the barbarian, still

  worse, the primitive animal, the grinning, sanguinary and lustful ape, who chuckles

  while he kills and gambols over the ruins he has created.’298 Such, Taine wrote, was

  the ‘actual government’ to which France had been given up.

  For page upon page, chapter upon chapter, Taine continued in similar vein, the

  tone only changing when he described how the National Assembly, operating like

  ‘an academy of utopians’ rather than a ‘legislature of practitioners’,299 began the

  process of turning spontaneous anarchy into ‘legal anarchy’.300 With great obstina-

  cy it had refused to consider the ‘real man’ before its very eyes and had persisted in

  writing a constitution for ‘the abstract beings found in books’. It was ‘a masterpiece

  of speculative reason and of practical unreason’.301 Meanwhile, the people set about

  293 Origines de la France contemporaine, 62.

  294 Ibid. 65.

  295 Ibid. 68.

  296 Ibid. 65.

  297 Ibid. iii. 61.

  298 Ibid. 84.

  299 Ibid. iv. 44.

  300 Ibid. 47.

  301 Ibid.

  History, Revolution, and Terror

  291

  ‘the voluntary destruction of property’. It was this passion, Taine wrote, that gave

  the Revolution its ‘enduring energy, its primary impulse’.302

  It was from this ‘social decomposition’ that the Jacobins emerged and, like

  ‘mushrooms out of compost’, began the conquest of power. Their programme,

  Taine recognized, amounted to the regeneration of society and of man. The vehicle

  of this ‘liberating operation’ was to be ‘an omnipotent State’ exercising unlimited

  jurisdiction. No freedom was to be left to the individual. Again the quality of

 

‹ Prev