Book Read Free

Revolution and the Republic

Page 66

by Jeremy Jennings


  physicians, and not priests or misguided moralists, would be the superintendents of

  our behaviour and beliefs. In line with their conclusions and advice, legislators and

  governments would take the leading role in shaping and improving human conduct

  and manners and in this way the conflicting interests of the individuals who made

  up society would be brought into harmony. The State, and not the Church, would

  be our moral educator and there would be no need to have recourse to divine

  inspiration or sanction.

  In summary, the Idéologues placed their full weight behind attempts to discredit

  Christian metaphysics and used the considerable institutional power at their

  disposal to propagate a secular moral science and ethics. If this was true of their

  activities within the Institut, it was similarly so of the most important journal in

  which they published, the Décade philosophique.64 Whilst the articles it published

  displayed a limited sympathy towards Protestantism and Jansenism, Catholicism

  was characterized as being intrinsically intolerant and obscurantist. Its pages were

  never anything less than intransigently anticlerical. Moreover, the journal held

  Christianity as a whole responsible for preventing the advance of the human spirit

  by filling people’s heads with irrational fears and absurd beliefs. Humanity had to

  be cured of this malady.

  Yet the abiding preoccupation of the Idéologues was to stabilize the Republic and

  to bring the revolutionary turmoil of the 1790s to a close. Their philosophy

  reflected their disillusionment. To that end, idéologie was arguably designed to

  replace what they saw as a discredited Church and thus to replicate the stabilizing

  function of religion. As the late Robert Wokler argued,65 idéologie exuded a distrust

  of politics and placed what faith it had in the development of a new social science to

  cure the ills of the nation. Order would be secured through the inculcation of a

  morality of prudent and tempered self-interest, implanted in the minds of the

  people via a set of moralizing public institutions. Social hygiene was to be the

  maxim.

  This, like so much else at the time, proved to be a chimera. If the members of the

  Idéologue circle offered their services to Napoleon Bonaparte, he made clear his

  64 See Joanna Kitchin, Un journal ‘philosophique’: La Décade (1794–1807) (1965), 139–77, and

  Marc Regaldo, Un milieu intellectuel: La Décade philosophique (1794–1807), 5 vols. (1976). Kitchin

  refers to La Décade as the ‘organ of the Idéologues’: Un journal ‘philosophique’, p. vii. McManners,

  French Revolution, 135, refers to La Décade as ‘their mouth-piece’.

  65 ‘Ideology and the origins of social science’, in Mark Goldie and Robert Wokler (eds.), The

  Cambridge History of Eighteenth-Century Political Thought (Cambridge, 2006), 688–709.

  Religion, Enlightenment, and Reaction

  311

  opinion of the Classe des Sciences morales et politiques by closing it down in

  January 1803, the First Consul quickly concluding that they were a disruptive and

  unwelcome presence. Although no believer, he readily perceived that the Church

  was a far more efficient institution of social control than a coterie of ‘twelve or

  fifteen obscure metaphysicians’.66 As Napoleon told the assembled clergy of Milan

  in June 1800: ‘No society can exist without morality. But there is no good morality

  without religion. Religion alone therefore can give the State firm and lasting

  support.’67 The Concordat of 1801 and the presence of Pope Pius VII at his

  coronation as emperor served Napoleon’s purpose admirably and certainly far better

  than any Idéologue-inspired Council of Public Instruction might have done. When

  this strategy faltered, he persuaded the Church to canonize a St Napoleon and

  conveniently arranged for the celebration to coincide with the Feast of the Assump-

  tion, thereby obliging the faithful to worship the Virgin Mary and the emperor at one

  and the same time.68 Nevertheless, the preoccupation with developing and establish-

  ing a secular, non-theistic morality endured throughout the nineteenth century.

  So too did the perceived need to moralize the people in a post-revolutionary society.

  The curious thing is that the arguments advanced by believers and non-believers

  often sounded strangely alike.

  I I

  One group that might have been expected to welcome the Revolution were French

  Protestants. Calvinists in the south and Lutherans in Alsace, they comprised about

  700,000 adherents in total. Although the harsh persecutions of the reigns of Louis

  XIV and XV had largely subsided—the last Protestants were freed from the galley

  ships of Toulon in 1775—they continued to suffer legal disabilities until the

  promulgation of the Edict of Non-Catholics in 1788. Moreover, if doctrinal debate

  mattered little to the vast majority of Protestant believers—most of whom lived in

  small, isolated rural communities—at an elite level there was undoubtedly a

  coincidence of interest allying Protestant pleas for toleration and the concerns of

  the philosophes.

  Protestants (along with Jews) were therefore amongst the first beneficiaries of the

  Revolution’s reforms, all legal distinctions between Protestants and Catholics being

  abolished before the end of 1789. Two Protestants, the pastor Rabaut de Saint-

  Étienne and the future leader of the Feuillants, Antoine-Pierre Barnave,69 achieved

  early prominence in Parisian politics and others came to the fore at a provincial

  level. Many Protestants welcomed the inauguration of the Republic in 1792 but, to

  66 This was the derogatory phrase used to describe the Idéologues in an article publ. in the Journal de

  Paris. The article was inspired by Napoleon.

  67 Quoted in Bernard Reardon, Liberalism and Tradition: Aspects of Catholic Thought in Nineteenth-

  Century France (Cambridge, 1975), 2.

  68 See Sudhir Hazareesingh, The Saint Napoleon: Celebrations of Sovereignty in Nineteenth-Century

  France (Cambridge, Mass., 2004).

  69 Both were executed in 1793.

  312

  Religion, Enlightenment, and Reaction

  the extent that they supported the Girondins and the federalist cause, they quickly

  fell foul of Jacobin repression (one of the victims being the father of François

  Guizot). Nor could they entirely escape the excesses of the campaign of de-

  Christianization: recently opened Protestant temples were forced to close and

  pastors, often under threat of imprisonment, were obliged to abandon their

  ministry. Nevertheless, despite the considerable damage inflicted upon the Protes-

  tant community, the Republic displayed less fervour in eradicating Protestantism

  than it did in attempting to destroy the very last remnants of Catholicism. In

  acknowledgement of this fact, Catholics were subsequently to extract their (some-

  times bloody) revenge. After 1795, a much-weakened Protestant congregation

  sought to reconstitute the fabric of its religious life as best it could, and with

  varying levels of success. Protestants benefited from the separation of Church and

  State instituted by the Directory and they continued to enjoy the right of religious

  observance even after Napoleon had signed the Concordat with the pap
acy. The

  restored monarchy of Louis XVIII and Charles X likewise did not take away this

  right. The July Monarchy proved especially sympathetic towards Protestants.70

  One Protestant who had risen to prominence under the ancien régime was

  Jacques Necker, Louis XVI’s finance minister.71 Out of power between 1784 and

  1788, he had spent much of his time musing over the decline of morality in French

  society and, by way of response, published De l’importance de la morale et des

  opinions religieuses at the very moment when preparations began for the summon-

  ing of the Estates-General.72 In the words of George Armstrong Kelly, it was ‘an

  extremely long and windy work’ but also one of ‘remarkable interest’.73 Two

  themes are prominent. The first was Necker’s unambiguous recognition of the

  social utility of religion and that the general influence of religious morality was on

  the decline. Moreover, he doubted that the ‘cold lessons’ of political philosophy

  would serve as an adequate replacement. ‘We are delivering ourselves up to an

  illusion’, he wrote, ‘if we hope to establish morality upon the connection between

  individual interest and the public interest, and if we imagine that the authority of

  social laws can do without the support of religion.’74 A ‘political catechism’ would

  have little purchase upon the behaviour of the people. Good laws alone, in other

  words, were not sufficient. The second theme had a more distinctively Protestant

  flavour. Religious opinions and sentiments, in Necker’s view, enlarged and deep-

  ened our moral inclinations. They freed us from the tyranny of our passions and

  distanced us from our immediate, temporal interests. Religion instilled us with

  ‘benevolent virtues’, and, above all, with the virtue of charity. There was, Necker

  believed, nothing good, beautiful, or dignified about a condition of irreligion. The

  70 See Burdette C. Poland, French Protestantism and the French Revolution: A Study of Church and

  State, Thought and Religion, 1685–1815 (Princeton, NJ, 1957).

  71 See Henri Grange, Les Idées de Necker (1974), 53–9, 514–614.

  72 Necker, De l’importance de la morale et des opinions religieuses (1788).

  73 Armstrong Kelly, The Humane Comedy: Constant, Tocqueville, and French Liberalism

  (Cambridge, 1992), 95.

  74 Necker, De l’importance, 21.

  Religion, Enlightenment, and Reaction

  313

  behaviour of a ‘virtuous atheist’, he maintained, merely reflected ‘the indirect

  influence of religious opinions’.75

  All the evidence suggests that Necker’s own experiences in the Revolution did

  little to change these convictions. In 1800 he published his three-volume Cours de

  morale religieuse.76 The topics addressed ranged from divine providence and the

  immortality of the soul to conjugal duty and the general principles of morality.

  Nothing, he there reaffirmed, was more important to nations than the alliance

  between morality and religion. And the best of religions was one that was ‘simple,

  reasonable, and pure’ and free of ‘fanatical intolerance’ and superstition. Only such

  a religion, ‘majestic in its simplicity’, would provide us with the ‘wisdom’ and

  ‘dignity’ required to make proper use of our liberty. Religion fostered the spirit of

  moderation.

  We could speculate at some length about the influence such Calvinist piety had

  upon Necker’s daughter, Germaine de Staël. By all accounts she received a solid

  religious education from her parents and one which, if light on dogma, emphasized

  the reasonableness of Christianity.77 Like her father, she came to believe in the

  social benefits of religion. Indeed, she developed this argument further by suggest-

  ing that nowhere was this more so than in a republic. Writing in Des Circonstances

  actuelles qui peuvent terminer la Révolution,78 she bewailed the ‘demoralization’ of

  France under the Republic—everyone, she stated, was motivated by self-interest

  and the love of money—and asserted that only a morality supported by religion

  could provide a ‘complete code’ covering all our actions as well as ‘a code which

  unites men by way of a kind of covenant of souls, the indispensable preliminary to

  any social contract’. Religion alone, she argued, could endow us with a sense of

  personal dignity, an awareness of the perfectibility of the human spirit, and a love of

  virtue. In the same text, Madame de Staël completely dismissed the idea that

  religion was only necessary for the ignorant masses. ‘Nothing’, she wrote, ‘seems

  more to be detested than this assertion.’79

  Similarly, she never tired of announcing the merits of Protestantism over

  Catholicism. ‘The Reformation’, she wrote in De la Littérature considérée dans ses

  rapports avec les institutions sociales, ‘is the period of history that most effectively

  served the perfectibility of the human species. The Protestant religion contains

  within itself no active germ of superstition and gives to virtue every support that can

  be gained from sensible opinions. In those countries where the Protestant religion is

  professed, it does nothing to prevent philosophical research and efficaciously

  maintains the purity of morals.’80 Luther, she was later to write, recalled religion

  to the land of thought.81 Just as importantly, Madame de Staël realized that the

  75 Ibid. 78.

  76 Necker, Cours de morale religieuse, 3 vols. (Geneva, 1800). See esp. vol. i, pp. i–xliv.

  77 See Rosenblatt, Liberal Values, 34–5.

  78 Written in 1798, this text was publ. posthumously.

  79 Germaine de Staël, Des Circonstances actuelles qui peuvent terminer la Révolution (1906), 212–29.

  80 Staël-Holstein, De la Littérature considérée dans ses rapports avec les institutions sociales (1800),

  i. 311.

  81 Germaine de Staël, De l’Allemagne (1968), ii. 245.

  314

  Religion, Enlightenment, and Reaction

  advocates of revolution had made the mistake of believing that only an atheist could

  love liberty and that aristocratic privilege and the absolute power of the throne were

  integral to religious belief. It was Christianity, she countered, that had ‘brought

  liberty to this earth, justice to the oppressed, respect for the unfortunate, and finally

  equality before God, of which equality before the law is only an imperfect

  reflection’.82 If, as she willingly conceded, the light of reason was necessary to

  free us from our prejudices, then, by the same token, it was ‘in the soul that the

  principles of liberty are grounded’.83

  Yet Madame de Staël’s religious sensibilities were nothing if not complex. Her

  original Calvinism had overlaid upon it elements of Rousseauian deism and, after

  the turn of the century, Kantianism84 and, later still, aesthetic mysticism. ‘Religious

  emotions, more than all others together,’ she wrote, ‘awaken in us the feeling of the

  infinite.’85 The universe, she was also to write, resembled a poem rather than a

  machine. It is not, therefore, without some justification that Madame de Staël has

  been seen as one of the founders of European Romanticism. However, it was these

  religious views—those of a ‘good Calvinist’, as she once described herself 86—that

&n
bsp; not only underpinned her criticisms of the political fanaticism of the Terror, but

  also informed her censure of the Republic and her disparagement of Bonaparte. She

  had only disdain for Napoleon’s attempt to reinstate the dominant position of the

  Catholic Church.

  Germaine de Staël’s most sustained engagement with matters relating to religion

  is found in what was arguably her most important work, De l’Allemagne. The text

  was begun in exile in Weimar in 1808, where she had been reading Schiller and

  Fichte and conversing at length with such friends as Auguste von Schlegel. Through

  this she became persuaded that Germany was the very antithesis of France, that the

  genius and erudition of the Germans was the very opposite of the superficiality and

  mediocrity of the French. Their literature and philosophy were untouched by the

  spirit of materialism and concerned themselves with the most hidden mysteries of

  our being. ‘The German moralists’, she wrote, ‘have raised up sentiment and

  enthusiasm from the contempt of a tyrannical reason.’87 To that extent, it struck

  her that the Germanic nations were ‘naturally religious’ and ‘metaphysical’. More-

  over, theirs was a religion of inner conviction rather than fanaticism, of contempla-

  tion and meditation rather than dogmatism. The Catholic religion in Germany, she

  conceded, was more tolerant than in any other country.88 By way of contrast, she

  made perfectly explicit her criticism of the French philosophy of the eighteenth

  century. If ‘the new German philosophy’ respected religion and affirmed the moral

  dignity of man, the French variety rested upon a ‘scoffing scepticism’ that was, in

  82 Germaine de Staël, Considérations sur la Révolution française (1983), 604.

  83 Ibid. 605.

  84 An important influence was Charles de Villers. In 1804 he had publ. Essai sur l’esprit et l’influence

  de la Réformation de Luther.

  85 Staël, De l’Allemagne, ii. 238.

  86 Staël, Des Circonstances, 220.

  87 Staël, De l’Allemagne, ii. 200.

  88 Ibid. 255.

  Religion, Enlightenment, and Reaction

  315

  her opinion, ‘destructive of every belief of the heart’. It was, she remarked more

  than once, a ‘degrading doctrine’ based upon a mixture of ‘frivolity’ of the mind

 

‹ Prev