Book Read Free

Revolution and the Republic

Page 96

by Jeremy Jennings


  was a ‘literary and intellectual’ tradition. Great literature had given the French soul

  a ‘truthful expression, a durable expression, an immortal expression’. In Le Génie

  latin he made clear his view that the particular genius of the French was to be

  ‘Latins in sentiment, Latins in morals, Latins in taste, Latins in spirit, Latins in

  language, and Latins in thought’. If we cease to be Latins, he wrote, ‘we will cease

  at the same time to be French’.76 The third tradition, and by far the most

  important, was religion. Specifying that he spoke as ‘neither believer nor moralist

  but simply as a historian and an observer’, Brunetière’s conclusion was unequivocal:

  ‘What I determine in both fact and history is that . . . in the same way that

  Protestantism is England and “orthodoxy” is Russia, so France is Catholicism.

  What I determine, in both fact and history, is that for twelve centuries the role of

  acting as a protector and propagandist of Catholicism has belonged to France.’77

  This, therefore, was Brunetière’s conclusion: ‘everything that we do, everything

  that we allow to be done, against Catholicism, we allow to be done and we do it to

  the detriment of our influence in the world, against the grain of our history, and at

  72 Brunetière, L’Idée de patrie (1896).

  73 Brunetière, Les Ennemis de l’âme française (1899).

  74 See Brunetière, Discours de combat (1920), 249–91.

  75 See also ‘La Nation et l’armée’, ibid. 215–48.

  76 ‘Le Génie latin’, ibid. 289–90.

  77 Les Ennemis de l’âme française, 57–8.

  454

  France, Intellectuals, and Engagement

  the expense of the qualities which are those of the “French soul”’.78 You could not,

  Brunetière concluded, be ‘French and anti-Catholic’.79

  It was these traditions, Brunetière resumed, that had made France what she was

  and to that extent they were ‘neither monarchical nor republican, but were French,

  uniquely French’. However, he was in no doubt that ‘the best of governments’

  would always be the one which most respected French traditions and that ‘the best

  of institutions’ would be those which allowed these traditions to develop and to be

  renewed. Similarly, in a long footnote to his published text, Brunetière was careful

  to specify that being a Protestant or a Jew or a Muslim or even a ‘Free-thinker’ was

  not what he meant by being anti-Catholic: what he had in mind, he assured his

  readers, was the ‘militant and active’ anti-Catholicism of groups such as the Free-

  masons. He also made it clear in L’Idée de patrie that he did not believe that races

  formed nations. ‘The French race’, he wrote, ‘is not the producer but rather the

  creation or, if I dare say so, the created being of the history of France.’80 Neverthe-

  less, and despite Brunetière’s attempt to portray French history as one long

  unbroken continuum, it is clear that the Catholic religion was to be considered a

  fundamental dimension of the identity and meaning of France and that those who

  were not Catholics could scarcely be considered full members of the nation.

  In Brunetière’s view, the French soul was under attack and France was internally

  weakened. By whom? By politicians, intellectuals, and freethinkers was his answer.

  By all those who, ‘in their desperate assault on all our traditions, confound a liberty

  of spirit with an independence of the heart’. All these had worked ‘to denature the

  French soul’, to turn the ‘essentially sociable’ French towards individualism. This

  was to be the central theme of the numerous articles that Brunetière published in

  the Revue des Deux Mondes as well as the essays that appeared in the series of

  volumes entitled Discours de combat. In these pieces can be discerned a consistent

  and loud objection to subjectivism, scepticism, rationalism, moral relativism, and

  what was repeatedly characterized as intellectual dilettantism. This translated itself

  into a hostility towards literary Romanticism, the theory of art for art’s sake, the

  naturalism of Émile Zola’s novels, the errors of the philosophy of the eighteenth

  century, Protestantism as a form of ‘individual salvation’, and what was described as

  a Nietzschean ‘aristocracy of intelligence’. These texts endorsed not only the merits

  of tradition over novelty and the future triumph of idealism over materialism in

  science, art, and politics but also the idea of solidarity as ‘a Christian and, above all,

  Catholic idea’.81 Brunetière was equally of the opinion that there were reasons to

  believe in God and, moreover, that we needed to believe in God. Before this

  mystery, he avowed, all one could do was yield.82 Given the universality of the

  Catholic faith, he did not believe in the need for a national church.83

  78 Les Ennemis de l’âme française, 58.

  79 Ibid. 67.

  80 L’Idée de patrie, 19.

  81 See esp. ‘L’Idée de solidarité’, in Discours de combat (1903), 49–83; L’Action sociale du

  Christianisme (Besançon, 1904); and ‘La Renaissance de l’idéalisme’, Discours de combat (1920), 3–57.

  82 ‘Le Besoin de croire’, Revue des Deux Mondes, 150 (1898), 702–20, and ‘Les Raisons actuelles de

  croire’, Discours de combat (1903), 1–48.

  83 ‘Voulons-nous une église nationale?’, Revue des Deux Mondes, 6 (1901), 277–94.

  France, Intellectuals, and Engagement

  455

  For all the ambiguities and contradictions in Brunetière’s position––always the

  acute observer, Georges Sorel was to comment after Brunetière’s death that ‘this

  man who was so perceptive in his study of texts displayed considerable naivety in

  matters concerning practical life’84––he nevertheless provided a formidable and

  powerful combination of ideas of great appeal to the nationalist right. Deployed by

  Brunetière at the height of the Dreyfus Affair, this anti-individualist and Catholic

  vision of France challenged many of the basic presuppositions of republican politics

  and culture at the turn of the century. Where these meanings of France could lead

  was best illustrated by Brunetière’s fellow member of the Ligue de la patrie

  française, Maurice Barrès,85 author of Scènes et doctrines du nationalisme and one

  of the most popular writers of his day.

  Here too there was an attempt to transcend and to encompass all aspects and

  features of French history, be they Catholic, revolutionary, or Bonapartist. ‘Let us

  leave these tales’, Barrès wrote, ‘we find greater profit in merging ourselves together

  with all the moments of the history of France, in living with her dead, in not placing

  ourselves beyond any of her experiences.’86 All these conflicting experiences, he

  continued, ‘proceed from the same source and lead to the same goal: they are the

  development of the same seed and the fruits of the same tree’.87 No conception of

  France could prevail over ‘the France of flesh or blood’. Yet, this generosity of spirit

  and of vision quickly vanished when Barrès came to speak of Protestants, and

  especially of Jews. The ‘Catholic world’, Barrès wrote, ‘is where my forebears grew

  to maturity and prepared the way for me. As a consequence I find it the least jarring

&nb
sp; to my nature. It can best accommodate my various roles and best promote the life

  suited to my nature.’88 This was why he felt able to celebrate ‘the destruction of the

  Protestant forces’: ‘I intend to preserve the benefits of this victory with all the power

  at my command, for it enables the tree of which I am one leaf to continue to exist.’

  Barrès pointed out that in Alsace and Lorraine it was the Protestants who were most

  likely to accept German rule.

  The Jew, as a member of ‘a race antagonistic to my own’, fared even worse in the

  Barrèsian scheme of things. The Jews, Barrès argued, had no patrie in the way the

  French understood it. For them, it was not a matter of their native soil and of their

  ancestors but ‘only a place where they find greatest profit’. Thus, Barrès had no

  difficulty comprehending the nature of Dreyfus’s crime. ‘In psychological terms’,

  Barrès wrote, ‘it is sufficient for me to know that he is capable of treason’ and this he

  was able to ‘deduce from his race’.89 On this view, the actual guilt or otherwise of

  Dreyfus appeared almost irrelevant and of secondary importance. What mattered,

  as Barrès never tired of repeating, was that the question should be resolved ‘in

  light of the interests of France’. And by these standards Dreyfus was guilty. Indeed,

  84 Review of V. Giraud, Ferdinand Brunetière, Notes et Souvenirs, in Le Mouvement socialiste, 22

  (1908), 93–4.

  85 See Zeev Sternhell, Maurice Barrès et le nationalisme français (2000).

  86 Scènes et doctrines du nationalisme (1906), 82.

  87 Ibid. 83.

  88 Ibid. 60.

  89 Ibid. 152.

  456

  France, Intellectuals, and Engagement

  the ‘worst crime’ of Dreyfus and his supporters in their ‘anti-French campaign’ was

  that for the past five years they had weakened the army and the nation.90

  This, according to Barrès, was an argument that the intellectuals, with their

  passion for metaphysics and abstract truth, could not understand. An intellectual,

  he announced, is ‘an individual who convinces himself that society should be

  founded on the basis of logic and who fails to see that it rests on past exigencies

  that precede and are perhaps foreign to individual reason’.91 Such was the case with

  the central figure in Barrès’s famous novel Les Déracinés,92 the professor of philos-

  ophy Paul Bouteiller. The charge was that he, and those in real life like him who

  taught what Barrès regarded as the official Kantian doctrine of the educational

  system, approached man as ‘an abstract universal entity’ and encouraged their

  students to become ‘citizens of humanity, free spirits, initiates of pure reason’. As

  a result, all were ‘uprooted’ from their race and from their land. All became

  incapable of bearing witness to ‘French truth and French justice’.93 The intellectual

  thus functioned as ‘the enemy of society’, producing a decadence that derived from

  ‘a lack of moral unity’ and the absence of a ‘common understanding of our goal, our

  resources, our centre’. They were ‘the anarchists of the speaker’s platform’.94 ‘As

  for ourselves’, Barrès commented, ‘we are happier to be intelligent than to be

  intellectual.’95

  Nationalism, therefore, was defined by Barrès as the acceptance of a form of

  determinism.96 It was a ‘sense of descent’, a way of seeing things deeply rooted in

  the soil of France, her history, and her ‘national conscience’. Correctly understood,

  it provided a series of ‘fixed points’ and ‘landmarks’ that ‘over the preceding

  centuries have educated our reflexes’. So Zola’s defence of Dreyfus could be

  explained by the fact that he was not French but rather ‘an uprooted Venetian’.97

  The outrage with regard to occupied Alsace and Lorraine was that little French

  children were being prevented from thinking and speaking like Frenchmen.

  Those ‘too recently’ accepted into the French nation had troubled the ‘national

  conscience’ precisely because they bore the blood of their non-French ancestors.

  Accordingly, it was among the people, among those uncontaminated by the

  aberrations of rationalism, that was to be found the authentic expression of the

  nation’s true instincts in all their vigour and vitality.

  These views carried with them a clear political programme. Nationalism, Barrès

  argued, necessitated a series of ‘protectionist’ measures designed to defend the

  French people. The nationality laws were to be tightened in order to reduce ‘the

  interference of the foreigner into our politics’. Laws on the ownership of property

  were to be designed so as to prevent foreigners possessing ‘the soil of France’ and to

  limit their commercial and industrial activities. The ‘financial feudality’ comprised

  of Protestants and the ‘kingdom of Israel’––described by Barrès as ‘the dangerous

  plutocracy of exotics from which France might perish’––was to be challenged and

  90 Scènes et doctrines du nationalisme (1906), 209.

  91 Ibid. 45.

  92 Barrès, Les Déracinés (1897).

  93 Scènes et doctrines du nationalisme, 13.

  94 Ibid. 220.

  95 Ibid. 45.

  96 Ibid. 8–10.

  97 Ibid. 40.

  France, Intellectuals, and Engagement

  457

  defeated through a series of measures designed to secure the economic interests of

  French workers. The union of the race and of the earth was to be sealed by granting

  ‘a corner of the land’ to every French family. There was to be no room for either

  cosmopolitan socialism or economic liberalism. ‘Our salvation’, Barrès concluded,

  ‘lies in ceasing to be uprooted and scattered individuals.’98

  To the opinions voiced by both Brunetière and Barrès, the Dreyfusard camp

  made an immediate reply. Against Brunetière’s Après le Procès was lined up Émile

  Duclaux’s Avant le Procès,99 Alphonse Darlu’s M. Brunetière et l’individualisme,100

  and, thirdly, Émile Durkheim’s L’Individualisme et les intellectuels.101 If Duclaux

  again defended the liberty, impartiality, and competence of the ‘scientific spirit’ and

  therefore the duty of ‘intellectuals’ to make use of their expertise on matters of

  public concern,102 Darlu, one of the founders of the Revue de métaphysique et de

  morale, was quick to point out that Brunetière had misconceived the nature of the

  individualism he so deplored and as a result had exaggerated its dangers. Of greater

  force and interest was the response of Durkheim. Like Darlu, Durkheim was of the

  opinion that Brunetière had mistaken individualism for ‘the utilitarian egoism’ of

  Herbert Spencer and of liberal political economy. This, Durkheim conceded, did

  amount to an ‘egoistic cult of the self’ but it was in decline and had, in any case, to

  be placed alongside ‘another individualism’, one derived from Kant, Rousseau, and

  the Déclaration des Droits de l’Homme of 1789. This form of individualism, he

  countered, saw all actions carried out for personal gain ‘as the very source of evil’

  and saw the human person as sacred. It also held that ‘there was no reason of State

  which can excuse an outrage against the person’.103 So, Durkheim argued, turning

&n
bsp; the tables upon his opponents, ‘not only is individualism not anarchy but hence-

  forth it is the only system of beliefs which is able to ensure the moral unity of the

  country’.104 This was so because, as societies grew in size and complexity, it was

  impossible to ‘prevent men from becoming increasingly differentiated from one

  another’ or ‘to bring them back to the conformism of earlier times’. In those

  circumstances, the only viable alternative was to ‘complete, extend, and organize’

  the individualism bequeathed by the eighteenth century, to pass beyond the

  ‘negative ideal’ of freeing the individual from the political fetters that bound him,

  such that we might learn properly to make use of our liberty. ‘All moral education’,

  Durkheim wrote, ‘should be directed to this end.’105

  What of Brunetière’s case against the intellectual? What, as Durkheim put it, of

  his argument that ‘intellectual and moral anarchy would be the inevitable conse-

  quence of liberalism?’106 ‘Respect for authority’, Durkheim replied, ‘was in no way

  98 Ibid. 425–77.

  99 Émile Duclaux, Avant le Procès (1898).

  100 Alphonse Darlu, M. Brunetière et l’individualisme (1898).

  101 Revue bleue, 10 (1898), 7–13.

  102 A year later Duclaux showed himself to be far less eager to express a view on anti-Semitism. ‘It is

  not my habit’, he explained, ‘to make prophecies that scarcely fall within my field of competence’: see

  Henri Dagan, Enquête sur l‘antisémitisme (1898), 52.

  103 Revue bleue, 8–9.

  104 Ibid. 10.

  105 Ibid. 13.

  106 Ibid. 10.

  458

  France, Intellectuals, and Engagement

  incompatible with rationalism provided that authority itself was rationally ground-

  ed.’107 However, the case of Dreyfus was ‘one of those questions which, by

  definition, pertained to the common judgement’ of men. To know whether a

  court of justice might try a man without hearing his defence, Durkheim continued,

  there was no need of any ‘special knowledge’. It was a matter of ‘practical morality’

  upon which everyone of good sense was competent and about which no one could

  be indifferent. If, Durkheim concluded,

  a certain number of artists, but above all scientists, have believed that they ought to

 

‹ Prev