Book Read Free

Revolution and the Republic

Page 102

by Jeremy Jennings

it only succeeded to replacing one regime by another, if it did not effect a

  transformation of the moral conscience of man.

  Reworking a formula first devised by Jacques Maritain, primacy was to be given

  to the spiritual over the material. This quite definitely did not entail an endorse-

  ment of bourgeois idealism (Mounier spoke of an ‘anaemic idealism’) or indeed of a

  bogus reactionary spiritualism, but was rather to be grounded upon what Mounier

  referred to as ‘the concrete’ or ‘living individual’. It was for this reason that Mounier

  defined the doctrine of Esprit as that of ‘personalism’. ‘A personalist civilization’,

  Mounier explained,

  is a civilization whose structures and intelligence are directed towards enabling all those

  individuals who comprise it to become persons. Natural collectivities are there recog-

  nized as realities, as possessing their own purpose, as being different from the sum of

  individual interests and as being superior to the interests of the individual. Nevertheless

  they have as their ultimate goal that of placing each person in a condition where they

  257 Jean-Louis Loubet del Bayle, Les Non-Conformistes des années trente (1969).

  258 See Michel Winock, Histoire Politique de la Revue ‘Esprit’ 1930–1950 (1975) and Loubet del

  Bayle, Les Non-Conformistes, 121–57.

  482

  France, Intellectuals, and Engagement

  can live as a person, where they can enjoy the maximum of initiative, of responsibility,

  and of spiritual life.259

  Aligned to this would be a ‘personalist democracy’ which, as Mounier was at pains

  to point out, would be far removed from ‘a liberal and parliamentary democracy’

  resting upon ‘the postulate of popular sovereignty’ and ‘the myth of the will of the

  people’.260

  Such views fed into a powerful sense of dissatisfaction with the democratic institu-

  tions of what Albert Thibaudet termed the ‘République des professeurs’.261 Contempt

  for politicians, for political parties, and for politics in general now became almost the

  norm as government after government failed to meet the challenges posed by France’s

  domestic and international problems. This malaise received graphic illustration with

  the right-wing riots of 6 February 1934 in Paris, interpreted by many as an abortive

  fascist coup. The intellectuals of the left responded with the creation of the Comité

  de vigilance des intellectuelles antifascistes, whilst the electorate voted into power the

  left-wing Popular Front government in 1936. The extreme right, now with Jewish

  premier Léon Blum as one of their principal targets and scapegoats––‘Rather Hitler

  than Blum’ read the famous slogan––only intensified their campaign against what

  they saw as a corrupt and degenerate political regime. This ill-tempered frame of

  mind was captured brilliantly in Robert Brasillach’s autobiographical account, Notre

  avant-guerre, published in 1941 and dated ‘6 February Year VII. National Revolu-

  tion’.262 For Brasillach, the Popular Front was nothing less than a ‘revolution of

  intellectuals’ leading to ‘the ruin of the State’ and the ‘vulgarization of immorality’.

  Never had stupidity, pedantry, and mediocrity been more in evidence. Out of this

  ‘extraordinary bedlam’ the workers had become convinced that they had no need to

  work and that everything would be provided by the government. Hope for France,

  he therefore believed, lay in abandoning ‘the promises of liberalism, the equality of

  man, and the will of the people’ and in following the example of Nazi Germany.

  There, he wrote, we have seen the ‘birth of fascist man’, young, virile, proud of ‘his

  race and of his nation’. Here was the basis of an intellectual collaboration that followed

  the fall of France in 1940263 and which, in Brasillach’s own case, led to his execution

  for treason in 1945.

  There is a question mark over how extensive such collaboration was.264 Jeannine

  Verdès-Leroux, for example, has argued that there were ‘few true writers ready

  to declare themselves as collaborators’.265 Those that did, she believes, were mostly

  second-rate and there is no evidence to suggest that writers were queuing up to

  be invited to the Institut allemand in Paris. Others would disagree, pointing to the

  259 ‘Manifeste au service du personnalisme’, in Œuvres de Mounier (1961), i. 523.

  260 Ibid. 619.

  261 Albert Thibaudet, La République des professeurs (1927).

  262 Robert Brasillach, Notre avant-guerre (1941).

  263 See Julian Jackson, The Fall of France: The Nazi Invasion of 1940 (Oxford, 2003). See also the

  classic text by Marc Bloch, L’Étrange Défaite (1946).

  264 See Albrecht Betz and Stefan Martens (eds.), Les Intellectuels et l’Occupation 1940–1944:

  Collaborer, partir, résister (2004).

  265 Refus et violences: Politique et littérature à l’extrême droite des années trente aux retombées de la

  Libération (1996), 216.

  France, Intellectuals, and Engagement

  483

  examples of Drieu la Rochelle, Henry de Montherlant, and Lucien Rebatet as

  evidence of widespread collaboration. What is undoubtedly true is that the world of

  wartime intellectual collaboration was constituted by a curious hotchpotch of

  convinced fascists (of one sort or another),266 pacifists, defeatists, anti-Semites,

  anti-Communists, outright opportunists, and, later, anti-Gaullists. What is also

  clear is that those who were prepared to cast themselves as the ideologues of the

  National Revolution267 instituted by Marshal Pétain’s Vichy regime268 were drawn

  from both the right and the left and that they were prepared to call upon a very

  diverse set of sources as guides to the intellectual character and inspiration of the

  New Europe. In 1942, for example, the writer Alfred Fabre-Luce published an

  Anthologie de la Nouvelle Europe.269 In addition to readings taken from Hitler,

  Mussolini, Gobineau, Nietzsche, Richard Wagner, and others of a similar hue, he

  also selected texts from Renan, Georges Sorel, Charles Péguy, Paul Nizan, specifi-

  cally arguing in his preface that ‘Proudhon, Michelet, Quinet, sons of 89 and active

  participants in 1848, had already treated national socialist themes: respect for force,

  a counter-religion, the cult of the family and of the homeland.’270

  It was arguably the monarchist doctrines of Action Française and of its principal

  theoretician, Charles Maurras, rather than the temptations of fascism, which received

  the greatest interest from those eager to save something from the wreckage of

  humiliating defeat. For Maurras, the defeat of 1940 amounted to ‘a divine surprise’.

  Despite his anti-Germanism, he had no hesitation in calling for unconditional

  support of Marshal Pétain and the Vichy regime. Writing in La Seule France, he

  sought to blame France’s defeat upon disunity and to protect the armed forces from

  any blame, arguing that ‘the government of parties is the symbol of our divisions’. ‘In

  France’, he proclaimed, ‘the Republic is the reign of the Foreigner.’271 Accordingly,

  the restoration of both the State and the nation would require putting an end to ‘the

  enormous power and monstrous influence exercised in France by people of a foreign

  birth and
culture’. Maurras therefore supported the anti-Semitic and anti-Masonic

  legislation associated with the National Revolution, defended measures to strengthen

  the family, advocated educational reform designed to give greater influence to the

  Church, called for an end to democratic liberties, and promoted a series of industrial

  measures intended to forge a community of interests between workers and owners.

  Yet, as the abject failure (not to mention corruption and political infighting) of

  Vichy’s political programme revealed, Maurras’s own conception of France, of the

  ‘pays réel’, no longer had any significant purchase upon the real world. The clock

  could not be turned back to pre-1789. Ironically, Maurras himself was a perfect

  illustration of the problem, for his (as we might recall) was a Catholicism without

  faith. He was an unbeliever.

  266 See Philippe Burrin, La Dérive fasciste: Doriot, Déat, Bergery, 1933–1945 (1986).

  267 See Philippe Burrin, ‘The Ideology of the National Revolution’, in Edward J. Arnold (ed.), The

  Development of the Radical Right in France (Houndmills, 2000), 135–52.

  268 See Julian Jackson, France: The Dark Years 1940–1944 (Oxford, 2001).

  269 Alfred Fabre-Luce, Anthologie de la nouvelle Europe (1942).

  270 Ibid., pp. ii–iii. See Daniel Lindenberg, Les Années souterraines 1937–1947 (1990).

  271 La Seule France (1941), 136.

  484

  France, Intellectuals, and Engagement

  There are two further aspects of intellectual collaboration meriting our brief

  attention. The first concerns attitudes towards the French Revolution. It should

  come as no surprise that pro-Vichy and pro-Nazi sympathizers were, in the main,

  hostile to the Revolution of 1789. In their view, the Revolution had been illegiti-

  mate, bequeathing a political regime characterized by chronic instability and a

  society in the grip of moral decadence. In a special edition of the review Je suis

  partout marking the 150th anniversary of the Revolution, for example, Robert

  Brasillach wrote that there was no reason to believe that the leaders of the Revolu-

  tion had been any less corrupt than the politicians of the Third Republic, whilst

  right-wing historian Pierre Gaxotte defined the Revolution as ‘an exercise in

  expropriation and extermination’. The other contributions were similar in tone

  and strident in their denunciation of a Revolution led by Jews and Freemasons.

  Nevertheless, for the aspiring Fascist there was much to admire in the cold and

  calculating leadership of Robespierre and the dictatorial power exercised by the

  Jacobins. Viewed from this perspective, their hostility to the bourgeois, liberal state,

  their preoccupation with the nation and national defence, and their emphasis on

  their own discipline and purity (not to mention, their ruthless dispatch of their

  enemies) offered an eighteenth-century prefiguration of national-socialism. For the

  tormented souls dreaming of a new order, the Revolution of Year II, Robespierre’s

  Revolution, was a form of totalitarianism avant la lettre.272

  The second aspect worthy of comment was a virulent form of self-hatred. In large

  part this focused upon France, and what was taken to be her decadence, her

  bourgeois culture, her rationalism, her materialism, her supine surrender, her vanity

  and arrogance, her abominable political leaders. ‘France’, Drieu la Rochelle con-

  fided to his diary in 1942, ‘is finished, a second or perhaps even a third-rate

  country.’273 She had become, novelist Roger Peyrefitte wrote, ‘a civilization of

  shop girls’.274 To an extent these sentiments were fuelled by snobbery and by what

  amounted to an aristocratic contempt for the masses, but they also were fired by a

  form of self-loathing that went beyond a detestation of Jews and of pederasts. Again

  Drieu la Rochelle pointed the way. His writings displayed hatred for others and

  self-disgust in equal measure. However, particular opprobrium was heaped upon

  the intellectual as a physically weak, effeminate, impotent, and sick individual, the

  very embodiment of a lack of vitality and virility. Faced with his own imperfection

  as a disembodied subhuman, therefore, Drieu la Rochelle idealized the man of

  action and longed for a world of youth, vigour, life, honour, and heroism. With his

  realization that collaboration had failed, he descended into self-pitying pessimism.

  In 1944 he refused all offers of escape from France and committed suicide in March

  of the following year.275

  272 See George L. Mosse, ‘Fascism and the French Revolution’, Journal of Contemporary History, 24

  (1989), 5–26, and Shlomo Sand, ‘Les Représentations de la Révolution dans l’imaginaire historique du

  fascisme français’, Mil Neuf Cent, 9 (1991), 29–48.

  273 Journal 1939–1945 (1992), 318.

  274 Quoted in Jackson, France: The Dark Years, 211.

  275 See Pascal Balmand, ‘Anti-Intellectualism in French Political Culture’, in Jeremy Jennings (ed.),

  Intellectuals in Twentieth-Century France (Houndmills, 1993), 165–9. See also Pascal Ory,

  France, Intellectuals, and Engagement

  485

  One writer who was immune from such spiritual impoverishment was Simone

  Weil.276 Born in 1909 of Jewish ancestry, Weil was educated at the prestigious

  Lycée Henri IV in Paris and at the École Nationale Supérieure, where she studied

  philosophy. Upon graduation, the naturally rebellious Weil took up a teaching

  post in the provincial town of Le Puy and (somewhat uneasily) managed to

  combine her professional duties with militant trade unionism as well as writing

  for both La Révolution prolétarienne, edited by Pierre Monatte, and Boris Souvar-

  ine’s La Critique sociale.277 Never an admirer of the French Communist Party or of

  orthodox Marxism, she set about the writing of Oppression et liberté and did so in

  the firm conviction that we were living in an age ‘without a future’.278

  Since 1789, Weil argued, each new generation had placed its hopes in revolution

  but such hopes could no longer be sustained. Weil based this claim upon a critique

  of the Soviet Union––Lenin and the Bolsheviks, in her view, had succeeded only

  in creating a new form of oppression imposed upon the proletariat by a state

  bureaucracy and a privileged intellectual caste––but, more fundamentally, and

  contrary to the views of Marx, she believed that the capitalist system had not

  ‘developed within itself the material conditions required for a regime of liberty

  and equality’.279 Rather, Weil was convinced that the division, specialization, and

  mechanization of labour typical of modern production methods fashioned the

  possibility of a permanent enslavement of the workers and not their free association.

  Never, Weil wrote, has the individual been so completely delivered up to a ‘blind

  collectivity’. Never had the ‘social machine’ worked more efficiently at ‘breaking

  hearts and crushing spirits’280 Such a bleak vision provided few grounds for

  optimism, but Weil was adamant that the ‘most fully human civilization’ would

  place the dignity of ‘manual labour’ at its centre and as its highest value. The best

  that we could do in these circumstances, Weil wrote, was to ‘strive to introduce a

  little play into the cogs of the machi
ne that crushes us’.281

  It was after the completion of Oppression et liberté in the autumn of 1934 that

  Weil resigned as a teacher and began working as a machine operative in a factory.

  This painful experience only confirmed her fatalism. The same was true of the

  Popular Front. Despite her initial enthusiasm and sense of joy, the strikes and

  factory occupations of the summer of 1936 served to convince her further that a

  radical social transformation was not possible. Nevertheless, with the outbreak of

  the civil war in Spain, Weil made her way to Barcelona to join the anarchists where,

  like many a volunteer, she proved to be more of a hindrance than a help. What

  followed was a period of profound reflection and her conversion to a deeply

  spiritual Christianity.

  L’Anarchisme de droite ou du mépris considéré comme une morale (1985) and François Richard,

  L’Anarchisme de droite dans la littérature contemporaine (1988).

  276 See Mary G. Dietz, Between the Human and the Divine: The Political Thought of Simone Weil

  (Totowa, NJ, 1988).

  277 See Weil, Œuvres complètes, II/1. L’Engagement syndical (1927–juillet 1934) (1988).

  278 Oppression et liberté (1955), 58.

  279 Ibid. 63.

  280 Ibid. 142.

  281 Ibid. 158.

  486

  France, Intellectuals, and Engagement

  In the few years that were to remain to her––Weil died in Ashford, Kent, on

  23 August 1943 at the age of 34––a preoccupation with the divine became ever

  more present in her thoughts and her writings but the realities of politics––most

  notably, the rise of Nazism and the fall of France in 1940––could not be avoided.

  Living in Marseilles, Weil left for New York in May 1942 and arrived in London in

  December of the same year. She there joined the Free French and, with her health

  in rapid decline, wrote a long and unfinished manuscript entitled ‘L’Enracine-

  ment’.282 Subtitled ‘Prelude to a Declaration of Duties towards Mankind’, it was

  explicitly intended as a contribution to the debates about what form of government

  and society was required in post-liberation France. To say the least, Weil’s views did

  not chime with those of many of her exiled compatriots.

  The manuscript itself was divided into three sections. The first explored our

 

‹ Prev