Book Read Free

Revolution and the Republic

Page 106

by Jeremy Jennings


  Strauss continued the anti-Sartrean theme, announcing that the ‘elimination

  of the subject represents what might be called a methodological need’ and that

  structuralism, by reintegrating man into nature, made it ‘possible to disregard the

  subject––that unbearably spoilt child who has occupied the philosophical scene for

  too long’. Existentialism, Lévi-Strauss concluded, was ‘a self-admiring activity which

  allows contemporary man, rather gullibly, to commune with himself in ecstatic

  contemplation of his own being’. The allotted task of structuralism, in short, was

  to break with the philosophical inheritance of humanism, an aim fully articulated

  in the last sentence of Michel Foucault’s Les Mots et les choses, where the reader was

  told that man was a recent invention who would soon disappear ‘like a face drawn in

  sand at the edge of the sea’.

  This anti-humanist position, rooted in dissatisfaction with the phenomenologi-

  cal theory of the subject, found a variety of expressions in the writings of structur-

  alism. Roland Barthes, championing the reader and announcing ‘the pleasure of the

  text’, spoke of ‘the death of the author’. Likewise, Jacques Lacan, reworking Freud,

  rebelled against the ‘ego-centred’ character of psychoanalysis and used the basic

  concepts of Ferdinand de Saussure’s structural linguistics to illustrate that the

  conscious life of the individual did not provide the means of its own intelligibility.

  Althusser, as we have already seen, spoke of history as ‘a process without a subject’.

  Who exactly the structuralists were and whether they constituted a fixed and

  identifiable group or school are not questions that deflect from the fact that the

  1960s was a very much the structuralist decade. Their work received immense

  critical (and popular) acclaim, sold in huge quantities and effectively established a

  new philosophical orthodoxy or paradigm. In large part, however, this success can

  be attributed to non-philosophical causes. The vogue for structuralism coincided

  with France’s belated entry into the consumer society and seemed to postulate its

  350 Judt, Past Imperfect, French Intellectuals 1944–1956 (Berkeley and Los Angeles, Calif., 1992), 154.

  351 Claude Lévi-Strauss. La Pensée sauvage (1962).

  352 Claude Lévi-Strauss, L’Homme nu (1971).

  France, Intellectuals, and Engagement

  501

  decisive rejection. This was most obvious in Lévi-Strauss’s explicit challenge to the

  supposed superiority and universality of the categories of Western reason. ‘The

  scientific spirit in its most modern form’, Lévi-Strauss wrote, will serve ‘to legiti-

  mize the principles of savage thought and to re-establish it in its rightful place’.353

  Similarly, the structuralist challenge to the values of the bourgeois and capitalist

  society of the West was evident in Lacan’s ethics of desire and in Foucault’s ethics of

  liberation. It was there too in the work of Roland Barthes. In his preface to the

  1970 edition of Mythologies, for example, he wrote as follows: ‘I had just read

  Saussure and as a result acquired the conviction that by treating “collective

  representations” as signs, one might hope to go further than the pious show of

  unmasking them and account in detail for the mystification which transforms petit-

  bourgeois culture into a universal nature.’ And this was the conclusion he reached

  from the fifty-four short sketches that followed: ‘the whole of France is steeped

  in this anonymous ideology: our press, our films, our theatre, our pulp literature,

  our rituals, our justice, our diplomacy, our conversations, our remarks about the

  weather, the cooking we dream of, the garments we wear, everything in everyday

  life, is dependent upon the representation which the bourgeoisie has and makes us

  have of the relations between man and the world’. The world of the bourgeoisie had

  been constructed as if it were the world of Eternal Man.354

  Nevertheless, when the student protests of May 1968 rocked France to its very

  foundations, Lévi-Strauss, Jacques Lacan, Roland Barthes, and the other structur-

  alists responded with what J. G. Melchior described as an ‘eloquent’ silence.355 One

  of the many famous student slogans of the day summed up the situation admirably:

  ‘Barthes says that structures do not take to the streets. We say: neither does

  Barthes.’ Sartre, the intellectual hero of the hour, had his revenge.356

  Ironically, the events of May 68 also sounded the death knell of the Sartrean

  model of the committed intellectual.357 Most importantly, the very philosophical

  foundations that had underpinned the Sartrean model of the universal intellectual

  were progressively dismantled. Sartre’s Marxist humanism was jettisoned in a

  philosophical revolution that, via post-structuralism, led ultimately to Jacques

  Derrida and deconstruction. In its assault upon what was taken to be the ‘logocen-

  trism’ at the heart of the Western metaphysical tradition, philosophy simply ceased

  to be engaged in the formulation of normative theories or to concern itself with

  questions of public life. And thus writers like Philippe Sollers, the influential

  353 Lévi-Strauss, The Savage Mind (London: 1966), 269.

  354 Barthes, Mythologies (St Albans, 1973), 140.

  355 From Prague to Paris: A Critique of Structuralist and Post-Structuralist Thought (London, 1986).

  356 These comments on structuralism are expanded upon in my ‘Structuralism’, in Simon

  Glendinning (ed.), The Edinburgh Encyclopedia of Continental Philosophy (Edinburgh, 1999), 505–

  14. See François Dosse, Histoire du structuralisme, 2 vols. (1992).

  357 See François Hourmont, Le Désenchantement des clercs: Figures de l’intellectuel dans l’après-Mai

  68 (Rennes, 1997). More broadly, see Pascal Ory, L’Entre-deux Mai: Histoire culturelle de la France Mai

  68–Mai 1981 (1983); Julian Bourg, From Revolution to Ethics: May 68 and Contemporary French

  Thought (Montreal and Kingston, 2007); and Serge Audier, La Pensée anti-68: Essai sur les origines

  d’une restauration intellectuelle (2008).

  502

  France, Intellectuals, and Engagement

  editor of the literary review Tel Quel,358 could break with Sartre’s definition

  of committed literature and argue that a writer’s commitment was displayed not

  in any message to be conveyed but in the activity of writing itself. Later, Julia

  Kristeva––who herself was to provide a withering description of the self-obsession

  of French intellectuals359––reduced the philosophical project to an attempt to

  destabilize the ‘master discourses’ constituting the existing symbolic order.360

  Jean-François Lyotard, the high priest of postmodernism, could likewise argue

  that ‘The responsibility of “intellectuals” is inseparable from the (shared) idea of

  a universal subject. It alone gave Voltaire, Zola, Péguy, Sartre (to stay within

  the confines of France) the authority that has been accorded to them.’ As, he

  continued, we no longer believed that a universal subject exists, there ought

  therefore no longer to be any intellectuals.361 Gone were the days when the

  intellectual was able to speak out in the name of truth and, in so doing, aspire to

  change the world for the better.
/>   Not only this, but the ideological climate that had sustained the ‘intellectuel

  de gauche’ appeared to evaporate. How this occurred is a complicated story, but

  there can be no doubt that the publication of Alexander Solzhenitsyn’s The

  Gulag Archipelago in French in 1974 produced a major shock to the whole

  edifice, cruelly exposing the past errors and political misjudgements of France’s

  intellectuals before Marxist totalitarianism.362 Faced with such compelling

  evidence of complicity with tyranny and mass murder, the claims of the

  intellectuals to superior knowledge and to a greater lucidity were mercilessly

  stripped away, leaving behind only the image of a figure prone to folly and bouts

  of ideological blindness.363 The picture was of a community of intellectuals in

  disarray, feeling unsure of itself and of how it should act in a world in which it

  no longer enjoyed automatic respect. Power and influence seemed to have

  slipped from its grasp.

  In those circumstances, the immediate years that followed saw the publication

  of a veritable flotilla of books and articles devoted to the examination of the

  intellectual’s supposed demise and its causes. Picking over the carcass of a fallen

  national hero, all evinced a nostalgia for a lost golden age of heroic Dreyfusard

  intellectuals battling against the forces of darkness and all agreed in their condem-

  nation of a corrupted, degraded, and mediocre present. When the content of a

  358 Philippe Forest, Histoire de Tel Quel, 1960–1982 (1996) and Danielle Marx-Scouras, The

  Cultural Politics of Tel Quel: Literature and the Left in the Wake of Engagement (University Park, Pa.,

  1996).

  359 Julia Kristeva, Les Samouraïs (1990).

  360 See ‘A New Type of Intellectual: The Dissident’, in Toril Moi (ed.), The Kristeva Reader

  (Oxford, 1986), 292–300.

  361 ‘Tombeau de l’intellectuel’, Le Monde (8 Oct. 1983). See also Lyotard, Tombeau de l’intellectuel

  et autres papiers (1984).

  362 See Michael Scott Christofferson, French Intellectuals against the Left: The Antitotalitarian

  Moment of the 1970s (New York, 2004), 89–112.

  363 See e.g. Michel-Antoine Burnier, Le Testament de Sartre (1982) and Jeannine Verdès-Leroux, La

  Lune et le caudillo: Le Rêve des intellectuels et le régime cubain (1989).

  France, Intellectuals, and Engagement

  503

  culture had come to be so determined by the market, Régis Debray wrote,

  a philosopher was not judged by his ideas but by the colour of his eyes.364

  From among the wreckage, however, there appeared several alternative models of

  the intellectual. Arguably the most influential of these was that fashioned by Michel

  Foucault. Formulated as early as 1972 and restated on many subsequent occa-

  sions––most notably in an interview given in 1977––Foucault sought to replace the

  ‘universal’ intellectual (with Voltaire and Sartre cast as the prototype) with that of

  the ‘specific’ intellectual.365 As with Julien Benda, there was reference to ‘the great

  treason of the intellectuals’, but here it was taken to be the inculcation of the values

  of ‘bourgeois justice’ among the proletariat. So also there were derogatory com-

  ments directed against those dismissed as ‘les intellectuels professionnels parisiens’.

  But Foucault’s central argument was that the intellectual could no longer make

  claim to be ‘a giver of lessons’ or to act as a ‘moral legislator’. ‘The work of the

  intellectual’, Foucault argued, ‘is not to mould the political will of others.’ Rather,

  the role of the intellectual was ‘to make visible the mechanisms of repressive power

  which operate in a hidden manner’. This was to be done by providing ‘instruments

  of analysis’ drawn from the intellectual’s own work ‘within specific sectors’.

  It was, then, as ‘specialists’ and as ‘experts’ engaging in ‘specific’ and ‘local’

  struggles rather than as ‘universal prophets’ or ‘the bearers of values’ that intellec-

  tuals should operate. Yet in one respect at least the work of the intellectual could

  take on a ‘general significance’ and have implications which were not ‘simply

  professional or sectoral’. Starting from the assumption that truth was not ‘the

  child of protracted solitude’ but the product of ‘multiple forms of constraint’,

  the function of the intellectual, Foucault believed, was to struggle to destroy ‘the

  regime of truth’ integral to the structure and functioning of present society.

  Foucault himself sought to exemplify the role of the ‘specific’ intellectual not

  only through his own writings, most notably Naissance de la clinique and Surveiller

  et punir,366 but also through his own political commitments and interventions.

  In 1971, for example, he established the Groupe d’information sur les prisons to

  secure prison reform.367 A series of similar gestures linking his academic work to

  contemporary social and political issues were made by Foucault in the years before

  his death in 1984. It was this model that was to be taken up and developed by

  thinkers on the left of the political spectrum in the years to come.

  As influential as Foucault’s reformulation of the relationship of the intellectual to

  politics might have been, it provided little attraction for those who had now

  become––or who had always been––deeply sceptical about the supposed virtues

  of the revolutionary project. For this increasingly numerous and vocal group there

  364 See Le Pouvoir intellectuel en France (1979). Debray returned to this theme in i.f. suite et fin

  (2000).

  365 See e.g. ‘Les Intellectuels et le pouvoir’, in Dits et écrits 1954–1988 (1994), ii. 306–15; ‘Entretien

  avec Michel Foucault’, ibid. iii. 140–60; and ‘L’Intellectuel et les pouvoirs’, ibid. iv. 747–52. The

  quotations that follow are drawn from a wide range of sources from within the 4 vols. of Dits et écrits.

  366 Naissance de la clinique (1972); Surveiller et punir (1975).

  367 See Didier Eribon, Michel Foucault (1989), 314–28.

  504

  France, Intellectuals, and Engagement

  was another and wiser source of inspiration: Raymond Aron.368 Unlike the apoliti-

  cal Sartre,369 Aron had not been blind to the dangers of the rise of fascism and in

  the summer of 1940, immediately following the fall of France, he had left for

  London to join the Free French and there became one of the editors of La France

  libre. Following the Liberation, Aron devoted himself to journalism and to the

  pursuit of an immensely distinguished academic career, quickly making known his

  opposition to communism and his support for the United States and the Atlantic

  Alliance. As the Cold War intensified, Aron became a leading member of the CIA-

  financed Congress for Cultural Freedom. If he quickly saw the futility and the

  ‘tragedy’ of the cause of French Algeria, he similarly dismissed the student protests

  of May 68 as a self-indulgent ‘psychodrama’ fuelled by ‘the worst form of utopian-

  ism and revolutionary mythology’.370

  Always an admirer of Montesquieu and Tocqueville (as well as a lifelong

  reader of Marx),371 time and time again Aron returned to the themes of the

  fragility of civilization and the ever-present threat of tyr
anny and totalitarianism.

  If political thought in France, in his view, tended to be either nostalgic or

  utopian, then, by the same token, political action was divorced from reality

  and from economic necessities. The French left in particular, he believed, needed

  to free itself from ‘the siren charms of ideal emancipation’ and of its faith in both

  revolution and the proletariat. Both, Aron argued, were a form of ‘imaginary

  compensation’ for the successive revolutionary failures that had occurred from

  1789 to 1848. The intellectuals of the left, he asserted, were in search of a secular

  religion.

  For his pains, over many years Aron was treated as something of a pariah––better

  to be wrong with Sartre rather than be right with Aron was the celebrated quip––

  and his influence scarcely stretched beyond a small group of loyal friends and

  former students. His intellectual itinerary was however the mark of a philosopher

  and a commentator who refused to turn his back on political realities and who, in

  Aron’s own words, had sought ‘to lead the life of an active witness’. It was this

  willingness to look the realities of politics square in the face that underpinned his

  conception of the intellectual as ‘a committed observer’.

  The origins of this notion can be traced back to Aron’s experiences in Germany

  during the 1930s but it was given much clearer articulation with the publication of

  L’Opium des intellectuels in 1955 and then, much later, in a series of interviews

  368 See Daniel J. Mahoney, The Liberal Political Science of Raymond Aron (Lanham, Md., 1992);

  Nicholas Baverez, Raymond Aron: Un moraliste au temps des idéologies (1993); Brian C. Anderson,

  Raymond Aron: The Recovery of the Political (Lanham, Md., 1997); and ‘The Peripheral Insider:

  Raymond Aron and the Wages of Reason’, in Judt, Burden of Responsibility, 137–82. Above all, see

  Aron’s own autobiographical reflections contained in Mémoires: 50 Ans de réflexion politique (1983). An

  excellent selection of Aron’s work in French is to be found in Penser la liberté, penser la démocratie

  (2005) and in English in The Dawn of Universal History (New York, 2002).

  369 On the relationship between the two men see Sirinelli, Sartre et Aron: Deux intellectuels dans le

 

‹ Prev