Book Read Free

Greek Historiography

Page 20

by Thomas F Scanlon


  (Th. 7.84). It is the counterpoint to the glorious departure of the fleet in Book 6. Nicias had just addressed them in their despair, in a speech that notes good fortune arising from belief in the gods and invokes

  hope in the future, two appeals we last heard from the desperate Melians –

  hope in the gods being otherwise rare in Thucydides’ reality (Th. 7.77; cf. 5.104). Nicias ends with the cliché that, as the men are isolated here,

  “you who are Athenians will raise up again, fallen as it is, the great

  power of the city; men are the city, not walls and ships without men”

  (Th. 7.77). There is only pathos in this reassurance, reminding readers of the mighty power of the past and ignoring the Thucydidean formula

  that power must be derived from walls, ships, and material resources

  (especially at Th. 1.1–19; see Kallet‐Marx 1993 and Kallet 2001). Yet

  the comment seems not to belittle the appeal to pious hope, but rather

  to sympathize with Nicias’ admirable and rare, yet ultimately pernicious, adherence to a traditional code of values in the face of the realities of force. Perhaps the difference here is that Nicias’ self‐representation

  comes essentially to bring a modicum of merciful comfort to his men,

  and it does not cloud crucial decision making. Nicias’ religious scruples, as noted earlier, were only partly to blame for an undue delay in action (Th. 7.50). At the end, after his death, in a quasi‐obituary, Thucydides empathizes with Nicias as a tragic hero of sorts, concluding: “he

  died, although of all the Hellenes, at least in my time, certainly the least deserving to reach this level of misfortune because of a way of life directed entirely toward virtue” (Th. 7.86). The “virtue” ( arete ̄) admired here is civic excellence and altruistic generosity, in other words Nicias had not misused his wealth to bribe his way to safety; and he had told Gylippus, when surrendering, “to do as he pleased with him but

  stop the massacre of the rest of the soldiers” (Th. 7.85). The chapter

  ends with a dismal summary of seven thousand Athenians and allies

  dying while ill‐fed and working in the hot, deep and narrow quarries of Syracuse: “this Hellenic event turned out to be the greatest connected

  with this war and, at least in my opinion, of Hellenic events we have heard of, the most splendid for those who won and the most wretched for those who were ruined”; he names it “total destruction” ( pano ̄ lethria) – a term that, as mentioned above, recalls the destruction of Troy (Th. 7.87).

  It has been pointed out that Book 7, unlike any in Thucydides, is reso-

  nant with both the Iliad and the Odyssey in invoking a homecoming that never happens (Allison 1997a).

  118

  ThucydidEs on ThE Ends of PowEr

  Book 8

  The epic defeat in Sicily seems to signal a tragic closure to the war, but the history of the war is a massive and tantalizing fragment; the account ends abruptly in 411 bc, but what the narrative ending would have been is only hinted at by Thucydides in the obituary for Pericles: “And after they had failed in Sicily … and now had a revolutionary situation in the city, they nevertheless still held out against both their previous enemies … and

  they did not give in until, coming to grief through individual disputes, they brought about their own overthrow” (Th. 2.65). In essence, then,

  this book shifts to a new story of the internal dissolution of the city owing to its inability to unite against external danger.

  The narrative is complex, as were the events, and this requires a virtually new, punchy, episodic style, whose unity is less obvious than in Books 6 and 7, yet whose coherence is present through variations on several

  motifs: the playing of the “Persian card” by both sides, the constant self-centered intrigues of Alcibiades, the resilience of Athens against external foes and yet its endless internal convulsions, and the Peloponnesians’ triumph and demoralization (Dewald 2005: 152–4). The themes continue

  to include human ambition and greed and a lack of civic mindedness,

  difficult now to preserve even as a formal pretense. How these are woven more tightly into the “end game” of the war, the final books Thucydides might have written, we can only guess, but the threads indicate coherence of the new pattern, which continues in Xenophon’s less impressive but

  somewhat similar narrative of Books 1 and 2 of the Hellenica.

  We offer only a brief overview of this book’s discursive story. Initial despair at the loss of Sicily turns into a determination not to give in; the fear of an allied revolt and the concern about Sicilian finances are shown to be overstated (Th. 8.9, 8.26). The Spartans continue to attack Athens from Decelea, and numerous revolts of former allies break out. But one

  major change is the collaboration of Sparta with Persia for the sake of financial favors from the “barbarians,” while the Persians are actually manipulating Greek politics to prevent the emergence of any strong

  Hellenic state that might threaten them, a ruse that continues long past the end of this war. Treaty documents remarkably verify the freedom of

  other Greeks that Sparta was willing to “sell out” for its own ends, despite many earlier claims of “liberating Greece” from Athens (Th. 8.84).

  Alcibiades attempts to work his way back to a reconciliation with the

  Athenians in Book 8 by promising to woo the Persians, through the satrap Tissaphernes, to side with Athens. The duplicitous, self‐serving psychology of both the Athenian and the Persian characters comes to the

  ThucydidEs on ThE Ends of PowEr

  119

  fore here, just as baser human motives had throughout the earlier work

  (8.45–58). Alcibiades’ machinations are scuttled when the oligarchy of

  the Four Hundred comes to power. On Samos there occurred an Athenian

  antidemocratic revolt, then later a counterrevolution to restore democracy on the island, while Athens itself is split between pro‐ and anti‐oligarchs.

  The Peloponnesians win a victory off Euboea, and that valuable island is lost to Athens, but the victors, due to their sluggish character in

  Thucydides’ view, fail to exploit their advantage by taking the Piraeus.

  The Athenians finally restore a mostly democratic regime and manage a

  sea victory against the Peloponnesians at the Hellespont. The abrupt end comes with Tissaphernes trying to reconcile with the Peloponnesians in

  411 bc, for his own self‐serving reasons.

  Yet behind the external back‐and‐forth struggles there emerges a cru-

  cial, newly invigorated political dimension, namely an internal strife to stabilize the government of Athens, culminating in the governments of

  the Four Hundred and the oligarchic Five Thousand (Connor 1984:

  214–15). The loss of political coherence in the city is its own greatest enemy. An Athenian democratic faction is empowered on Samos (Th.

  8.76), an oligarchic one in Athens is further split into moderate and

  extreme oligarchs (Th. 8.89).

  Thucydides’ skepticism of both oligarchy and democracy controlling

  Athens’ allies is reflected in a passage describing the revolt of Thasos: For the Athenian establishers of oligarchy, then, what happened was the opposite of what they wanted regarding Thasos, I suppose, among many of their other subjects as well. For after the cities had been given “moderate government” and freedom of action, they went on to outright independence, attaching no value to the sham of “law and order” under the Athenians.

  (Th. 8.64)

  The historian uncovers the hypocrisy of the oligarchs and how it affects external affairs, as it will continue to do for the rest of the war. The contrasting passion for and fear of the Athenian oligarchs recalls the force of human passions elsewhere in the work (Th. 8.66; cf. the fear after the

  incidents of the Eleusinian Mysteries and herms before the Si
cilian

  expedition, Th. 6.24; Connor 1984: 223). No single Athenian leader

  dominates in this section, but men like the famously wily Phrynicus and the skilled orator Antiphon, part of the Four Hundred conspiracy, show

  great talent, albeit wasted on self‐seeking manipulation of the government and people (Th. 8.68). The historian’s striking praise of the government of the Five Thousand (who succeeded the Four Hundred) has caused

  120

  ThucydidEs on ThE Ends of PowEr

  scholars to wonder how to square this with his praise of democracy

  through Pericles in the funeral oration:

  And not least – for the first time in my experience – the Athenians appear to have governed themselves well. For a balanced mixture of the few and the many came about, and this above all raised the city out of the difficulties that beset it. (Th. 8.97, Connor 1984: 228)

  Had Thucydides changed his view of government forms? More likely, the

  phrase “governed themselves well” applies to their conduct rather than to the form of government, and “balanced mixture” alludes to an appreciation of the moderation of the oligarchic and democratic forms to achieve stability in the city.

  Conclusions

  Thucydides was moved, intellectually and emotionally, to write about a

  war through which he lived; he was stirred by a deeply personal experience, distinct from Herodotus’, as is evident throughout the Thucydidean narrative. While Thucydides, too, owes much to Homer and earlier poetic and ethical thought, his innovative perspective resonates with the style and thought of the later fifth century, with the expression of Presocratic philosophers and sophists, with Euripidean searching, and with Hippocratic concerns with the emerging life sciences. Thucydides does not endorse

  any particular intellectual movement or political stance, but his work

  reflects the highly turbulent atmosphere of the times and it presents the war to others as a case study in human interactions and reactions during the great challenge to Athenian rule.

  His description of the dynamics of history in new terms – in speeches

  of others, in his own digressions, and in his insights into the actions of the participants on all sides – is the essence of his contribution to the genre.

  The greatest legacies of Thucydides are arguably his bold invention of a new prose language, his sharp focus on the human psyche, and his pressing determination to bring to light the truth behind the hypocrisy or the muddled reasoning of words and deeds that eroded Greek states from

  within. Belief in divine manipulation or fate is replaced by a clear concept of human nature as the grand motivator in history. He is also determined to trace the failures and successes of states and persons in power, which he does with the insider’s sense of intense interest and insight. Xenophon and Polybius, among his heirs, also evidence an insider’s perspective and

  ThucydidEs on ThE Ends of PowEr

  121

  insight at times, but they lack his intensity and focus. Eternal glory is implied in Thucydides’ admiration of the power of Pericles’ Athens, but a more ordinary and lasting shame is described in the self‐serving impulses of those in civil strife at Corcyra and in Athens after the Sicilian disaster.

  Bibliography

  Allison, J. W. 1983. “Pericles’ Policy and the Plague.” Historia 32: 14–23.

  Allison, J. W. 1997a. “Homeric Allusions at the Close of Thucydides’

  Sicilian Narrative.” American Journal of Philology 118(4): 499–516.

  Allison, J. W. 1997b. Word and Concept in Thucydides. Atlanta, GA: Scholars Press.

  Andrewes, A. 1981. “Indications of Incompleteness.” In A. W. Gomme,

  A. Andrewes, and K. J. Dover, eds., A Historical Commentary on

  Thucydides, vol. 5, 361–83. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

  Andrews, J. A. 2000. “Cleon’s Hidden Appeals.” The Classical Quarterly 50: 45–62.

  Axarlis, N. 1998. “Plague Victims Found: Mass Burial in

  Athens.” Archaeology. At http://www.archaeology.org/online/news/

  kerameikos.html (accessed January 25, 2013).

  Barnes, J. 1979. The Presocratic Philosophers. Vol. 2: Empedocles to Democritus. London: Routledge.

  Bosworth, B. 1993. “The Humanitarian Aspect of the Melian Dialogue.”

  Journal of Hellenic Studies 113: 30–44. (Reprinted in Rusten, ed., 2009: 312–37.)

  Chambers, M. 1957. “Thucydides and Pericles.” Harvard Studies in

  Classical Philology 62: 79–92.

  Connor, W. R. 1984. Thucydides. Princeton: Princeton University Press.

  Cook, M. 2001. “Something Incurable: Hope and Tragedy in

  Thucydides.” Abstracts of the 132nd Annual Meeting of the American

  Philological Association, 9.

  Cornford, F. M. 1907. Thucydides Mythhistoricus. London: Arnold.

  Crane, G. 1998. Thucydides and the Ancient Simplicity: The Limits of Political Realism. Berkeley: University of California Press.

  Debnar, P. A. 2000. “Diodotus’ Paradox and the Mytilene Debate

  (Thucydides 3. 37–49).” Rheinishes Museum 143(2): 161–78.

  Desmond, W. 2006. “Lessons of Fear: A Reading of Thucydides.”

  Classical Philology 101: 359–79.

  Dewald, C. 2005. Thucydides’ War Narrative: A Structural Study.

  Berkeley: University of California Press.

  122

  ThucydidEs on ThE Ends of PowEr

  Döring, K. 2011. “The Students of Socrates.” In D. R. Morrison, ed.,

  The Cambridge Companion to Socrates, 24–47. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

  Dover, K. J. 1981. “Strata of Composition.” In Gomme, Andrewes, and

  Dover, 384–444.

  Edmunds, L. 1975a. Chance and Intelligence in Thucydides. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.

  Edmunds, L. 1975b. “Thucydides’ Ethics as Reflected in the Description

  of Stasis.” Harvard Studies in Classical Philology 79: 72–92.

  Finley, J. H. 1967. Three Essays on Thucydides. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.

  Gagarin, M. and P. Woodruff, eds. and trans. 1995. Early Greek Political Thought, from Homer to the Sophists. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

  Gervasi, R. A. 1984 [1981]. “The Concept of elpis in Thucydides.” PhD

  thesis, Ohio State University (University Microfilms, Ann Arbor,

  Michigan).

  Gomme, A. W. 1945. An Historical Commentary on Thucydides, vol. 1.

  Oxford: Clarendon.

  Gomme, A. W., A. Andrewes, and K. J. Dover. 1970. An Historical

  Commentary on Thucydides. Vol. 4: Books V (25)–VII. Oxford: Clarendon.

  Gomme, A. W., A. Andrewes, and K. J. Dover. 1981. An Historical

  Commentary on Thucydides. Vol. 5: Book VIII. Oxford: Clarendon.

  Grene, D. 1965. Greek Political Theory: The Image of Man in Plato and Thucydides. Chicago, IL: University of Chicago Press.

  Grethlein, J. 2004. “Logographos and Thuc. 1.21.1.” Prometheus 30: 209–16.

  Guthrie, W. K. C. 1971. The Sophists. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

  Hammond, N. G. L. 1952. “The Arrangement of the Thought in the

  Proem and in other Parts of Thucydides 1.” Classical Quarterly 2: 127–41.

  Hornblower, S. 1987. Thucydides. London: Duckworth.

  Hornblower, S. 1991. A Commentary on Thucydides. Vol. 1: Books I–III.

  Oxford: Clarendon.

  Hornblower, S. 1996. A Commentary on Thucydides. Vol. 2: Books IV–V.24. Oxford: Clarendon.

  Hornblower, S. 2008. A Commentary on Thucydides, vol. 3. Oxford: Clarendon.

  Huart, P. 1968. Le Vocabulaire de l’analyse psychologique dans l’oeuvre de Thucydide. Paris: Klincksieck.

  ThucydidEs on ThE Ends of PowEr

  123

  Hunter, V. 1973. Thucydides the Artful Reporter. Toronto: University of Toront
o Press.

  Hussey, E. 1985. “Thucydidean History and Democritean Theory.” In

  E. Hussey, F. D. Harvey, and P. A. Cartledge, eds., Crux: Essays in Greek History Presented to G. E. M. de Ste. Croix on his 75th Birthday, 118–38. London: Duckworth.

  Immerwahr, H. R. 1973. “Pathology of Power and the Speeches in

  Thucydides.” In Stadter, ed., 16–31.

  Irwin, T. 1989. Classical Thought. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

  Kallet, L. 2001. Money and the Corrosion of Power in Thucydides: The Sicilian Expedition and Its Aftermath. Berkeley: University of California Press.

  Kallet‐Marx, L. 1993. Money, Expense, and Naval Power in Thucydides’

  History 1–5.24. Berkeley: University of California Press.

  Kerferd, G. B. 1981. The Sophistic Movement. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

  Lang, M. 1984. Herodotean Narrative and Discourse. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.

  Lattimore, S., trans. 1998. Thucydides: The Peloponnesian War. Indianapolis, IN: Hackett.

  Loraux, N. 2009. “Thucydides and Sedition among Words.” In Rusten,

  ed., 261–92.

  Luginbill, R. D. 1999. Thucydides on War and National Character.

  Boulder, CO: Westview Press.

  Macleod, C. 1974. “Form and Meaning in the Melian Dialogue.”

  Historia 23 (1974): 385–400. (Reprinted in C. Macleod, 1983,

  Collected Essays, 52–67. Oxford: Oxford University Press.)

  Macleod, C. 1982. “Thucydides and Tragedy.” Classicum 8: 1–10.

  Manuwald, B. 1979. “Der Trug des Diodotus (zu Thukydides 3.42–

  48).” Hermes 107: 407–22.

  Manuwald, B. 2009. “Diodotus’ Deceit (on Thucydides 3.42–48),”

  trans. J. Rusten. In Rusten, ed., 241–60 [originally in German as

  Manuwald 1979].

  Marinatos, N. 1981. Thucydides and Religion. Königstein: Hain.

  McGregor, M. F. 1956. “The Politics of the Historian Thucydides.”

  Phoenix 10: 93–102.

  Meyer, E. A. 2008. “Thucydides on Harmodius and Aristogeiton,

  Tyranny, and History.” Classical Quarterly 58(1): 13–34.

 

‹ Prev