Young William James Thinking

Home > Other > Young William James Thinking > Page 40
Young William James Thinking Page 40

by Paul J Croce


  to natu ral se lection prompted James’s sharp response: “[I]t really astounds

  one to see such a man give such a burlesque misrepre sen ta tion of Darwin’s

  book.” The young scientist clearly relished the chance to exercise his scien-

  tific skills and take a stand for Darwinism. Also, it was spring, and he was

  feeling the winter “yield to a time when nature seems to cooperate with

  life”; this contributed to thinking in more optimistic terms again. By early

  May 1870, he declared to his brother Henry, “I have I think at last begun to

  rise out of the slough of the past 3 months, and I mean to try not to fall back

  again.” As James strug gled through improvements and setbacks, and through

  the temporary guidance, respectively, of strug gle and ac cep tance, he con-

  ceived of a plan for action that would provide more stability. He solemnly

  proposed: “[S]trive thou after order.” And he added with grim determina-

  tion, “I at last see a certain order in the state I’m in,” indicating how far he

  had already progressed toward achieving that goal in coping with his im-

  mediate trou bles. 58 With the clarity of his most recent vow, James would

  seek order as a platform for balancing his impulses and for motivating

  action.

  The Will to Order

  James’s glimmer of order would come from a surprising quarter, not from faith

  in fixity but instead from finding force in his will, an order not from founda-

  tional security but from orienting coherence. He took his first step toward

  this goal when he declared in an April 1870 diary entry, “I think that yester-

  day was a crisis in my life.” With this crisis, he was not reporting trou bles

  but excitement from reading the French phi los o pher Charles Renouvier.

  Two years earlier, he had already read his work, noticing it was “so diff er ent

  228  Young William James Thinking

  fr[om]. the namby pamby diffuseness of most,” but the Frenchman’s words

  about the will in par tic u lar now leaped out at him with urgency. He found

  “no reason why [Renouvier’s] definition of free will— ‘the sustaining of a

  thought because I choose to when I might have other thoughts’— need be

  the definition of an illusion.” Still, he could muster only a tentative prom-

  ise to himself: “At any rate, I will assume for the pres ent— until next year—

  that [a truly free will] is no illusion.” It was another vow, mere words

  about the will, but his terse aphorism provided a clear blueprint: “My first

  act of free will shall be to believe in free will.” 59 This outlook suggested a platform for order not from prior security, but in providing direction into

  the future.

  For all the bravery of James’s tone about his “first act of free will,” his

  personal promise was not a first, and it was not an action, but it reinforced

  his hope. He did not even fully agree with Renouvier, and even these inspi-

  rational words on free will would not end his trou bles. He had made efforts

  in this direction before: he had read and discussed philosophies of the will,

  urged friends toward assertions of will, and tried it himself, but it was dif-

  ficult to sustain. And he was not, in fact, engaging in action, but dwelling in

  theory, even as his words served as a promise of action for the next few

  months. Still, he had found a guideline for his impulses, which had previ-

  ously been tamped down by his trou bles and by his needling sense that per-

  haps the personal will was just an illusion compared with the forces of fate

  and materialist factors ready to explain it away. While his reading of Renou-

  vier was inspiring, James reported directly to the French phi los o pher that

  “on other points of your philosophy I still have doubts.” In par tic u lar, James

  could not adopt the more thoroughly secular outlook of the French phi los o-

  pher; yet, despite Renouvier’s impatience with religion, he had directly bor-

  rowed his outlook on freedom from the man he called “my master,” the more

  obscure French Catholic mystic Jules Lequyer. While Lequyer endorsed free

  will because of his belief that “God . . . created me creator of myself,” Renou-

  vier took the idea in a more functional psychological direction as a way to

  demote claims to certainty: “[T] here is no certitude; all there is is men who

  are certain.” James accepted this voluntarism as a philosophical expression

  of his impulse to think of each claim for “certitude” in science or religion as

  “nothing but belief, . . . a moral attitude,” even as the pluralism of perspec-

  tives prevents claims to ultimate certainty. And this would spur James’s con-

  struction of his own theory with each “certainty” serving as a “Sentiment of

  Rationality” (1879) shaping philosophical commitment.60

  Crises and Construction  229

  With these goals for science and religion in mind, James would spend

  the next few years trying to fire up his will; his contrasts with most scien-

  tific thinking and his own uncertainties filled his introspective scrutinizing

  with so many shifts of personal reactions that his path would look like a

  parody of zigzagging indecision. But he was actually applying a personal

  version of his understanding of science: prior suggestive experiences

  served as his research, the Renouvier- inspired assertion was his hypoth-

  esis, and his motivational efforts were experiments on himself, now not

  with acid phosphate or chloral, but with philosophy. Diary entries with

  hope for improvement— but also with examples of discouragement— were

  his introspective laboratory reports on his most impor tant experiment: his

  explorations of the possibilities for asserting free will to launch his mature

  career. While Renouvier and, less directly, Lequyer were the immediate

  contexts for his April 1870 resolution, his more substantial guides were in

  his ongoing approaches to science and religion, with his hopes to under-

  stand the role of freedom in each field of his early education. 61

  Before Renouvier’s confirmation of his willful initiative, James had never

  been able to sustain his efforts through water- cure treatments or the lessons

  of the Stoics, or, most recently, when facing the death of Minny Temple. Re-

  nouvier’s ideas added the sharpness of philosophical expression. His own

  philosophizing about ac cep tance and strug gle had cleared the ground by

  putting identifying labels on his contrasting outlooks during his trou bles;

  his Renouvier- inspired theory provided an explanation, and with that a

  game plan that focused the lessons of his prior efforts in support of his per-

  sis tent hopes. The diary maxim was a confidence- building declaration for

  justifying to himself that any one moment was a fresh beginning, built upon

  the orderly platform of the will’s inner citadel and the sturdiness of a coherent

  and persuasive theory; that guiding maxim could not eliminate the trou bles

  that surrounded him, but it did offer a way to manage his discouragements—

  and more: it suggested that with a fired-up will those trou bles would be-

  come incidental to larger purposes, and even sources of insight. Still, theory

  could be very insubstantial: its explanatio
ns were no substitute for experi-

  ence. The April 1870 diary entry was exciting, but he wanted more than ab-

  stractions. He even counseled himself to work “not in maxims”— the very

  gist of his Renouvier- inspired insight. So his conceptual experimentation

  would continue as he also vowed to “see to the sequel” of such theoretical

  promise in actual action. He specified the combination of theory and action

  that would give him direction— “not in Anschauungen [abstract intuitions

  230  Young William James Thinking

  or contemplative views], but in accumulated acts of thought lies salvation. ”62

  With thought as with action, this was no idle inquiry or academic exercise;

  this was philosophy for personal direction. His future was on the line.

  James’s new philosophical position, culminating in riveting attention to

  Renouvier’s words, addressed his years- long ambivalence about philoso-

  phizing. For all his attraction to deep reflection through his reading, writ-

  ing, and discussion with his friends, he was concerned about its tendency to

  be another force that undercut the power of the will. He had been burned

  by the very speculations that attracted him because their conflicting ab-

  stractions blurred his choices. Renouvier’s idea appealed precisely because

  it was a philosophy about willful action rather than a philosophy that would

  only encourage further disconcerting reflection. James’s purpose in turn-

  ing to philosophy, as with the Stoics, was for guidance through life. Now, to

  help his new resolution, he promised himself to “abstain from the mere

  speculation and contemplative Grüblei [deep, obsessive searching] in which

  my nature takes most delight.” Instead, he would “voluntarily cultivate the

  feeling of moral freedom, by reading books favorable to it, as well as by act-

  ing.”63 He had tried to cultivate his free initiative before, but he had so often

  fallen short. Now he was ready to be more systematic; Renouvier supported

  his will to order.

  After a few months of taking his own advice, James hoped “my callow

  skin being somewhat fledged, I may perhaps return to metaphysical study

  and skepticism without danger to my powers of action.” Until then, he

  vowed, “care little for speculation; much for the form of my action.” Far

  from being an invitation to the nondiscipline of believing anything he

  willed, Renouvier’s philosophical sanction was a basis for gaining “habits of

  order” and discipline, first steps— but only first steps— for dealing with his

  nagging prob lems. He knew how difficult it was to sustain his free will, so

  he was prepared to “accumulate grain on grain of willful choice.” In his

  physiological and psychological study, James had read Alexander Bain’s

  theories of neurophysiology and habit formation; in the Metaphysical Club,

  he had heard Nicholas St. John Green and Charles Peirce discuss the sig-

  nificance of habits and belief issuing in action; and he had even written

  about the importance of habits as early as 1859 when he recorded in his

  notebook that the development of intellect depends “more upon the early

  habit of cultivating the attention than upon the disparity between the pow-

  ers of individuals.” But merely reading and talking had not trained his hab-

  its for development of a more forceful will; so, beyond his weaker previous

  Crises and Construction  231

  personal efforts, his new hypothesis “furnished the exceptionally passion-

  ate initiative which Bain posits as needful for the acquisition of habits. ”64

  Still, even such initiative for action was not enough.

  Recalling his years of strug gle, when his efforts to gain health, female

  companionship, vocational and philosophical direction, and even freedom

  from worry about insanity led to deep frustration, James bleakly remem-

  bered that his only willful, “daring, . . . free initiative . . . [was] suicide”:

  willful action full of passion, but end of experiment. However, the

  Renouvier- inspired insight would allow him to “go a step further with my

  will,” because he would then “not only act with it,” which he had been able

  to do with repeated but only temporary successes, “but believe as well,”

  with the clarification of purpose and direction that philosophy could pro-

  vide. Theory and action had each brought him prob lems, but each had its

  merits as well. Rather than choose between them, he integrated them, to

  find the benefits of each: his theory asserting belief in free will would serve

  as an action, a bold and emboldening “act . . . of thought”; the philosophiz-

  ing in this experiment would avoid his trou bles from too much reflection by

  providing direction- giving guidance to his actions. Then his theory of “be-

  lief in free will” would serve as a platform, not for certainty, but for support

  of “my . . . creative power” to work toward philanthropic goals. No matter

  how many forces squash or overwhelm the will, he could still posit “the

  self[-]governing re sis tance of the ego to the world.” All his trou bles had

  pushed him down to this immovable rock. In the spirit of the Stoics, follow-

  ing his reading of Bain, and with the support of his discussion partners and

  Renouvier’s ideas, this would serve as a new starting point. René Descartes

  launched his philosophy from doubting every thing until he realized he was

  a thinking thing; James was shaping his philosophy from his awareness

  that he was a willing creature. With his capacity for willful strug gle sup-

  ported and ignited, he could plausibly maintain that “life . . .”— his own and

  his view of life in general— “ shall [be built in] doing and suffering and cre-

  ating.”65 In his exuberance, he named this path “salvation” because these

  constructive actions offered a personal and philosophical equivalent of a

  religious conversion— and an experimental plan.

  These personal and philosophical resolutions forecast James’s later will

  to believe and pragmatism, but at the time, they were the fruit of years of

  inner debate and uncertainty. They echoed in more full form James’s

  pledge from an early notebook that “nothing can be done without work”

  and his repeated vows to find ways to contribute some good to the world.

  232  Young William James Thinking

  His experimentation would continue, however, since his trou bles were still

  not solved at the time of his brave insight. He even made his April 1870 vow

  with a provisional nine- month promise to himself, expecting some changes

  only “ after the first of January. ”66 His declarations, however, were an impor-

  tant step in the development of a philosophy of life in de pen dent of abso-

  lutes, whether from materialist science, the idealism of his father, or any

  other secular or spiritual commitment; and these words show his resolve to

  build up the power of the will to affect experiences in this world— without

  expecting full control of them. Final solutions repeatedly discouraged him

  for their lack of flexibility and their inauthenticity to experience, but like

  his search for absolutes within finite natu ral spheres as he had detected

  among
the ancients, he still sought the idealism associated with absolutes

  in his philanthropic hopes for improvement. Now he found ways to take

  steps toward those hopes, from integration of philosophy, belief, and action;

  no one of these would be sufficient, but with his will to order he would work

  on bringing them together.

  For the next few weeks in the spring of 1870, sustained by his new resolu-

  tion and aided by the warming weather, James felt fairly strong. He was

  determined to implement his will. In early May, he was bravely ready to

  pledge his “brute power of re sis tance” to any prob lem. He chided the ac-

  cepting posture of idealistic philosophies, so ready “to blink the evil out of

  sight, and gloss it over.” There was no denying the severity of human prob-

  lems and traumas, including his own: they are “as real as the good,” as the

  ancients also emphasized. But he declared, at least from the comfort of his

  writing desk, that “evil . . . must be accepted and hated and resisted while

  there’s breath in our bodies.” By July, however, he sadly reported that “my . . .

  symptoms of improvement 2 months ago have not amounted to anything.”

  He apologized to his brother Bob in July 1870 for not writing earlier, but he

  “hardly felt well enough” to do even that. He was already looking back on

  his April declaration for the power of the free will with something like

  nostalgia. It reminded him of “ those glorious flushes of excitement during

  which one says— ‘let the truth, the internal good unrelated to consequences—

  prevail for one hour,’ ” so, no matter what would happen next, “I shall have

  lived!” Despite his resolution to continue without expecting results, his

  per sis tent trou bles tried his patience; but still he maintained his diary plan.

  Within a few months, he had grown weaker, and he even had some regret

  about his bold resolution. It was a sound plan for action, but it was still an

  Crises and Construction  233

  abstraction, and as he had feared for years, “all thought, all emotion which

  does not tend to action, is morbid & should be suppressed. ”67 His experi-

  ment, so helpful for confirming direction and providing a framework, would

  not be sufficient until he could sustain his action.

  While James experimented with his philosophy of action, his vacillation

 

‹ Prev