Book Read Free

Young William James Thinking

Page 46

by Paul J Croce


  with a lecture about ideas and the actual physical experiences of those sitting

  to listen. Surmising the thoughts in his audience, he used a meta phor drawn

  from news of the time about surging immigration into industrial Amer i ca;

  he portrayed an “Italian woman” who had arrived not to stay but who “had

  come to Amer i ca in order to raise funds to carry her back to Italy again.” In the

  same way, he proposed that his listeners were likely most at home not in his

  words but in their own thoughts. So he imagined applause at the end from

  “joy . . . when it is all over,” when they are “at last free to escape from the sound

  of the lecturer’s voice,” free to carry its intellectual sparks back to their own

  experiences. This disarmingly direct and tangible example displays an embodied

  version of his commitment to “ human trust in a future yet unrealized,” even as

  he recognized potential enrichment from new and even contrasting ideas. 2 For young James, however, this reliance on immediate experience and trust in the

  future, would be a long time in coming.

  Q

  Throughout a young adulthood of personal trou bles and wide- ranging

  education, William James was unmoored by the very abundance of his

  choices. Caught in a swirl of difficulties, diff er ent days—or even hours—

  brought whole new expectations about his prospects. He took a long time to

  grow up, even as that moratorium period until he was in his early thirties

  would add to the depths of his development. During his years of indecision

  and depression, he never stopped learning, and he constantly reflected on

  events of his life and even small shifts in his philosophical outlook, his vo-

  cational direction, and his health and social relations. For all the prob lems

  he experienced, he generally addressed them “by [him]self with pen in

  hand.” Writing was a way to unload the burden of the trou bles themselves,

  to capture thoughts from introspection and from discussion with friends,

  and to reflect on prob lems for pos si ble solutions. James’s philosophical

  commitment to the significance of experience started with his own. As his

  colleague George Herbert Palmer noted about his way of philosophizing,

  “using his own eyes and ears,” he offered “pungent statement[s] of just how

  things looked to him.” He looked at experience without blinking, even when

  those sources were none too august or professionally sanctioned, since after

  all, James observed, “augustness” is hardly a “decisive mark . . . of truth. ”3

  The very range of his youthful experiences, and the depth of their chal-

  lenges, would become creative resources for his mature work.

  264  Young William James Thinking

  Between Science and Philosophy

  In the 1870s James began his professional career by making use of both sci-

  ence and philosophy. The very pro cess of working in scientific fields while

  cultivating his own philosophy encouraged his challenges to scientific as-

  sumptions; however, he developed his philosophical theories not in defi-

  ance of science, but by working through science, with scientific work and its

  fidelity to natu ral facts serving first as ways to manage his wariness about

  philosophical speculation and then as a method for further philosophical

  inquiry. He would find meaning and animating power within the facts of

  natu ral experience using materialist science as a first step, not the last word.

  He worked in science until his reflections on its implications generated his

  philosophizing; and he transformed his issues of personal concern into pro-

  fessional discourse as he gained academic stature and a public hearing. The

  combination of training in his scientific disciplines, religious interest, and

  cultivation of humanistic artistry from his outside reading and reflections

  provided him with approaches for expressing his philosophical views in

  ways that would be new and inviting rather than just eccentric, a leap his

  father never could make. This is the birth of the best- known James. Because

  he built his theories from an eclectic combination of fields, his ideas would

  invite charges of inconsistency or indecisiveness; witness the paradoxical

  combination of words in the title of one of his philosophical essays “The

  Sentiment of Rationality” and the range within that text which begins with

  “recent psychological speculation” and ends with “mysteriousness . . . [in]

  the nature of things. ”4 But to the author, both paths were plausible applica-

  tions of fidelity to natu ral experience.

  This late-1870s vocational birth was long in gestation through his scien-

  tific education and avocational learning, with private and public writing

  galvanizing the insights of his youth and serving as dress rehearsals for

  later work. His first extensive essays were written in such rapid succession

  starting in 1878 that they were surely built upon the immediately preceding

  work and speculations, even as they laid the groundwork for his more elab-

  orated theories. At the time, however, his main task was to bridge his cur-

  rent scientific training with his philosophical speculation. Thinking of his

  essays as chapters in a planned “psychological work on the motives which

  lead men to philosophize,” he made use of his youthful drive to find imma-

  terial and humanistic ele ments, along with the physical facts, within the

  nature he was studying. He contrasted his views with “[Herbert] Spencer’s

  An Earnestly Inquiring State  265

  Definition of Mind” (January 1878), detecting adaptive purpose in the

  spontaneity of human consciousness; he supported “The Subjective Method”

  (January 1878) within scientific psy chol ogy, for its ability to spur energy,

  effort, and action; he assessed the ability to free from routine as the value

  added from human mental evolution, compared to nonhuman minds, his

  comparison of “Brute and Human Intellect” (July 1878); he responded to

  the con temporary question, “Are We Automata?” (January 1879), with a sharp

  critique of this reduction of mind exclusively to its physical factors; and he

  explored “The Sentiment of Rationality” (July 1879) on the role of physio-

  logical frameworks and psychological temperaments in shaping philosophical

  commitments. These works catapulted James to fame. For example, Ernst

  Mach, the influential Austrian phi los o pher and physicist, in presenting his

  “idea of concepts as labor- saving devices” in the 1880s praised the “refreshing

  vigor” of “The Sentiment of Rationality” and found “points of agreement,”

  especially because they both perceived “the constantly augmenting sweep

  of experience,” with enormity of facts “simplified by the action of con-

  cepts.” 5 In less than two years, James both applied his scientific education

  and critiqued it, enabling his ideas to circulate with cutting- edge science,

  even as he also found a place for the role of life and mind, with their myster-

  ies and direction- giving power.

  While James never wrote his planned psy chol ogy for philosophizing,

  these essays would become first drafts of his Princi ples of Psy chol ogy, which

  would brew for more than a
nother de cade before publication, almost as

  long as his own prior varied education. James’s major psy chol ogy book

  served as a summary of the state of the field in 1890; and yet, despite his

  thorough coverage of empirical facts of mind and be hav ior, and his vow to

  adhere to a “strictly positivistic point of view,” he kept turning to philo-

  sophical questions. At this point, he expressed the unorthodox dimensions

  of his leanings more through critique of scientific certainty than with the

  pre sen ta tion of alternatives—in effect, he applied the skeptical scrutiny of

  positivism to science itself. James’s ready mingling of psy chol ogy and phi-

  losophy has added to his reputation for indecision, or for professional cau-

  tion in his willingness to adopt what Gerald Myers has called a “provisional

  dualism” in his psy chol ogy text before the explicit nondualism of his later

  writings. However, viewing the arc of his career beginning with his young

  adulthood shows that James was consistently nondualist throughout; in

  this commitment, however, he did not oppose dualism but encompassed it

  as an intellectual tool useful for some purposes. In par tic u lar, he readily

  266  Young William James Thinking

  worked within the reigning dualist methodology that dominated scientific

  psy chol ogy, limiting his philosophical thought to commentary on the limits

  of this method and on issues left unresolved. These philosophical com-

  ments can look like reflective intrusions on his science in the immediate

  work of midcareer, when he was establishing his reputation in psy chol ogy. 6

  However, to James they were naturally interwoven with that work, and

  they show that, as with his view of materialism, he would regard dualism as

  a useful way to illuminate some portions of natu ral experience.

  James continued to apply his psy chol ogy to his philosophizing, and he

  continued his youthful mingling of material and immaterial realms of life, in

  addressing frequently contested dualities of body and mind and related con-

  trasts in other fields. In “The Will to Believe” (1897), immediately next to his

  insistence on the fixity of fact for the empirically explicit, he argued for the

  justification of belief when faced with genuinely ambiguous options, espe-

  cially in religion— action steps without tangible guarantee, just as he had al-

  ready resolved at the end of his youth. He brought together his re spect for

  mainstream science and for the Va ri e ties of Religious Experience (1902) in his

  “science of religions” framework, which allowed him to see each spiritual ex-

  perience and each religious tradition as a varied expression of the subliminal

  realm within the depths of human psy chol ogy— the objectivity embedded

  within the subjectivity as he had proposed to Chauncey Wright in the early

  1870s. In his essays in “radical empiricism” (from 1904), he placed the conven-

  tionally dualist “subject or . . . knower” and “the object known” as features of

  the same “pure experience,” simultaneous and in intimate relation; they

  “coexist, . . . with no separateness needing to be overcome”— a refinement of

  what he had observed in 1862 about the discrimination of separate things

  when “nature only offers Thing,” and akin to what he had witnessed among

  sectarian medical prac ti tion ers and the ancients. In Pragmatism (1907), he

  acknowledged “the good things on both sides of the line” of philosophical

  debates between empiricists and rationalists by incorporating both “tough-

  minded” facts and theories about “tender- minded” experiences, while avoid-

  ing the abstractions on either side— similar to the impatience with absolutist

  claims he was already registering during his education in science and reli-

  gion. He explained the continuous and contingent qualities of experience

  with its parts in weblike relation in A Pluralistic Universe (1909), in contrast

  with the familiar human simplifications that emerge when mental repre sen-

  ta tions carve artificially definite answers out of portions of experience; in the

  same way, since his youth, he had been noticing the teeming and chance- filled

  An Earnestly Inquiring State  267

  William James’s Ledge in the Adirondacks.

  Photo by Paul Croce, Shanty, Keene Valley, NY, June 2011.

  In 1875, James and three Harvard scientist friends, James Jackson Putnam,

  Charles Pickering Putnam, and Henry Pickering Bowditch, bought what they called

  their “Shanty,” deep in New York’s Adirondacks, where they would spend many

  summers. For James, the shanty offered a getaway from detailed work and a setting

  for thinking more deeply about the work of his deepest commitments. One favorite

  spot where he went to read and write became known as “Wm. James Ledge,” and the

  simple wooden sign still directs hikers to the spot.

  dimensions of experience in the making. And he investigated depth psy chol-

  ogy and psychical phenomena throughout his career, maintaining a spirit of

  scientific inquiry by following the leads presented by human experience; he

  scrutinized these extranatural claims, just as he had been ready since his

  youth to hear out but evaluate the claims of alternative medicine. Throughout

  this work, he maintained an active commitment, as he was already insisting

  in 1875, both to scientific inquiry and to novelties of all kinds, including

  “ great . . . religious promise.” 7

  These mature works emerged with variations on James’s youthful themes,

  as he comprehended the objective, physiological, and empirical (with all

  268  Young William James Thinking

  their complexities), along with the subjective, volitional, and mysterious

  (as humans have access), all as parts of abundant experience. The whole

  array was an opportunity to consider the natu ral settings, the intimate re-

  lations, the similar questions, and even the common under lying sources of

  these material and immaterial ingredients of life, even as each conven-

  tional distinction would operate in diff er ent fields, and circulate in people

  with diff er ent social habits, diverging temperaments, and contrasting con-

  victions. Later in life, he chose a meta phor from a literal natu ral setting to

  summarize his whole life work: we live in a “trackless forest of human

  experience,” with science, religion, philosophy, and more fruits of human

  creativity providing “spots, or blazes” to trails through the complexity and

  mystery. Each approach is potentially valuable, but these trails “leave . . .

  unexpressed almost every thing” in the whole forest. The mysterious whole

  maintained its allure as the “secret spring of all my poor life’s philosophic

  effort,” as he remained per sis tently interested in the interrelations of the

  trails. He spoke calmly about the trackless forest toward the end of his

  career, but early on he was still considering many trails and burdened by

  doubt: in his young adulthood, he felt ambitions to be a scientist, so he could

  “go out . . . into the dear old woods and fields” to make discoveries; but in

  the thick of his scientific education, he developed reflective worries about

  “the woods in which
the young mind grows up.” 8 He resolved his dilemmas

  not by getting out of the woods but by steering through them; and that

  would involve frank recognition of the whole forest, the whole intercon-

  nected range of experiences, even as he contributed to several disciplinary

  trails. His general posture on mystery, however, serves as his most pro-

  found contribution.

  Recognition of mystery offers a potent way to reconcile conflicting views,

  starting with science and religion, and not just based on his deflation of

  absolutist claims from all sides. In addition, acknowledging the mysterious

  grandeur of the whole cosmos can appeal to religious and idealist sensibili-

  ties; and attention to uncertainty can appeal to scientific skepticism—

  unknowing is, after all, an ingredient of positivist philosophy and an honest

  upshot of inductive reasoning, even with accumulation of numerous facts.

  Still, James welcomed naturalistic inquiries to reduce the mysteries. That

  scientific impulse has thrived from his teacher Emil du Bois- Reymond’s

  dedication to finding “physical- chemical . . . forces” to explain physiology, to

  con temporary neuroscientist Antonio Damasio’s eagerness to “understand

  how . . . physical cells . . . develop . . . a conscious mind.” James maintained

  An Earnestly Inquiring State  269

  The Writer’s Corner.

  Photo by Paul Croce, Shanty, Keene Valley, NY, June 2011.

  James’s favorite ledge provided a welcoming nook at a crease in the rock with pine

  needles for a seat and some sturdy pines for footrests. In the summer of 1898, he

  divided his time between hiking in the dense forests of the Adirondacks and sitting at

  his ledge, likely the spot where he wrote “Philosophical Conceptions and Practical

  Results,” the lecture in which he offered the first public statement of pragmatism.

  He used his hiking experiences, including times when he got so severely lost in the

  woods that he strained his heart, to introduce his listeners to the “trackless forest of

  human experience” (PRG, 258).

  that such scientific banishing of mystery would not always be pos si ble. And

  when scientific understanding could be achieved, it could be useful, but not

  for every human purpose; the methods needed to reduce mystery were not

 

‹ Prev