The Fabric of the Cosmos: Space, Time, and the Texture of Reality
Page 15
No Smoke but Fire
In case you missed any of the details, let's summarize where we've gotten. Through the Heisenberg uncertainty principle, quantum mechanics claims that there are features of the world—like the position and the velocity of a particle, or the spin of a particle about various axes—that cannot simultaneously have definite values. A particle, according to quantum theory, cannot have a definite position and a definite velocity; a particle cannot have a definite spin (clockwise or counterclockwise) about more than one axis; a particle cannot simultaneously have definite attributes for things that lie on opposite sides of the uncertainty divide. Instead, particles hover in quantum limbo, in a fuzzy, amorphous, probabilistic mixture of all possibilities; only when measured is one definite outcome selected from the many. Clearly, this is a drastically different picture of reality than that painted by classical physics.
Ever the skeptic about quantum mechanics, Einstein, together with his colleagues Podolsky and Rosen, tried to use this aspect of quantum mechanics as a weapon against the theory itself. EPR argued that even though quantum mechanics does not allow such features to be simultaneously determined, particles nevertheless do have definite values for position and velocity; particles do have definite spin values about all axes; particles do have definite values for all things forbidden by quantum uncertainty. EPR thus argued that quantum mechanics cannot handle all elements of physical reality—it cannot handle the position and velocity of a particle; it cannot handle the spin of a particle about more than one axis—and hence is an incomplete theory.
For a long time, the issue of whether EPR were correct seemed more a question of metaphysics than of physics. As Pauli said, if you can't actually measure features forbidden by quantum uncertainty, what difference could it possibly make if they, nevertheless, exist in some hidden fold of reality? But, remarkably, John Bell found something that had escaped Einstein, Bohr, and all the other giants of twentieth-century theoretical physics: he found that the mere existence of certain things, even if they are beyond explicit measurement or determination, does make a difference—a difference that can be checked experimentally. Bell showed that if EPR were correct, the results found by two widely separated detectors measuring certain particle properties (spin about various randomly chosen axes, in the approach we have taken) would have to agree more than 50 percent of the time.
Bell had this insight in 1964, but at that time the technology did not exist to undertake the required experiments. By the early 1970s it did. Beginning with Stuart Freedman and John Clauser at Berkeley, followed by Edward Fry and Randall Thompson at Texas A&M, and culminating in the early 1980s with the work of Alain Aspect and collaborators working in France, ever more refined and impressive versions of these experiments were carried out. In the Aspect experiment, for example, the two detectors were placed 13 meters apart and a container of energetic calcium atoms was placed midway between them. Well-understood physics shows that each calcium atom, as it returns to its normal, less energetic state, will emit two photons, traveling back to back, whose spins are perfectly correlated, just as in the example of correlated electron spins we have been discussing. Indeed, in Aspect's experiment, whenever the detector settings are the same, the two photons are measured to have spins that are perfectly aligned. If lights were hooked up to Aspect's detectors to flash red in response to a clockwise spin and blue in response to a counterclockwise spin, the incoming photons would cause the detectors to flash the same color.
But, and this is the crucial point, when Aspect examined data from a large number of runs of the experiment—data in which the left and right detector settings were not always the same but, rather, were randomly and independently varied from run to run—he found that the detectors did not agree more than 50 percent of the time.
This is an earth-shattering result. This is the kind of result that should take your breath away. But just in case it hasn't, let me explain further. Aspect's results show that Einstein, Podolsky, and Rosen were proven by experiment—not by theory, not by pondering, but by nature—to be wrong. And that means there has to be something wrong with the reasoning EPR used to conclude that particles possess definite values for features—like spin values about distinct axes—for which definite values are forbidden by the uncertainty principle.
But where could they have gone wrong? Well, remember that the Einstein, Podolsky, and Rosen argument hangs on one central assumption: if at a given moment you can determine a feature of an object by an experiment done on another, spatially distant object, then the first object must have had this feature all along. Their rationale for this assumption was simple and thoroughly reasonable. Your measurement was done over here while the first object was way over there. The two objects were spatially separate, and hence your measurement could not possibly have had any effect on the first object. More precisely, since nothing goes faster than the speed of light, if your measurement on one object were somehow to cause a change in the other—for example, to cause the other to take on an identical spinning motion about a chosen axis—there would have to be a delay before this could happen, a delay at least as long as the time it would take light to traverse the distance between the two objects. But in both our abstract reasoning and in the actual experiments, the two particles are examined by the detectors at the same time. Therefore, whatever we learn about the first particle by measuring the second must be a feature that the first particle possessed, completely independent of whether we happened to undertake the measurement at all. In short, the core of the Einstein, Podolsky, Rosen argument is that an object over there does not care about what you do to another object over here.
But as we just saw, this reasoning leads to the prediction that the detectors should find the same result more than half the time, a prediction that is refuted by the experimental results. We are forced to conclude that the assumption made by Einstein, Podolsky, and Rosen, no matter how reasonable it seems, cannot be how our quantum universe works. Thus, through this indirect but carefully considered reasoning, the experiments lead us to conclude that an object over there does care about what you do to another object over here.
Even though quantum mechanics shows that particles randomly acquire this or that property when measured, we learn that the randomness can be linked across space. Pairs of appropriately prepared particles— they're called entangled particles—don't acquire their measured properties independently. They are like a pair of magical dice, one thrown in Atlantic City and the other in Las Vegas, each of which randomly comes up one number or another, yet the two of which somehow manage always to agree. Entangled particles act similarly, except they require no magic. Entangled particles, even though spatially separate, do not operate autonomously.
Einstein, Podolsky, and Rosen set out to show that quantum mechanics provides an incomplete description of the universe. Half a century later, theoretical insights and experimental results inspired by their work require us to turn their analysis on its head and conclude that the most basic, intuitively reasonable, classically sensible part of their reasoning is wrong: the universe is not local. The outcome of what you do at one place can be linked with what happens at another place, even if nothing travels between the two locations—even if there isn't enough time for anything to complete the journey between the two locations. Einstein's, Podolsky's, and Rosen's intuitively pleasing suggestion that such long-range correlations arise merely because particles have definite, preexisting, correlated properties is ruled out by the data. That's what makes this all so shocking. 14
In 1997, Nicolas Gisin and his team at the University of Geneva carried out a version of the Aspect experiment in which the two detectors were placed 11 kilometers apart. The results were unchanged. On the microscopic scale of the photon's wavelengths, 11 kilometers is gargantuan. It might as well be 11 million kilometers—or 11 billion light-years, for that matter. There is every reason to believe that the correlation between the photons would persist no matter how far apart the detectors are placed.
This sounds totally bizarre. But there is now overwhelming evidence for this so-called quantum entanglement. If two photons are entangled, the successful measurement of either photon's spin about one axis "forces" the other, distant photon to have the same spin about the same axis; the act of measuring one photon "compels" the other, possibly distant photon to snap out of the haze of probability and take on a definitive spin value—a value that precisely matches the spin of its distant companion. And that boggles the mind. 8
Entanglement and Special Relativity: The Standard View
I have put the words "forces" and "compels" in quotes because while they convey the sentiment our classical intuition longs for, their precise meaning in this context is critical to whether or not we are in for even more of an upheaval. With their everyday definitions, these words conjure up an image of volitional causality: we choose to do something here so as to cause or force a particular something to happen over there. If that were the right description of how the two photons are interrelated, special relativity would be on the ropes. The experiments show that from the viewpoint of an experimenter in the laboratory, at the precise moment one photon's spin is measured, the other photon immediately takes on the same spin property. If something were traveling from the left photon to the right photon, alerting the right photon that the left photon's spin had been determined through a measurement, it would have to travel between the photons instantaneously, conflicting with the speed limit set by special relativity.
The consensus among physicists is that any such apparent conflict with special relativity is illusory. The intuitive reason is that even though the two photons are spatially separate, their common origin establishes a fundamental link between them. Although they speed away from each other and become spatially separate, their history entwines them; even when distant, they are still part of one physical system. And so, it's really not that a measurement on one photon forces or compels another distant photon to take on identical properties. Rather, the two photons are so intimately bound up that it is justified to consider them—even though they are spatially separate—as parts of one physical entity. Then we can say that one measurement on this single entity—an entity containing two photons—affects the entity; that is, it affects both photons at once.
While this imagery may make the connection between the photons a little easier to swallow, as stated it's vague—what does it really mean to say two spatially separate things are one? A more precise argument is the following. When special relativity says that nothing can travel faster than the speed of light, the "nothing" refers to familiar matter or energy. But the case at hand is subtler, because it doesn't appear that any matter or energy is traveling between the two photons, and so there isn't anything whose speed we are led to measure. Nevertheless, there is a way to learn whether we've run headlong into a conflict with special relativity. A feature common to matter and energy is that when traveling from place to place they can transmit information. Photons traveling from a broadcast station to your radio carry information. Electrons traveling through Internet cables to your computer carry information. So, in any situation where something—even something unidentified—is purported to have traveled faster than light speed, a litmus test is to ask whether it has, or at least could have, transmitted information. If the answer is no, the standard reasoning goes, then nothing has exceeded light speed, and special relativity remains unchallenged. In practice, this is the test that physicists often employ in determining whether some subtle process has violated the laws of special relativity. (None has ever survived this test.) Let's apply it here.
Is there any way that, by measuring the spin of the left-moving and the right-moving photons about some given axis, we can send information from one to the other? The answer is no. Why? Well, the output found in either the left or the right detector is nothing but a random sequence of clockwise and counterclockwise results, since on any given run there is an equal probability of the particle to be found spinning one way or the other. In no way can we control or predict the outcome of any particular measurement. Thus, there is no message, there is no hidden code, there is no information whatsoever in either of these two random lists. The only interesting thing about the two lists is that they are identical—but that can't be discerned until the two lists are brought together and compared by some conventional, slower-than-light means (fax, e-mail, phone call, etc.). The standard argument thus concludes that although measuring the spin of one photon appears instantaneously to affect the other, no information is transmitted from one to the other, and the speed limit of special relativity remains in force. Physicists say that the spin results are correlated—since the lists are identical—but do not stand in a traditional cause-and-effect relationship because nothing travels between the two distant locations.
Entanglement and Special Relativity: The Contrarian View
Is that it? Is the potential conflict between the nonlocality of quantum mechanics and special relativity fully resolved? Well, probably. On the basis of the above considerations, the majority of physicists sum it up by saying there is a harmonious coexistence between special relativity and Aspect's results on entangled particles. In short, special relativity survives by the skin of its teeth. Many physicists find this convincing, but others have a nagging sense that there is more to the story.
At a gut level I've always shared the coexistence view, but there is no denying that the issue is delicate. At the end of the day, no matter what holistic words one uses or what lack of information one highlights, two widely separated particles, each of which is governed by the randomness of quantum mechanics, somehow stay sufficiently "in touch" so that whatever one does, the other instantly does too. And that seems to suggest that some kind of faster-than-light something is operating between them.
Where do we stand? There is no ironclad, universally accepted answer. Some physicists and philosophers have suggested that progress hinges on our recognizing that the focus of the discussion so far is somewhat misplaced: the real core of special relativity, they rightly point out, is not so much that light sets a speed limit, as that light's speed is something that all observers, regardless of their own motion, agree upon. 16 More generally, these researchers emphasize, the central principle of special relativity is that no observational vantage point is singled out over any other. Thus, they propose (and many agree) that if the egalitarian treatment of all constant-velocity observers could be squared with the experimental results on entangled particles, the tension with special relativity would be resolved. 17 But achieving this goal is not a trivial task. To see this concretely, let's think about how good old-fashioned textbook quantum mechanics explains the Aspect experiment.
According to standard quantum mechanics, when we perform a measurement and find a particle to be here, we cause its probability wave to change: the previous range of potential outcomes is reduced to the one actual result our measurement finds, as illustrated in Figure 4.7. Physicists say the measurement causes the probability wave to collapse and they envision that the larger the initial probability wave at some location, the larger the likelihood that the wave will collapse to that point—that is, the larger the likelihood that the particle will be found at that point. In the standard approach, the collapse happens instantaneously across the whole universe: once you find the particle here, the thinking goes, the probability of its being found anywhere else immediately drops to zero, and this is reflected in an immediate collapse of the probability wave.
In the Aspect experiment, when the left-moving photon's spin is measured and is found, say, to be clockwise about some axis, this collapses its probability wave throughout all of space, instantaneously setting the counterclockwise part to zero. Since this collapse happens everywhere, it happens also at the location of the right-moving photon. And, it turns out, this affects the counterclockwise part of the right-moving photon's probability wave, causing it to collapse to zero too. Thus, no matter how far away the right-moving photon is from the left-mo
ving photon, its probability wave is instantaneously affected by the change in the left-moving photon's probability wave, ensuring that it has the same spin as the left-moving photon along the chosen axis. In standard quantum mechanics, then, it is this instantaneous change in probability waves that is responsible for the faster-than-light influence.
Figure 4.7 When a particle is observed at some location, the probability of finding it at any other location drops to zero, while its probability surges to 100 percent at the location where it is observed.
The mathematics of quantum mechanics makes this qualitative discussion precise. And, indeed, the long-range influences arising from collapsing probability waves change the prediction of how often Aspect's left and right detectors (when their axes are randomly and independently chosen) should find the same result. A mathematical calculation is required to get the exact answer (see notes section 18 if you're interested), but when the math is done, it predicts that the detectors should agree precisely 50 percent of the time (rather than predicting agreement more than 50 percent of the time—the result, as we've seen, found using EPR's hypothesis of a local universe). To impressive accuracy, this is just what Aspect found in his experiments, 50 percent agreement. Standard quantum mechanics matches the data impressively.
This is a spectacular success. Nevertheless, there is a hitch. After more than seven decades, no one understands how or even whether the collapse of a probability wave really happens. Over the years, the assumption that probability waves collapse has proven itself a powerful link between the probabilities that quantum theory predicts and the definite outcomes that experiments reveal. But it's an assumption fraught with conundrums. For one thing, the collapse does not emerge from the mathematics of quantum theory; it has to be put in by hand, and there is no agreed-upon or experimentally justified way to do this. For another, how is it possible that by finding an electron in your detector in New York City, you cause the electron's probability wave in the Andromeda galaxy to drop to zero instantaneously? To be sure, once you find the particle in New York City, it definitely won't be found in Andromeda, but what unknown mechanism enforces this with such spectacular efficiency? How, in looser language, does the part of the probability wave in Andromeda, and everywhere else, "know" to drop to zero simultaneously? 19