The Temple of Set I

Home > Other > The Temple of Set I > Page 42
The Temple of Set I Page 42

by Michael A Aquino


  the morally good as what one ought to do according to prevailing passionate custom. Hume

  denied that the good could be ascertained by dispassionate reasoning. Reason, he said, is useful

  only to discover the most practical or sensible approaches to problems. Hence virtue and vice are

  products of sentiment. Virtue is not approved because it is “intrinsically virtue”; it is

  considered to be virtue because it meets with passionate approval.

  The point of this brief tour through certain key concepts in the evolution of ethics is simply

  to show clearly what all too many people perceive only dimly and imprecisely - how the United

  States has developed its “official ethics”. If this background is not understood, Setians cannot

  clearly understand why certain ethical norms are expected in this country - or understand why

  some foreign cultures “mysteriously/unreasonably” reject those norms ... often on what they

  consider to be ethical grounds!

  The science of ethics is not peripheral or incidental to the Temple of Set; it is central to it.

  Whether people hold a certain opinion or behave in a certain way is critically influenced by

  whether or not they believe themselves justified in so doing. Once “rightness” or “wrongness” is

  established, specific LBM workings will be interpreted accordingly. In order to be effective, a

  magician must first recognize and consciously appreciate the ethical components of his

  designs that are particular to their cultural point of origin.

  - 221 -

  Earlier in this chapter it was demonstrated that Western civilization’s efforts to apprehend

  “truth” - and to answer the integral question of whether “truth” and “the good” are inseparable -

  have been arduous and frustrating. The United States emerged at a moment in history - the

  Enlightenment - when reason reigned supreme, and so the values of the Enlightenment’s most

  optimistic and practical political philosopher, John Locke, were incorporated into our

  Constitution.

  Lockean values have served us reasonably well these past two centuries, but what of those

  countries who have “worshipped strange gods”? What do they know of “the good”, and in what

  respect - if any - do they hold “the truth”?

  The principal social contract theorists - Hobbes, Locke, and Rousseau - saw the state as a

  human construct, justifiable only as it might serve the interests of its citizens. The first of two

  great challenges to this preeminence of the individual came from Georg W.F. Hegel, who insisted

  that the state is prior to man.

  Hegel conceived of the universe as the manifestation of God’s mind seeking complete self-

  realization through a process called dialectic idealism. As applied to our particular planet, it is

  the notion that the history of the world consists of part of the spirit of God, manifesting itself

  through the collective spirits of mankind, moving onwards through logic (the dialectic) towards

  completion. An existing idea (thesis) is criticized and partially refuted by its opposite

  (antithesis), resulting in a more perfect product (synthesis). Hegel felt the organic state to be

  the manifestation or reflection of the dialectic of God’s mind in the world. Accordingly it might

  well proceed in ways and towards goals which are not necessarily the sum total of the ways and

  goals of the individual human minds within it.

  The task of national leaders, according to Hegel, is thus to apprehend the “spirit of the

  state” ( Volksgeist) and to make their decisions in support of its furtherment rather than for the

  citizens who may chance to populate it at a given point in time. The Enlightenment values of

  individualism and rights against a government were considered by Hegel to limit freedom:

  Since they reduce the scope and power of the whole, they serve to restrict possibility.

  Hegel plus a heavy dose of 19th-century Wagnerian Romanticism pointed the way to the

  state-cults of National Socialist Germany and Fascist Italy. Germany in particular sought to

  redirect the sense of life-consciousness from the individual human being to the state. Most

  Germans were able to achieve this only in a mundane sense - in a kind of ecstatic selflessness

  created and sustained by propaganda. But the “monk-knights” of the prewar SS could disdain,

  even willingly embrace the death of the individual human body according to the doctrine that

  disciplined personal consciousness could be transferred to a larger life-form - that of the

  Hegelian state - and that individual sacrifice towards the strengthening of that life-form would

  actually contribute towards one’s greater immortality. In a very real way incomprehensible to the

  mundane mind, therefore, all of the individual-death references in the SS - such as the

  Totenkopf insignia and ritual pledges of “faithfulness unto death” - were in fact arrogant

  affirmations of immortality. To Dr. Rauschning Hitler remarked:

  To the Christian doctrine of the infinite significance of the individual human soul and of

  personal responsibility, I oppose with icy clarity the saving doctrine of the nothingness and

  insignificance of the individual human being, and of his continued existence in the visible

  immortality of the nation. The dogma of vicarious suffering and death through a divine savior

  gives place to that of the representative living and acting of the new Leader-legislator, which

  liberates the mass of the faithful from the burden of free will.

  Both National Socialism and Fascism are now ghosts of history, but the principle which

  underlay their phenomenal power and impact - the organic state as prior to its citizens - remains

  very much a force in the contemporary international environment.

  - 222 -

  In the United States, social and political truth is arrived at via the methods specified in the

  Constitution, all of which are based on some combination of direct or representative voting. Our

  national perception of truth is thus democratic - an approach which John Locke would consider

  eminently reasonable, but one which would affront Plato and Hegel. To them, truth was/is an

  absolute principle - not something to be determined by whim, much less by the masses. Plato

  held that truth could be attained through the dialectic of human philosophical enquiry; Hegel

  insisted that only God could consciously employ such a dialectic, and that the most humanity

  could hope for was to sense its reflection through the dynamics of the state.

  What is it we see when we look at the many “democracies” and “republics” of the world and

  perceive them to be behaving not as vehicles for the benefit of their individual citizens, but

  rather as cultural amœbæ of ethnocentric, even xenophobic passion which contemptuously

  sweep aside appeals to reason? A few are relics of ancient theocratic systems, but most have shed

  this worn-out skin only to regenerate it under the guise of the Volksgeist.

  One may indeed communicate with the citizens of such cultures as individuals, but to

  influence the culture as a whole one may not appeal just to the citizens’ individual desires.

  Rather one must speak to the interest of whatever it is that they perceive their “national spirit” to

  be. To seek to “Westernize” it - to alter citizens’ conception of the state into a social-contract

  model - is to attack not a set of rational opinions, but an article of faith which is pe
rceived to

  be the very fountain of truth and ethics.

  The second great challenge to social-contract individualism came, of course, from Karl

  Marx. Marx was strongly influenced by Hegel, but believed that Hegel had made a fundamental

  mistake in using nations as the basis for his dialectic and in relating it to a divine manifestation

  or purpose. Marx considered the dialectic to be a function of economic struggle between social

  classes, and he denied the existence of any supernatural intelligence, calling all religion “the

  opiate of the people”.

  Marxism, sometimes called dialectic materialism to distinguish it from the dialectic

  idealism of Hegel, is a theory of socialism that identifies class struggle as the fundamental force

  in history. Increasing concentration of industrial control in the capitalist class and the

  consequent intensification of class antagonisms and of misery among the workers will lead to a

  revolutionary seizure of power by the proletariat and the subsequent establishment of a classless,

  utopian society.

  Marx, like Hegel, premised his ideas on a necessary, inevitable process of history.

  Thus communism would eventually come to pass, no matter what capitalism tries to do to stop

  it. The other side of this coin is that there is nothing Marxists can do to speed it up; their society

  must first evolve to the “last stages” of decadent capitalism. This didn’t suit V.I. Lenin, who

  wanted to accelerate social evolution a bit. His prescription for doing so was the so-called

  “dictatorship of the proletariat”, under which a communist elite would force-march the masses

  towards their eventual paradise. The state apparat would then “wither away”.

  As in the case of Hegelian state-preeminence, communism cannot simply be challenged or

  refuted by appeals to individual self-interest. To a serious Marxist, history is again moved by far

  greater forces than the wills of individuals who may chance to inhabit it at a given point in time.

  Marxist states view the advanced capitalist cultures as social bombs collectively approaching

  critical mass; their desire is accordingly to avoid being caught up in the desperate external

  adventurism, including apocalyptic warfare, which they expect deteriorating capitalist nations to

  employ in an effort to stave off their inevitable communist revolutions.

  Communism [to use the label by which modern Marxism is generally known] incorporates

  two attitudes towards the truth. The “greater truth” - the materialist dialectic - is considered to

  be absolute, and adherence to it is once again supra-rational: an article of faith. Why an article

  of faith? Because the people, if given the sole power to determine the government, might revolt

  - 223 -

  against it again - particularly if it is not [as per Locke] designed to facilitate their pursuit of

  personal interests. The option of further revolution must therefore be removed - by representing

  the Communist Party as the “priesthood” of a “god” higher than that of the people themselves. In

  service to this “god”, lesser ethical issues are unimportant - and indeed heretical if they confuse

  or inhibit the greater truth.

  When capitalists seek to “reason” with communists, they fail to realize that they are

  regarded as ignorant, corrupt, or deluded by their very inability to see and accept the

  “great truth” . A sincere communist does not reason with such an opponent any more than

  with a child; he seeks rather to placate, deceive, or otherwise control him.

  To communicate with a communist theoretician is thus a difficult task. One must first

  establish basic rapport by displaying an understanding of, if not an agreement with Marxist

  theory. Immediate goals of mutual interest may then be pursued jointly insofar as they do not

  intrude into ideological realms where the communist’s position must necessarily rigidify.

  A curious and paradoxical picture emerges from this examination of communist vs.

  capitalist ethics. In the West we are accustomed to regard the United States as a “religious”

  society, and to condemn communism for its “godlessness”. In communist countries theorists

  disdain Western adherence to religion and take pride in communism’s “state atheism”. But is

  this picture borne out in practice?

  Locke advocated a national structure in which supreme wisdom lay in the will of the

  citizenry and in which organized religion played only a symbolic and ceremonial role: in his

  words a “reasonable Christianity”. Our governments have since approached our national and

  international problems under the presumption that the free will of the human beings

  directly involved will order the course of events. This is vintage Enlightenment-thinking,

  and to date the United States has seen no reason to subordinate it to any “higher authority”. In

  terms of its political decision-making processes, the United States behaves atheistically.

  On the other hand, communist leaders do not consider themselves able to control or

  influence the passage of events as free agents. They may make minor adjustments here and

  there, but the basic course of the future is above and beyond their control, locked in place

  according to Marx’ principles of historic determinism. Like the ancient Mesopotamians, they

  perceive themselves as the incidental tools of a “god” - whose name just happens to be Dialectic

  Materialism instead of Baal or Marduk. In terms of its political decision-making processes,

  communism behaves theistically.

  Where ethics are concerned, therefore, capitalism holds itself fully responsible for its own,

  while communism considers any and all “minor” ethical abuses automatically justified if in

  service of its “god”. This is a very crucial point - and it explains why the United States goes

  through such persistent agonies of self-criticism while communist countries such as China and

  the late Soviet Union shrug off far more horrendous excesses.

  [At the conclusion of the 20th Century CE, the Soviet Union dissolved into constituent

  quasi-capitalist states. Communism as a political and economic phenomenon has revealed its

  fragility. It will be interesting to see what happens to communism as a “religion”.]

  The Black Magician contemplating a particular LBM working must therefore determine not

  only whether that working will be ethical in his eyes, but also ethical according to the cultural

  mindsets of all other parties to the working: participants, objects, catalysts, witnesses. To label a

  working “good” or “evil” by some knee-jerk, propagandistic formula is entirely inadequate.

  [Formula “good/evil” values are merely appropriate for the profane masses, who can’t - and

  don’t want to - understand anything more precise.]

  There is thus no easy answer to the question of whether a given magical act is “good” or

  “evil”. In itself it is ethically neutral. As Machiavelli so clearly observed, it is the result it

  produces which will be judged - and then it is up to the magician to determine what judgments

  - 224 -

  - by which judges - will be important. Successfully conducted, such an assessment will not only

  reinforce the success of a given working; it will also ensure that the magician correctly

  anticipates the actual consequences of its immediate results.

  This chapter was intended to achieve two goals: First, to alert yo
u to the fact that everyone

  in the world is practicing LBM on everyone else, usually unconsciously and usually extremely

  unskillfully. Second, to advise you that, as you become sensitive to its use on you - and skilled in

  your own use of it on others - you can accomplish a great deal.

  You will now have to go out and study the aforementioned subjects, practice them, and

  become fluent in them before they will be of any real use to you. Just reading this chapter and

  assuming that you “get the message” is not sufficient.

  It is perhaps appropriate to conclude with a brief but necessary warning: As an association

  of Adepts in LBM, the Temple of Set could not function cooperatively if its Initiates practiced

  this particular Art on one another, no matter with what good intentions. You are trusting the

  Temple and its sages to enhance and Recognize your self-initiation - not to mislead or

  exploit you for lesser/ulterior purposes. You must reciprocate in turn. So remember this point

  and remember it well:

  Do not - ever - attempt to control another Setian through LBM.

  Because he trusts you not to, his usual guards will be down, and you may think him easy to

  influence in this way. Nevertheless it is just a question of time before either your “victim” or

  another Setian realizes what is happening, whereupon you will find yourself facing probable

  expulsion.

  In all contacts and communications within the Temple, be straightforward, direct, and

  open. In profane society you might be pounced upon as a “mark” or “sucker” for such behavior,

  but within the Temple of Set you will find yourself trusted and respected as a fellow Initiate and

  magician.

  - 225 -

  20: Greater Black Magic

  There are two sharp distinctions between the Temple of Set’s principles and those of other

  religions, philosophies, and occult doctrines. The first is that, while we do not consider logical

  positivism as being sufficient to explain the universe, we do consider it a necessary foundation

  upon which to build such an explanation. Sound metaphysics must be in keeping with what is

  known about related subjects in physics, else the metaphysics are simply articles of faith. “Faith”

  is how one excuses a belief he cannot justify through any rational or logical criteria.

 

‹ Prev