Book Read Free

The Big Picture

Page 5

by Carroll, Sean M.


  10

  11

  12

  I

  13

  n 1971, viewers watching live TV got to see Apollo 15 astronaut David

  14

  Scott perform a fun demonstration. Near the end of an extravehicular

  15

  moon walk, Scott held up a hammer and a feather, then proceeded to

  16

  let go of them simultaneously. Both objects, under the gentle pull of the

  17

  moon’s gravity, fell to the ground, landing at precisely the same time.

  18

  That’s not what would have happened here on Earth, unless you

  19

  were practicing your spacesuit drills in one of NASA’s giant vacuum

  20

  chambers. Under ordinary circumstances, air resistance would greatly slow

  21

  the fall of the feather, while the hammer would be largely unaffected.

  22

  But in the vacuum on the moon’s surface, their trajectories were indistin-

  23

  guishable.

  24

  Scott had confirmed an important insight put forward by Galileo Gali-

  25

  lei back in the late sixteenth century: the natural motion of all objects is to

  26

  fall in the same way under the influence of gravity, and it is only friction

  27

  caused by air that makes heavier objects seem to fall faster than lighter ones

  28

  in our everyday experience. And a good thing too. As mission controller Joe

  29

  Allen put it, this experimental result was “predicted by well- established

  30

  theory, but a result nonetheless reassuring considering both the number of

  31

  viewers that witnessed the experiment, and the fact that the homeward

  32

  journey was based critically on the validity of the particular theory being

  33

  tested.”

  34

  The story is told that Galileo performed a version of the experiment

  S35

  N36

  23

  Big Picture - UK final proofs.indd 23

  20/07/2016 10:02:37

  T H E B IG PIC T U R E

  01

  himself, dropping balls of different weights (but comparable air resistance)

  02

  from the top of the Leaning Tower of Pisa. Galileo doesn’t seem to have

  03

  claimed that he did this, but it was later asserted by his pupil Vincenzo

  04

  Viviani in a biography of his master.

  05

  06

  07

  08

  09

  The Leaning Tower of Pisa.

  (Courtesy of W. Lloyd MacKenzie)

  10

  11

  12

  13

  14

  15

  16

  17

  18

  19

  20

  21

  22

  23

  24

  25

  26

  The experiment we know Galileo actually performed was an easier one

  27

  to construct and control: he rolled balls of different masses down inclined

  28

  planes. He was able to show that the balls accelerated in a uniform fashion,

  29

  by an amount that depended on the angle of the plane but not on the

  30

  masses of the balls. He then suggested that if we could trust this result all

  31

  the way to planes that were inclined absolutely perpendicular to the floor,

  32

  that would be exactly like dropping objects straight down, without a plane

  33

  there at all. Therefore, he concluded, all masses would fall in a uniform way

  34

  under the force of gravity, if it weren’t for the influence of air resistance.

  35S

  More important than this specific finding is the underlying message it

  36N

  conveys: we can learn about the natural motion of objects by imagining we

  2 4

  Big Picture - UK final proofs.indd 24

  20/07/2016 10:02:38

  t h E W O R l d M Ov E S b y I t S E l F

  can get rid of various nuisance effects, such as friction and air resistance,

  01

  and then perhaps recovering more realistic kinds of motion by putting

  02

  those effects back in later.

  03

  That is no small insight. It is arguably the biggest idea in the history of

  04

  physics.

  05

  Physics is, by far, the simplest science. It doesn’t seem that way, because

  06

  we know so much about it, and the required knowledge often seems esoteric

  07

  and technical. But it is blessed by this amazing feature: we can very often

  08

  make ludicrous simplifications— frictionless surfaces, perfectly spherical

  09

  bodies— ignoring all manner of ancillary effects, and nevertheless get re-

  10

  sults that are unreasonably good. For most interesting problems in other

  11

  sciences, from biology to psychology to economics, if you modeled one tiny

  12

  aspect of a system while pretending all the others didn’t exist, you would

  13

  just end up getting nonsense. (Which doesn’t stop people from trying.)

  14

  This enormous, paradigm- shifting idea— in idealized situations where

  15

  friction and dissipation can be ignored, physics becomes simple— was in

  16

  large part responsible for helping to establish an equally influential, argu-

  17

  ably more world- shattering concept: conservation of momentum. It might

  18

  not sound like a principle of such dramatic import, but momentum is at the

  19

  very heart of a shift in how we view the world, from an ancient cosmos of

  20

  causes and purposes to a modern one of patterns and laws.

  21

  22

  •

  23

  Before Galileo and others revolutionized the study of motion in the six-

  24

  teenth and seventeenth centuries, Aristotle had long reigned as the leading

  25

  thinker on the subject. Aristotle’s view of physics was resolutely teleologi-

  26

  cal: he thought of objects as having a natural state of being, and processes

  27

  as being directed toward a goal. Famously, he suggested that we could dis-

  28

  tinguish between four different kinds of “causes,” although “kinds of expla-

  29

  nation” might be a better translation of what he had in mind. The four

  30

  kinds were material cause, the stuff of which an object is made; formal

  31

  cause, the essential property that makes an object what it is; efficient cause, 32

  the thing that brings the object about (closest to our informal notion of

  33

  “cause”); and final cause, the purpose for which an object exists. Under-

  34

  standing why things change and move and behave the way they do comes

  S35

  down to putting them in the context of these causes.

  N36

  25
/>   Big Picture - UK final proofs.indd 25

  20/07/2016 10:02:38

  T H E B IG PIC T U R E

  01

  For Aristotle, the nature of an object determines how it moves. Of the

  02

  four classical elements, earth and water tend to fall to lower elevations,

  03

  whereas air and fire tend to rise. An object can be in its natural state of rest

  04

  or motion, where it will tend to remain until a “violent motion” causes it to

  05

  change, after which it will return.

  06

  Consider a coffee cup sitting at rest on a table. It is in its natural state, in

  07

  this case at rest. (Unless we were to pull the table out from beneath it, in

  08

  which case it would naturally fall, but let’s not do that.) Now imagine we

  09

  exert a violent motion, pushing the cup across the table. As we push it, it

  10

  moves; when we stop, it returns to its natural state of rest. In order to keep

  11

  it moving, we would have to keep pushing on it. As Aristotle says, “Every-

  12

  thing that is in motion must be moved by something.”

  13

  This is manifestly how coffee cups do behave in the real world. The dif-

  14

  ference between Galileo and Aristotle wasn’t that one was saying true

  15

  things and the other was saying false things; it’s that the things Galileo

  16

  chose to focus on turned out to be a useful basis for a more rigorous and

  17

  complete understanding of phenomena beyond the original set of examples,

  18

  in a way that Aristotle’s did not.

  19

  In the sixth century, John Philoponus, a philosopher and theologian

  20

  living in Egypt, began the journey from Aristotle to our present under-

  21

  standing of motion. He suggested that we should think of a motive power

  22

  or “impetus,” which was imparted to a body by the initial act of pushing,

  23

  and kept the body in motion until all of the impetus had dissipated. It was

  24

  a small step forward, but one that opened up a new vista on how to think

  25

  about the nature of motion. Rather than talking about causes, the focus

  26

  shifted to quantities and properties of matter itself.

  27

  28

  29

  30

  31

  32

  33

  34

  35S

  Ibn Sina (Avicenna), Persian philosopher

  36N

  and polymath, d. 1037.

  2 6

  Big Picture - UK final proofs.indd 26

  20/07/2016 10:02:38

  t h E W O R l d M Ov E S b y I t S E l F

  Another crucial contribution was made by the Persian thinker Ibn Sina

  01

  (sometimes Romanized as Avicenna), one of the leading lights of the Is-

  02

  lamic Golden Age, around the year 1000. He elaborated on Philoponus’s

  03

  idea of impetus, calling it “inclination” ( mayl). It was Ibn Sina who pro-

  04

  posed that inclination didn’t disperse on its own, but only due to air resis-

  05

  tance or other external influences. And in a vacuum, he points out, there is

  06

  no such resistance: an undisturbed projectile would keep moving at a con-

  07

  stant rate, forever.

  08

  This brings us remarkably close to the modern idea of inertia— the con-

  09

  cept that bodies will move uniformly unless acted upon. In the fourteenth

  10

  century, Jean Buridan, a French cleric who was probably influenced by Ibn

  11

  Sina, came up with a quantitative formula equating the impetus with the

  12

  weight of an object times its velocity. At the time, however, the distinction

  13

  between mass and weight was not understood. Galileo, influenced in turn

  14

  by Buridan, coined the term “momentum” and said it would remain con-

  15

  stant in a body that was not being acted on by any forces, but he didn’t

  16

  clearly differentiate between momentum and velocity. It was René Des-

  17

  cartes who equated momentum with mass times speed, but even he (despite

  18

  being the inventor of analytic geometry) didn’t appreciate that momentum

  19

  has a direction as well as a magnitude; that was left to Dutch scientist

  20

  Christiaan Huygens in the seventeenth century. Then, it was Isaac Newton

  21

  who put the notion to brilliant use in his systematic reinvention of the sci-

  22

  ence of motion, which we still teach in high schools and colleges today.

  23

  24

  •

  25

  Why is conservation of momentum such a big deal? We’re not here to study

  26

  Newtonian mechanics, as rewarding as that would be. There will be no

  27

  exercises involving pulleys or inclined planes. We’re here to think about the

  28

  fundamental nature of reality.

  29

  For Aristotle, physics was a story of natures and causes. Whenever there

  30

  was motion of any sort, there had to be a mover: an efficient cause that led

  31

  to that motion. Aristotle had a more expansive definition of “motion” than

  32

  we use today, one that is really closer to “transformation.” It would include,

  33

  for example, an object changing its color, or possibilities becoming actuali-

  34

  ties. But the same principles apply; Aristotle’s conviction was that all of

  S35

  these transformations implied the existence of a transforming cause. There’s

  N36

  27

  Big Picture - UK final proofs.indd 27

  20/07/2016 10:02:38

  T H E B IG PIC T U R E

  01

  nothing absurd about such an idea. In our everyday experience, things don’t

  02

  “just happen”— something works to cause them, to bring them about. Ar-

  03

  istotle, without any of the benefit of modern scientific knowledge, was try-

  04

  ing to codify what he knew about the way the world works into some kind

  05

  of systematic framework.

  06

  So Aristotle observes a world populated by countless changing things,

  07

  and infers a cause in each case. A is caused to move by B, which in turn is

  08

  caused to move by C, and so on. It’s reasonable to ask: What started it all?

  09

  To what can we trace back this chain of motions and causes? He quickly

  10

  rejects the possibilities that any motions are self- caused, or that the chain

  11

  of causes goes back infinitely far. It needs to terminate somewhere, in some-

  12

  thing that causes motion but does not itself move: an unmoved mover.

  13

 
Aristotle’s theory of motion was largely set forth in his book Physics, but

  14

  the details of the unmoved mover were left to a later one, Metaphysics.

  15

  There, despite being nominally a pagan, he identifies the unmoved mover

  16

  with God: not just an abstract principle but a being, immortal and benevo-

  17

  lent. It’s not a bad argument for God’s existence, although it’s easy to poke

  18

  holes in it by denying the underlying assumptions. Maybe some motions do

  19

  cause themselves, or maybe infinite regresses are perfectly okay. But this

  20

  “cosmological argument” was extremely influential, picked up and elabo-

  21

  rated on by Thomas Aquinas and others.

  22

  Most important for our purposes, the whole structure of Aristotle’s ar-

  23

  gument for an unmoved mover rests on his idea that motions require causes.

  24

  Once we know about conservation of momentum, that idea loses its steam.

  25

  We can quibble over the details— I have no doubt Aristotle would have

  26

  been able to come up with an ingenious way of accounting for objects on

  27

  frictionless surfaces moving at constant velocity. What matters is that the

  28

  new physics of Galileo and his friends implied an entirely new ontology, a

  29

  deep shift in how we thought about the nature of reality. “Causes” didn’t

  30

  have the central role that they once did. The universe doesn’t need a push;

  31

  it can just keep going.

  32

  It’s hard to overemphasize the importance of this shift. Of course, even

  33

  today, we talk about causes and effects all the time. But if you open the

  34

  contemporary equivalent of Aristotle’s Physics— a textbook on quantum

  35S

  field theory, for example— words like that are nowhere to be found. We

  36N

  2 8

  Big Picture - UK final proofs.indd 28

  20/07/2016 10:02:38

  t h E W O R l d M Ov E S b y I t S E l F

  still, with good reason, talk about causes in everyday speech, but they’re no

  01

  longer part of our best fundamental ontology.

  02

  What we’re seeing is a manifestation of the layered nature of our de-

  03

  scriptions of reality. At the deepest level we currently know about, the basic

  04

  notions are things like “spacetime,” “quantum fields,” “equations of mo-

  05

  tion,” and “interactions.” No causes, whether material, formal, efficient, or

  06

  final. But there are levels on top of that, where the vocabulary changes.

  07

  Indeed, it’s possible to recover pieces of Aristotle’s physics quantitatively, as

 

‹ Prev