The Big Picture
Page 6
08
limits of Newtonian mechanics in an appropriate regime, where dissipation
09
and friction are central. (Coffee cups do come to a stop, after all.) In the
10
same way, it’s possible to understand why it’s so useful to refer to causes and
11
effects in our everyday experience, even if they’re not present in the underly-
12
ing equations. There are many different useful stories we have to tell about
13
reality to get along in the world.
14
15
16
17
18
19
20
21
22
23
24
25
26
27
28
29
30
31
32
33
34
S35
N36
29
Big Picture - UK final proofs.indd 29
20/07/2016 10:02:38
01
02
03
4
04
05
What Determines What Will Happen?
06
07
08
09
10
11
12
13
14
15
16
17
Isaac Newton, the most influential scientist of all time, was a very reli-
gious man. His views were undoubtedly heterodox by the standards of
his childhood Anglican faith; he rejected the Trinity, and wrote nu-
merous works on prophesy and biblical interpretation, with chapter titles
18
such as “Of the power of the eleventh horn of Daniel’s fourth Beast, to
19
change times and laws.” He couldn’t rely on an argument for God’s exis-
20
tence along the lines of Aristotle’s unmoved mover. His own work seemed
21
to depict a universe moving perfectly well under its own power, but as he
22
pointed out in the “General Scholium” (an essay appended to later editions
23
of his masterwork, Principia Mathematica), someone had to set it all up:
24
25
This most excellently contrived System of the Sun, and Plan-
26
ets, and Comets, could not have its Origin from any other than
27
from the wise Conduct and Dominion of an intelligent and
28
powerful Being.
29
30
Elsewhere, Newton seemed to imply that the mutual perturbations of the
31
planets on one another would gradually cause the system to get out of
32
whack, at which point God would intervene to set things back in order.
33
Pierre- Simon Laplace, a French physicist and mathematician born a cen-
34
tury after Newton, thought differently. Scholars debate over his true reli-
35S
gious views, which seem to have vacillated between deism (God created the
36N
world, but did not subsequently intervene in its operation) and outright
30
Big Picture - UK final proofs.indd 30
20/07/2016 10:02:38
W h At dE t E R M I n E S W h A t W I l l h A PPE n ?
atheism. Laplace is the one who, when asked by Emperor Napoleón why
01
God didn’t appear in his book on celestial mechanics, purportedly replied,
02
“I had no need of that hypothesis.” Whatever his ultimate beliefs, it seems
03
that Laplace held steadfastly against the idea of a Creator who would ever
04
directly interfere in the motions of the world.
05
06
07
08
09
10
11
12
13
14
15
16
17
18
19
20
21
22
23
Pierre- Simon Marquis de Laplace, 1749– 1827.
24
25
Laplace was one of the first thinkers to truly understand classical
26
(Newtonian) mechanics, deep in his bones— better than Newton himself.
27
Someone was bound to do it. Science progresses, and we learn more and
28
more about our best theories; there are many physicists today who under-
29
stand relativity better than Einstein, or quantum mechanics better than
30
Schrödinger or Heisenberg. Laplace tackled problems from the stability of
31
the solar system to the foundations of probability, routinely inventing the
32
required new mathematics along the way. He suggested that Newtonian
33
gravity could be thought of as a field theory, positing a “gravitational poten-34
tial field” that filled all of space, thereby resolving Newton’s puzzlement
S35
about actions at a distance between faraway bodies.
N36
31
Big Picture - UK final proofs.indd 31
20/07/2016 10:02:39
T H E B IG PIC T U R E
01
Perhaps Laplace’s greatest contribution to our understanding of me-
02
chanics was not a technical or mathematical advance, but a philosophical
03
one. He realized that there was a simple answer to the question “What
04
determines what will happen next?” And the answer is “The state of the
05
universe right now.”
06
There’s a worry that this result threatens the existence of human agency,
07
our ability to make choices about what to do next. As we’ll see, that’s not
08
really an issue of physics, but one of description: What is the best way we
09
have to talk about human beings? When we talk about simple Newtonian
10
systems, like the planets moving through the solar system, determinism is
11
part of the picture. When we talk about enormously more complex things
12
like people, there’s no way for us to have enough information to make iron-
13
clad predictions. Our best theories of people, presented on their own terms
14
and without reference to underlying particles and forces, leave plenty of
15
room for human choice.
16
•
17
18
The world, according to classical physics, is not fundamentally teleological.
19
What happens next is not influenced by any future goals or final causes
20
toward which it might be working. Nor is it fundamentally historical; to
21
know the future— in principle— requires only precise knowledge of the
22
present moment, not any additional knowledge of the past. Indeed, the en-
23
tirety of both the past and future history ar
e utterly determined by the
24
present. The universe is resolutely focused on the current moment; it
25
marches forward, instant to instant, under the grip of unbreakable physical
26
laws, with no heed paid to its glorious accomplishments or to its hopeful
27
prospects. Much later, the biologist Ernst Haeckel would dub this view-
28
point dysteleology, though the term is so ungainly that it never really
29
caught on.
30
In modern parlance, Laplace was pointing out that the universe is some-
31
thing like a computer. You enter an input (the state of the universe right
32
now), it does a calculation (the laws of physics) and gives you an output (the
33
state of the universe one moment later). Similar ideas had previously been
34
suggested by Gottfried Wilhelm Leibniz and Roger Boscovich, and were
35S
prefigured over two millennia earlier by Ajivika, a heterodox school of an-
36N
cient Indian philosophy. Since computers hadn’t been invented yet, Laplace
32
Big Picture - UK final proofs.indd 32
20/07/2016 10:02:39
W h At dE t E R M I n E S W h A t W I l l h A PPE n ?
imagined a “vast intellect” that knew the positions and velocities of all the
01
particles in the universe, and understood all the forces they were subject
02
to, and had sufficient computational power to apply Newton’s laws of mo-
03
tion. In that case, as he put it, “for such an intellect nothing would be
04
uncertain, and the future just like the past would be present before its eyes.”
05
His contemporaries immediately judged “vast intellect” to be too boring,
06
and renamed it Laplace’s Demon.
07
It’s convenient to say “one moment later,” but for Newton and Laplace,
08
and to the best of our current understanding in theoretical physics, the flow
09
of time is continuous rather than discrete. That’s no problem at all; this is a
10
job for calculus, which Newton and Leibniz invented for just this reason.
11
By the “state” of the universe, or any subsystem thereof, we mean the posi-
12
tion and the velocity of every particle within it. The velocity is just the rate
13
of change (the derivative) of the position as time passes; the laws of physics
14
provide us with the acceleration, which is the rate of change of the velocity.
15
Together, you give me the state of the universe at one time, and I can use
16
the laws of physics to integrate forward (or backward) and get the state of
17
the universe at any other time.
18
We’re using the language of classical mechanics— particles, forces— but
19
the idea is much more powerful and general. Laplace introduced the idea of
20
“fields” as a centrally important concept in physics, and the notion became
21
entrenched with the work of Michael Faraday and James Clerk Maxwell on
22
electricity and magnetism in the nineteenth century. Unlike a particle,
23
which has a position in space, a field has a value at every single point in
24
space— that’s just what a field is. But we can treat that field value like a
25
“position,” and its rate of change as a “velocity,” and the whole Laplacian
26
thought experiment goes through undisturbed. The same is true for Ein-
27
stein’s general theory of relativity, or Schrödinger’s equation in quantum
28
mechanics, or modern speculations such as superstring theory. Since the
29
days of Laplace, every serious attempt at understanding the behavior of the
30
universe at a deep level has included the feature that the past and future are
31
determined by the present state of the system. (One possible exception is
32
the collapse of the wave function in quantum mechanics, which we’ll dis-
33
cuss at greater length in chapter 20.)
34
This principle goes by a simple, if potentially misleading, name: conser-
S35
vation of information. Just as conservation of momentum implies that the
N36
33
Big Picture - UK final proofs.indd 33
20/07/2016 10:02:39
T H E B IG PIC T U R E
01
universe can just keep on moving, without any unmoved mover behind the
02
scenes, conservation of information implies that each moment contains
03
precisely the right amount of information to determine every other
04
moment.
05
The term “information” here requires caution, because scientists use the
06
same word to mean different things in different contexts. Sometimes “in-
07
formation” refers to the knowledge you actually have about a state of affairs.
08
Other times, it means the information that is readily accessible, embodied
09
in what the system macroscopically looks like (whether you are looking
10
at it and have the information or not). We are using a third possible defini-
11
tion, what we might call the “microscopic” information: the complete spec-
12
ification of the state of the system, everything you could possibly know
13
about it. When speaking of information being conserved, we mean literally
14
all of it.
15
These two conservation laws, of momentum and information, imply a
16
sea change in our best fundamental ontology. The old Aristotelian view was
17
comfortable and, in a sense, personal. When things moved, there were mov-
18
ers; when things happened, there were causes. The Laplacian view— one
19
that continues to hold in science to this day— is based on patterns, not on
20
natures and purposes. If this certain thing happens, we know this other
21
thing will necessarily follow thereafter, with the sequence described by the
22
laws of physics. Why is it that way? Because that’s the pattern we observe.
23
•
24
25
Laplace’s Demon is a thought experiment, not one we’re going to reproduce
26
in the lab. Realistically, there never will be and never can be an intelligence
27
vast and knowledgeable enough to predict the future of the universe from
28
its present state. If you sit down and think about what such a computer
29
would have to be like, you eventually realize it would essentially need to be
/> 30
as big and powerful as the universe itself. To simulate the entire universe
31
with good accuracy, you basically have to be the universe. So our concern
32
here isn’t one of practical engineering; it’s not going to happen.
33
Our interest is a matter of principle: the fact that the current state of the
34
universe determines its future, not that we can imagine taking advantage
35S
of that fact to make predictions. This feature, determinism, rubs some
36N
34
Big Picture - UK final proofs.indd 34
20/07/2016 10:02:39
W h At dE t E R M I n E S W h A t W I l l h A PPE n ?
people the wrong way. It’s worth taking a careful look at its limitations and
01
prospects.
02
Classical mechanics, the system of equations studied by Newton and
03
Laplace, isn’t perfectly deterministic. There are examples of cases where a
04
unique outcome cannot be predicted from the current state of the system.
05
This doesn’t bother most people, since cases like this are extremely rare—
06
they are essentially infinitely unlikely among the set of all possible things a
07
system could be doing. They are artificial and fun to think about, but not
08
of great import to what happens in the messy world around us.
09
A more popular objection to determinism is the phenomenon of chaos.
10
The ominous name obscures its simple nature: in many kinds of systems,
11
very tiny amounts of imprecision in our knowledge of the initial state of
12
that system can lead to very large variations in where it eventually ends up.
13
As far as determinism is concerned, however, the existence of chaos could
14
not possibly be more irrelevant. Laplace’s point was always that perfect in-
15
formation leads to perfect prediction. Chaos theory says that slightly im-
16
perfect information leads to very imperfect prediction. True, and it doesn’t
17
change the picture the slightest bit. Nobody in their right mind was ever
18
under the impression that we would be able to use Laplace’s reasoning to
19
build a useful prediction- making device; the thought experiment was al-
20
ways a matter of principle, not one of practice.
21
The real issue with classical mechanics is that it’s not how the world
22
works. These days we know better: quantum mechanics, which came along
23
in the early twentieth century, is an entirely different ontology. There are
24
no “positions” and “velocities” in quantum mechanics; there is only “the