Book Read Free

The Big Picture

Page 10

by Carroll, Sean M.


  They emerge as we zoom out from the microscopic level to the level of the

  34

  everyday. To appreciate why we seem to live in a world of causes and pur-

  35S

  poses, while nature deep down is a story of impersonal Laplacian patterns,

  36N

  we need to understand the arrow of time.

  54

  Big Picture - UK final proofs.indd 54

  20/07/2016 10:02:39

  t I M E ’ S A R ROW

  •

  01

  02

  To understand time, it helps to start with space. Here on the surface of the

  03

  Earth, you would be forgiven for thinking that there is an intrinsic differ-

  04

  ence between the directions “up” and “down,” something deeply embedded

  05

  into the fabric of nature. In reality, as far as the laws of physics are con-

  06

  cerned, all directions in space are created equal. If you were an astronaut,

  07

  floating in your spacesuit while you performed an extravehicular activity,

  08

  you wouldn’t notice any difference between one direction in space and any

  09

  other. The reason why there’s a noticeable distinction between up and down

  10

  for us isn’t because of the nature of space; it’s because we live in the vicinity

  11

  of an extremely influential object: the Earth.

  12

  Time works the same way. In our everyday world, time’s arrow is unmis-

  13

  takable, and you would be forgiven for thinking that there is an intrinsic

  14

  difference between past and future. In reality, both directions of time are

  15

  created equal. The reason why there’s a noticeable distinction between past

  16

  and future isn’t because of the nature of time; it’s because we live in the af-

  17

  termath of an extremely influential event: the Big Bang.

  18

  Remember Galileo and conservation of momentum: physics becomes

  19

  simple when we ignore friction and other bothersome influences, and con-

  20

  sider isolated systems. So let’s think of a pendulum rocking back and forth,

  21

  and for convenience let’s imagine that our pendulum is in a sealed vacuum

  22

  chamber, free of air resistance. Now someone records a movie of the pendu-

  23

  lum rocking, and shows it to you. You are not very impressed; you’ve seen

  24

  pendulums before. Then they reveal the surprise: they were actually playing

  25

  the movie backward. You hadn’t noticed because a pendulum rocking back-

  26

  ward in time looks exactly like one rocking forward in time.

  27

  That’s a simple example of a very general principle. For every way that a

  28

  system can evolve forward in time in accordance with the laws of physics,

  29

  there is another allowed evolution that is just “running the system backward

  30

  in time.” There is nothing in the underlying laws that says things can evolve

  31

  in one direction in time but not the other. Physical motions, to the best of our

  32

  understanding, are reversible. Both directions of time are on an equal footing.

  33

  That seems reasonable enough for simple systems: pendulums, planets

  34

  moving around the sun, hockey pucks gliding on frictionless surfaces. But

  S35

  when we think about complicated macroscopic systems, everything in our

  N36

  55

  Big Picture - UK final proofs.indd 55

  20/07/2016 10:02:39

  T H E B IG PIC T U R E

  01

  experience tells us that certain things happen as time moves from past to

  02

  future, but not in the other direction. Eggs break and get scrambled but

  03

  don’t unscramble and unbreak; perfume disperses into a room but never

  04

  retreats back into its bottle; cream mixes into coffee but never spontane-

  05

  ously unmixes. If there is a purported symmetry between past and future,

  06

  why do so many everyday processes occur only forward and never backward?

  07

  Even for these complicated processes, it turns out, there is a time- reversed

  08

  process that is perfectly compatible with the laws of physics. Eggs could un-

  09

  break, perfume could go back into its bottle, cream and coffee could unmix.

  10

  All we have to do is to imagine reversing the trajectory of every single par-

  11

  ticle of which our system (and anything it was interacting with) is made.

  12

  None of these processes violates the laws of physics— it’s just that they are

  13

  extraordinarily unlikely. The real question is not why we never see eggs un-

  14

  breaking toward the future; it’s why we see them unbroken in the past.

  15

  •

  16

  17

  Our basic understanding of these issues was first put together in the nine-

  18

  teenth century by a group of scientists who invented a new field called sta-

  19

  tistical mechanics. One of their leaders was the Austrian physicist Ludwig

  20

  Boltzmann. It was he who took the concept of entropy, which was recog-

  21

  nized as a central idea in the study of thermodynamics and irreversibility,

  22

  and reconciled it with the microscopic world of atoms.

  23

  24

  25

  26

  Ludwig Boltzmann, master of entropy and

  27

  probability, 1844– 1906. (Courtesy of

  28

  Goethe University of Frankfurt)

  29

  30

  31

  32

  33

  34

  35S

  36N

  56

  Big Picture - UK final proofs.indd 56

  20/07/2016 10:02:39

  t I M E ’ S A R ROW

  Before Boltzmann came along, entropy was understood in terms of the

  01

  inefficiency of things like steam engines, which were all the rage at the time.

  02

  Anytime you try to burn fuel to do useful work such as pulling a locomo-

  03

  tive, there is always some waste generated in the form of heat. Entropy can

  04

  be thought of as a way of measuring that inefficiency; the more waste heat

  05

  emitted, the more entropy you’ve created. And no matter what you do, the

  06

  total entropy generated is always a positive number: you can make a refrig-

  07

  erator and cool things down, but only at the cost of expelling even more

  08

  heat out the back. This understanding was codified in the second law of

  09

  thermodynamics: the total entropy of a closed system never decreases, stay-

  10

  ing constant or increasing as time passes.

  11

  Boltzmann and
his colleagues argued that we could understand entropy

  12

  as a feature of how atoms are arranged inside different systems. Rather than

  13

  thinking of heat and entropy as distinct kinds of things, obeying their own

  14

  laws of nature, we can think of them as properties of systems made of at-

  15

  oms, and derive those rules from the Newtonian mechanics that applies to

  16

  everything in the universe. Heat and entropy, in other words, are conve-

  17

  nient ways of talking about atoms.

  18

  Boltzmann’s key insight was that, when we look at an egg or a cup of

  19

  coffee with cream, we don’t actually see the individual atoms and molecules

  20

  of which it is made. What we see are some observable macroscopic features.

  21

  There are many possible arrangements of the atoms that give us exactly the

  22

  same macroscopic appearance. The observable features provide a coarse-

  23

  graining of the precise state of the system.

  24

  Given that, Boltzmann suggested that we could identify the entropy of

  25

  a system with the number of different states that would be macroscopically

  26

  indistinguishable from the state it is actually in. (Technically, it’s the loga-

  27

  rithm of the number of indistinguishable states, but that mathematical

  28

  detail won’t concern us.) A low- entropy configuration is one where rela-

  29

  tively few states would look that way, while a high- entropy one corresponds

  30

  to many possible states. There are many ways to arrange molecules of cream

  31

  and coffee so that they look all mixed together; there are far fewer arrange-

  32

  ments where all of the cream is on the top and all of the coffee on the

  33

  bottom.

  34

  With Boltzmann’s definition in hand, it makes perfect sense that

  S35

  N36

  57

  Big Picture - UK final proofs.indd 57

  20/07/2016 10:02:39

  T H E B IG PIC T U R E

  01

  entropy tends to increase over time. The reason is simple: there are far more

  02

  states with high entropy than states with low entropy. If you start in a low-

  03

  entropy configuration and simply evolve in almost any direction, your en-

  04

  tropy is extraordinarily likely to increase. When the entropy of a system is

  05

  as high as it can get, we say that the system is in equilibrium. In equilib-

  06

  rium, time has no arrow.

  07

  •

  08

  09

  What Boltzmann successfully explained is why, given the entropy of the

  10

  universe today, it’s very likely to be higher- entropy tomorrow. The prob-

  11

  lem is that, because the underlying rules of Newtonian mechanics don’t

  12

  distinguish between past and future, precisely the same analysis should

  13

  predict that the entropy was higher yesterday, as well. Nobody thinks the

  14

  entropy actually was higher in the past, so we have to add something to our

  15

  picture.

  16

  The thing we need to add is an assumption about the initial condi-

  17

  tion of the observable universe, namely, that it was in a very low- entropy

  18

  state. Philosopher David Albert has dubbed this assumption the Past Hy-

  19

  pothesis. With that assumption, and an additional (much weaker) assump-

  20

  tion that the initial conditions weren’t finely tuned to make the entropy

  21

  decrease even further with time, everything falls into place. The reason why

  22

  the entropy was lower yesterday than it is today is simple: because it was

  23

  even lower the day before yesterday. And that’s true because it was even

  24

  lower the day before that. This reasoning proceeds stepwise all the way back

  25

  14 billion years into the past, right to the Big Bang. That may or may not

  26

  have been the absolute beginning of space and time, but it’s certainly the

  27

  beginning of the part of the universe we can observe. The origin of time’s

  28

  arrow, therefore, is ekinological: it arises from a special condition in the

  29

  far past.

  30

  Nobody knows exactly why the early universe had such a low en-

  31

  tropy. It’s one of those features of our world that may have a deeper explana-

  32

  tion we haven’t yet found, or may just be a true fact we need to learn to

  33

  accept.

  34

  What we know is that this initially low entropy is responsible for the

  35S

  “thermodynamic” arrow of time, the one that says entropy was lower

  36N

  58

  Big Picture - UK final proofs.indd 58

  20/07/2016 10:02:40

  t I M E ’ S A R ROW

  toward the past and higher toward the future. Amazingly, it seems that this

  01

  property of entropy is responsible for all of the differences between past and 02

  future that we know about. Memory, aging, cause and effect— all can be

  03

  traced to the second law of thermodynamics and in particular to the fact

  04

  that entropy used to be low in the past.

  05

  06

  07

  08

  09

  10

  11

  12

  13

  14

  15

  16

  17

  18

  19

  20

  21

  22

  23

  24

  25

  26

  27

  28

  29

  30

  31

  32

  33

  34

  S35

  N36

  59

  Big Picture - UK final proofs.indd 59

  20/07/2016 10:02:40

  01

  02

  03

  8

  04

  05

  Memories and Causes

  06

  07

  08

  09

  10

  11

  12

  13

  14

  15

  16

  17

  Every person’s life is caught in the relentless grip of time. We are born

  young, grow older, and die. We experience moments of surprise and

  delight, as well as periods of profound sadness. Our memories are

  cherished records of the past, and our aspirations help us map our future

  18

  plans. If we want to situate our everyday lives as human beings in a natural

  19

  world governed by physical laws, one of our first goals must be to under-

  20

  stand h
ow the flow of time relates to our individual lives.

  21

  You may be willing to believe that something straightforward and me-

  22

  chanical, such as increasing entropy, can be responsible for something

  23

  equally straightforward and mechanical, such as how cream mixes into cof-

  24

  fee. It seems harder to establish that entropy is responsible for all of our

  25

  experience of the flow of time. For one thing, the past and future seem not

  26

  only like different directions but also like completely different kinds of

  27

  things. The past is fixed, our intuition assures us; it has already happened,

  28

  while the future is still unformed and up for grabs. The present moment,

  29

  the now, is what actually exists.

  30

  And then along came Laplace to tell us differently. Information about

  31

  the precise state of the universe is conserved over time; there is no funda-

  32

  mental difference between the past and the future. Nowhere in the laws

  33

  of physics are there labels on different moments of time to indicate “has

  34

  happened yet” and “has not happened yet.” Those laws refer equally well

  35S

  to any moment in time, and they tie all of the moments together in a

  36N

  unique order.

  60

  Big Picture - UK final proofs.indd 60

  20/07/2016 10:02:40

  M E M O R I E S A n d C Au S E S

  We can highlight three ways that the past and future seem radically dif-

  01

  ferent to us:

  02

  03

  • We remember the past, but not the future.

  04

  • Causes precede their effects.

  05

  • We can make choices that affect the future, but not the past.

  06

  07

  All of these features of how time works can ultimately be reconciled

  08

  with the fact that the universe runs according to time- symmetric laws by

  09

  the additional fact that the past had a lower entropy than the future. Let’s

  10

  look at the first two now, postponing for the moment the contentious issues

  11

  of choice and free will. We will get there (I predict).

  12

  13

  •

  14

  There are few more important manifestations of time’s arrow than the phe-

  15

  nomenon of memory. We have impressions in our minds— not always per-

  16

  fectly accurate, but often quite good— of events that have happened in the

  17

  past. We do not, most of us agree, possess analogous impressions of the

  18

  future. The future may be predicted, but it cannot be remembered. This

  19

  imbalance accords quite well with our intuitive feeling that the past and the

 

‹ Prev