Book Read Free

The Big Picture

Page 69

by Carroll, Sean M.


  10

  courage, responsibility, and wisdom. The virtue- ethical versions of Bill and

  11

  Ted would have simply said, “Be excellent.”

  12

  Virtue sounds like a good thing to strive toward. Like consequentialism

  13

  and deontology, it’s an ostensibly attractive moral stance. Sadly, all of these

  14

  attractive approaches end up offering different advice in important cases.

  15

  How should we decide what ethical system to abide by?

  16

  •

  17

  18

  That’s a trick question. Knowing how we “should” decide something re-

  19

  quires that we already have some normative stance, a way of judging differ-

  20

  ent approaches. Let’s instead contemplate how we possibly could go about

  21

  choosing an ethical system at all.

  22

  There are many distinct ways of talking that can each capture some im-

  23

  portant truth about reality. Not all vocabularies capture truth; some are

  24

  simply incorrect. Our goal is to describe the world in useful ways, where

  25

  “useful” is always relative to some stated purpose. In the case of scientific

  26

  theories, “useful” means things like “able to make accurate predictions on

  27

  the basis of minimal input,” and “providing insight into the behavior of a

  28

  system.”

  29

  Morality adds an evaluative component to how we talk about the world.

  30

  This or that person or behavior is bad or good, right or wrong, admirable or

  31

  reprehensible. The criteria for usefulness that help us choose between alter-

  32

  native scientific theories are insufficient when it comes to constructing

  33

  moral principles. The point of moral reasoning is not to help us make pre-

  34

  dictions or provide insight into a person’s behavior.

  35S

  Happily, there are other senses of usefulness besides “helping us fit the

  36N

  408

  Big Picture - UK final proofs.indd 408

  20/07/2016 10:02:56

  Ru l E S A n d C O n S E Q u E n C E S

  data.” Each of us comes into the meta- ethical game with a preexisting set of

  01

  commitments. We have desires, we have feelings, we have things that we

  02

  care about. There are things that naturally attract us, and those that repel

  03

  us. Long before we have ever started thinking reflectively about what our

  04

  ethical stance should be, we already have some kind of nascent moral sen-

  05

  sibility.

  06

  Primatologist Frans de Waal has done studies to probe the origins of

  07

  empathy, fairness, and cooperation in primates. In one famous experiment,

  08

  he and collaborator Sarah Brosnan placed two capuchin monkeys in sepa-

  09

  rate cages, each able to see the other one. When the monkeys performed a

  10

  simple task, they were rewarded with a slice of cucumber. The capuchins

  11

  were quite content with this setup, doing the task over and over, enjoying

  12

  their cucumber. The experimenters then began rewarding one of the mon-

  13

  keys with grapes— a sweeter food than cucumbers, preferable in every way.

  14

  The monkey who didn’t get the grapes, who was previously perfectly con-

  15

  tent with cucumbers, saw what was going on and refused to do the assigned

  16

  task, outraged at the inequity of the new regime. Recent work by Brosnan’s

  17

  group with chimpanzees shows cases where even the chimp who gets the

  18

  grapes is unhappy— their sense of fairness is insulted. Some of our most

  19

  advanced moral commitments have very old evolutionary roots.

  20

  One approach to moral philosophy is to think of it as simply a method

  21

  for making sense of those commitments: making sure that we are true to

  22

  our own self- proclaimed morals, that our justifications for our actions are

  23

  internally consistent, and that we take into account the values of other

  24

  people where appropriate. Rather than fitting data in a scientific sense, we

  25

  can choose our ethical theories by how well they conform to our own exist-

  26

  ing sentiments. A moral framework is “useful” to a poetic naturalist to the

  27

  extent that it reflects and systematizes our moral commitments in a logi-

  28

  cally coherent way.

  29

  A nice feature of this perspective is that it is resolutely practical: it is

  30

  what people actually do when they try to think carefully about morality.

  31

  We have a feeling for what distinguishes right from wrong, and we try to

  32

  make it systematic. We talk to other people to learn how they feel, and take

  33

  that into account when developing the rules for functioning in society.

  34

  It can also be terrifying. You’re telling me that judging right from wrong

  S35

  N36

  409

  Big Picture - UK final proofs.indd 409

  20/07/2016 10:02:56

  T H E B IG PIC T U R E

  01

  is just a matter of our personal feelings and preferences, grounded in noth-

  02

  ing more substantial than our own views, with nothing external to back it

  03

  up? That there are no objectively true moral facts out there in the world?

  04

  Yes. But admitting that morality is constructed, rather than found lying

  05

  on the street, doesn’t mean that there is no such thing as morality. All hell

  06

  has not broken loose.

  07

  •

  08

  09

  The idea that moral guidelines are things invented by human beings based

  10

  on their subjective judgments and beliefs, rather than being grounded in

  11

  anything external, is known as moral constructivism. (When I say “human

  12

  beings” in this context, feel free to substitute “conscious creatures.” I’m not

  13

  trying to discriminate against animals, aliens, or hypothetical artificial in-

  14

  telligences.) Constructivism is a bit different from “relativism.” A moral

  15

  relativist thinks that morality is grounded in the practices of particular

  16

  cultures or individuals, and therefore cannot be judged from outside. Rela-

  17

  tivism is sometimes derided as an overly quietist stance— it doesn’t permit

  18

  legitimate critique of one system by another.

  19

  A moral constructivist, by contrast, acknowledges that morality origi-

  20


  nates in individuals and societies, but accepts that those individuals and

  21

  societies will treat the resulting set of beliefs as “right,” and will judge others

  22

  accordingly. Moral constructivists have no qualms about telling other peo-

  23

  ple that they’re doing the wrong thing. Furthermore, the fact that morals

  24

  are constructed doesn’t mean that they are arbitrary. Ethical systems are

  25

  invented by human beings, but we can all have productive conversations

  26

  about how they could be improved, just as we do with all sorts of things

  27

  that human beings put together.

  28

  Philosopher Sharon Street distinguishes between Kantian constructiv-

  29

  ism, after Immanuel Kant, and Humean constructivism, after David

  30

  Hume. These are two enormously influential thinkers who tended to come

  31

  at problems from very different perspectives, perhaps in part due to their

  32

  differing personalities. Kant, whose strict personal schedule was such that

  33

  residents of Königsberg were known to set their timepieces by his daily

  34

  walks, was part of a long tradition within philosophy of trying make every-

  35S

  thing precise, rigorous, and certain. He would brook no fuzziness in his

  36N

  ethical philosophy. Kant was the deontologist par excellence, and he

  4 10

  Big Picture - UK final proofs.indd 410

  20/07/2016 10:02:56

  Ru l E S A n d C O n S E Q u E n C E S

  founded his views on morality on the categorical imperative: act in such a

  01

  way that your actions could become a universal law. At one point Kant

  02

  seemed to suggest that it would be wrong to lie to a murderer who was at

  03

  your door in order to protect their potential victim, because lying shouldn’t

  04

  be a universal law. Scholars debate whether Kant really thought that it was

  05

  always wrong to lie, but one certainly gets the impression of strict deonto-

  06

  logical rectitude in his thought.

  07

  Hume, meanwhile, was much more at home in a world of skepticism,

  08

  empiricism, and uncertainty. He rejected absolute moral principles, and

  09

  instead of an objective imperative he proudly proclaimed that “Reason is,

  10

  and ought only to be, the slave of the passions.” Reason, that is, can help

  11

  us get what we want; but what we actually do want is defined by our pas-

  12

  sions. Hume was dubious of the natural philosophical tendency to make

  13

  things look just a bit tidier and more exact than they really are.

  14

  A Kantian constructivist accepts that morality is constructed by human

  15

  beings, but believes that every rational person would construct the same

  16

  moral framework, if only they thought about it clearly enough. A Humean

  17

  constructivist takes one more step: morality is constructed, and different

  18

  people might very well construct different moral frameworks for them-

  19

  selves.

  20

  Hume was right. We have no objective guidance on how to distinguish

  21

  right from wrong: not from God, not from nature, not from the pure force

  22

  of reason itself. Alive in the world, individual and contingent, we are bur-

  23

  dened and blessed with all of the talents and inclinations and instincts that

  24

  evolution and our upbringings have bequeathed to us. Those are the raw

  25

  materials from which morals are constructed. Judging what is good and

  26

  what is not is a quintessentially human act, and we need to face up to that

  27

  reality. Morality exists only insofar as we make it so, and other people might

  28

  not pass judgments in the same way that we do.

  29

  30

  31

  32

  33

  34

  S35

  N36

  4 11

  Big Picture - UK final proofs.indd 411

  20/07/2016 10:02:56

  01

  02

  03

  48

  04

  05

  Constructing Goodness

  06

  07

  08

  09

  10

  11

  12

  13

  14

  15

  16

  17

  So then, fellow humans. What kind of morality shall we construct?

  There is no unique answer to this question that applies equally

  well to all persons. But that shouldn’t stop each of us from doing the

  best we can to expand and articulate our own moral impulses into system-

  18

  atic positions.

  19

  Perhaps the most well- known approach to ethics is the consequentialist

  20

  theory of utilitarianism. It imagines that there is some quantifiable aspect

  21

  of human existence, which we can label “utility,” such that increasing it is

  22

  good, decreasing it is bad, and maximizing it would be best of all. The issue

  23

  then becomes how we should define utility. A simple answer is “happiness”

  24

  or “pleasure,” but that can seem a bit superficial and self- centered. Other

  25

  options include “ well- being” and “preference satisfaction.” What matters is

  26

  that there is something we can, in principle, quantify into a number (the

  27

  total amount of utility in the world), and then we can work to make that

  28

  number as big as possible.

  29

  This kind of utilitarianism runs into a number of well- known problems.

  30

  The attractive idea of “quantifying utility” becomes slippery when we try

  31

  to put it into practice. What does it really mean to say that one person has

  32

  0.64 times the well- being of another person? How do we combine well-

  33

  beings— is one person with a utility of 23 better or worse than two people

  34

  with utilities of 18 each? As Derek Parfit has pointed out, if you believe that

  35S

  there is some positive utility in the very existence of a somewhat- satisfied

  36N

  human being, it follows that having a huge number of somewhat- satisfied

  4 12

  Big Picture - UK final proofs.indd 412

  20/07/2016 10:02:56

  C O n S t Ru C t I n g g O O d n E S S

  people has more utility than a relatively smaller number of exquisitely

  01

  happy people. It seems counter to our moral intuitions to think that util-

  02

  ity can be increased just by making more people, even if they are less

  03

  happy ones.

&n
bsp; 04

  Another challenge for utilitarianism was offered by philosopher Robert

  05

  Nozick: the “utility monster,” a hypothetical being with incredibly refined

  06

  sensibilities and an enormous capacity for pleasure. At face value, standard

  07

  utilitarianism might lead us to think that the most moral actions are those

  08

  that keep the utility monster happy, no matter how sad that might make

  09

  the rest of us, because the monster is so incredibly good at being happy.

  10

  Relatedly, we could imagine technology progressing to the point where we

  11

  could place people in machines that would render them immobile, but gen-

  12

  erate in their brains maximal feelings of happiness or preference satisfac-

  13

  tion or a feeling of flourishing or whatever other utility measure we dreamed

  14

  up. Should we work toward a world where everyone is hooked up to such

  15

  machines?

  16

  Finally, the utilitarian calculus tends to not discriminate between util-

  17

  ity of ourselves and those we know and love, versus the utility associated

  18

  with anyone else in the world, or at any other time in history. For the major-

  19

  ity of people in the developed world, utilitarianism would seem to insist

  20

  that we give away a large fraction of our wealth to the cause of ridding the

  21

  world of disease and poverty. That may be a laudable goal, but it reminds us

  22

  that utilitarianism can be an exceedingly demanding taskmaster.

  23

  Utilitarianism doesn’t always do a good job of embodying our moral

  24

  sentiments. There are some things we tend to think are just wrong, even if

  25

  they increase the net happiness of the world, like going around and secretly

  26

  murdering people who are lonely and unhappy. There are other things we

  27

  think are laudable, even if happiness is slightly decreased thereby. Utilitar-

  28

  ians know about such examples, and are able to adjust the rules to make

  29

  them seem less problematic. The basic issue remains: the notion of attach-

  30

  ing a single value of “utility” to every action, and working to increase it, is a

  31

  hard one to pull off in practice.

  32

  Deontological approaches run into their own problems. Psychologists

  33

  have suggested that moral reasoning in general, and deontological reason-

  34

  ing in particular, functions primarily to rationalize opinions that we reach

  S35

  intuitively, rather than leading us to novel moral conclusions. Thalia

  N36

  4 13

 

‹ Prev