Book Read Free

The Big Picture

Page 70

by Carroll, Sean M.


  Big Picture - UK final proofs.indd 413

  20/07/2016 10:02:56

  T H E B IG PIC T U R E

  01

  Wheatley and Jonathan Haidt did a study in which they hypnotized sub-

  02

  jects to feel a strong sense of revulsion at certain innocuous words such as

  03

  “often” and “take.” They were then told simple stories about people who did

  04

  nothing particularly wrong from any reasonable ethical perspective. When

  05

  those stories contained the words they had been primed to react to, not

  06

  only did they feel disgust, but they also judged the actions of the people in

  07

  the stories to be somehow morally wrong. Without being able to articulate

  08

  exactly why, the subjects were convinced that the people being described

  09

  were somehow up to no good.

  10

  Clashes between universal ethical guidelines and our personal moral

  11

  sentiments would be okay, if we thought that our sentiments were merely

  12

  crude approximations to the more transcendent truths captured by those

  13

  guidelines. In that case, so much the worse for our sentiments. But if we

  14

  envision the project of moral philosophy as systematizing and rationalizing

  15

  our sentiments, rather than replacing them with an objective truth, then

  16

  such approaches have a bigger problem. Talking about morality might not

  17

  be so cut-and-dried.

  18

  •

  19

  20

  Deontology and consequentialism, and for that matter virtue ethics and

  21

  various other approaches, all capture something real about our moral im-

  22

  pulses. We want to act in good ways; we want to make the world a better

  23

  place; we want to be good people. But we also want to make sense and be

  24

  internally consistent. That’s hard to do while accepting all of these compet-

  25

  ing impulses at once. In practice, moral philosophies tend to pick one ap-

  26

  proach and apply it universally. And as a result of that, we often end up with

  27

  conclusions that don’t sit easily with the premises we started with.

  28

  It may be that the kind of moral code that fits most people the best isn’t

  29

  based on a strict construal of any one approach, but takes bits and pieces

  30

  from all of them. Consider a kind of “soft consequentialism,” where the

  31

  value of actions depends on their consequences, but also to some degree on

  32

  the actions themselves. Or imagine that we allow ourselves to place greater

  33

  value on helping people we know and care about than on helping those

  34

  farther away. These need not be seen as “mistakes”; they could be part of a

  35S

  complex and multifaceted, but internally consistent, way of realizing our

  36N

  basic moral inclinations.

  4 14

  Big Picture - UK final proofs.indd 414

  20/07/2016 10:02:56

  C O n S t Ru C t I n g g O O d n E S S

  Or— someone could be a perfectly moral person who based their behav-

  01

  ior on a small set of absolute rules, whether it was a particular flavor of

  02

  utilitarianism or adherence to the categorical imperative, because that’s

  03

  what they felt was the best fit to their inner convictions. And that’s okay.

  04

  The moral systems we construct serve our own purposes.

  05

  Abraham was commanded by God to do something horrible. It was a

  06

  great challenge to his humanity, but given his view of the world, the correct

  07

  course of behavior was clear: if you are certain that God is telling you to do

  08

  something, that’s what you do. Poetic naturalism refuses to offer us the

  09

  consolation of objective moral certainty. There is no “right” answer to the

  10

  trolley problem. How you should act depends on who you are.

  11

  12

  •

  13

  Ay, there’s the rub. We want there to be objective solutions to our dilem-

  14

  mas, as surely as there are theorems in mathematics or experimental discov-

  15

  eries in science. As good Bayesians, aware of our bias toward claims that we

  16

  would like to be true, this desire should make us especially skeptical of at-

  17

  tempts to found objective morality on a natural basis. But as human beings,

  18

  it often makes us all too readily accepting.

  19

  The worry is that, if morality is constructed, everyone will construct

  20

  whatever they like, and what they like won’t actually be very good. It’s an

  21

  ancient concern, usually directed at believers in the wrong religion or no

  22

  religion at all. Tertullian, an early Christian thinker from Africa who is

  23

  recognized as a Father of the Church, explained that an atomist like the

  24

  Greek philosopher Epicurus couldn’t be a good person. The problem is that

  25

  for Epicurus, life ends at death, so suffering is ephemeral, while Christians

  26

  believe in hell, so for them it’s forever. Why should anyone strive to be good

  27

  if there were no promise of an eternal reward, nor threat of eternal pun-

  28

  ishment?

  29

  30

  Think of these things, too, in the light of the brevity of any

  31

  punishment you can inflict— never to last longer than till death.

  32

  On this ground Epicurus makes light of all suffering and pain,

  33

  maintaining that if it is small, it is contemptible; and if it is

  34

  great, it is not long- continued. No doubt about it, we, who re-

  S35

  ceive our awards under the judgment of an all- seeing God, and

  N36

  4 15

  Big Picture - UK final proofs.indd 415

  20/07/2016 10:02:56

  T H E B IG PIC T U R E

  01

  who look forward to eternal punishment from Him for sin,—

  02

  we alone make real effort to attain a blameless life.

  03

  04

  The modern version of this worry is that, if we were to accept that mo-

  05

  rality is constructed, individuals will run around giving in to their worst

  06

  instincts, and we would have no basis on which to condemn obviously bad

  07

  things like the Holocaust. After all, somebody thought it was a good idea,

  08

  and without objective guidance how can we say they were wrong?

  09

  The constructivist answers that just because moral rules are invented by

  10

&nb
sp; human beings, that doesn’t make them any less real. The rules of basketball

  11

  are also invented by human beings, but once invented they really exist.

  12

  People even argue over what the “right” rules should be. When James Nai-

  13

  smith invented the game, the ball was thrown into peach baskets, and had

  14

  to be retrieved by hand each time a shot was made. Only later did they real-

  15

  ize that the game would be improved by replacing the basket with a hoop.

  16

  That made the game “better,” in the sense that it did a better job at fulfilling

  17

  its purpose as a game. The rules of basketball aren’t objectively defined,

  18

  waiting out there in the universe to be discovered; but they aren’t arbitrary

  19

  either. Morality is like that: we invent the rules, but we invent them for

  20

  sensible purposes.

  21

  The problem arises when we imagine people whose purposes— whose

  22

  foundational moral sentiments and commitments— are radically at odds

  23

  with ours. What are we to do with someone who just wants to play hockey

  24

  rather than basketball? In sports we might seek out different people to play

  25

  with, but when it comes to morality we all have to live together here on this

  26

  Earth.

  27

  We might hope, in the spirit of Kant, that simple logical requirements

  28

  of internal consistency would lead every rational person to construct the

  29

  same moral rules, even starting from slightly different initial feelings. But

  30

  that hope seems slim indeed. Sharon Street imagines an “internally coher-

  31

  ent Caligula,” who takes pleasure in the suffering of others. Such a monster

  32

  need not be illogical or inconsistent; they just have fundamental attitudes

  33

  with which we cannot agree. We’re not going to reason them out of their

  34

  stance. If they act on their impulses in ways that bring harm to others, we

  35S

  should respond as we actually do in the real world: by preventing them

  36N

  from doing so. When criminals refuse to be deterred, we put them in jail.

  4 16

  Big Picture - UK final proofs.indd 416

  20/07/2016 10:02:56

  C O n S t Ru C t I n g g O O d n E S S

  As a practical matter, the worries associated with constructivism are

  01

  somewhat overblown. Most people, in most circumstances, want to think

  02

  of themselves as doing good rather than evil. It’s not clear what operational

  03

  benefit would be gained by establishing morality as an objective set of facts.

  04

  Presumably we envision a person or group who was relatively rational, but

  05

  disagreed with us about morality, whom we could sit down with over coffee

  06

  and convince of the mistake they were making. In practice the recom-

  07

  mended strategy for a constructivist would be essentially the same: sitting

  08

  down and talking with the person, appealing to our common moral beliefs,

  09

  attempting to work out a mutually reasonable solution. Moral progress is

  10

  possible because most people share many moral sentiments; if they don’t,

  11

  reasoning with them wouldn’t help much no matter what.

  12

  If instead the worry is that we can’t justify stepping in to prevent im-

  13

  moral actions, that simply isn’t an issue for constructivists. If, upon rational

  14

  reflection, we decide that something is deeply wrong, there is no reason why

  15

  we cannot work to prevent it from happening, regardless of whether our

  16

  decision is based on external criteria or our own inner convictions. Again,

  17

  this is no more or less than what really happens in the world.

  18

  Deciding how to be good isn’t like solving a math puzzle, or discovering

  19

  a new fossil. It’s like going out to dinner with a group of friends. We think

  20

  about what we want for our individual selves, talk to others about their

  21

  desires and how we can work together, and reason about how to make it

  22

  happen. The group may include both vegetarians and omnivores, but with

  23

  a good- faith effort there’s no reason everyone can’t be satisfied.

  24

  25

  •

  26

  I once found myself on a panel at a large interdisciplinary meeting, attended

  27

  by people from the worlds of business, science, politics, and the arts. The

  28

  purpose of the panel was to discuss morality in the modern world. I had

  29

  been invited not because of any particular expertise in moral matters, but

  30

  it was a conference where most of the participants tended to be religious,

  31

  and I was known not to be; my job was to be the token atheist. And when

  32

  the time came for me to speak, the single question I was asked was: “What

  33

  do you think would be the best argument against your atheism?” The other

  34

  panelists, by contrast, were offered a chance to say something positive and

  S35

  constructive about their moral positions. There is a lurking suspicion in

  N36

  4 17

  Big Picture - UK final proofs.indd 417

  20/07/2016 10:02:56

  T H E B IG PIC T U R E

  01

  many corners that naturalists are objects of curiosity but not to be taken

  02

  seriously when it comes to talking about values.

  03

  Here in the early years of the twenty- first century, a majority of philoso-

  04

  phers and scientists are naturalists. But in the public sphere, at least in the

  05

  United States, on questions of morality and meaning, religion and spiritu-

  06

  ality are given a preeminent place. Our values have not yet caught up to our

  07

  best ontology.

  08

  They had better start catching up. When it comes to deciding how to

  09

  live, we’re like that first fish flapping up onto land: faced with a new world

  10

  of challenges and opportunities, and not yet really adapted to it. Technol-

  11

  ogy has given us enormous power to shape our world for better or for worse,

  12

  and by any reasonable estimate we are only at the very beginning of the

  13

  associated changes. We’re going to be faced with the kinds of moral ques-

  14

  tions that our ancestors could not possibly have contemplated, from

  15

  human- machine interfacing to the exploration of new planets. Engineers

  16

  working on self- dr
iving cars have already begun to realize that the software

  17

  is going to have to be programmed to solve certain kinds of trolley problems.

  18

  Poetic naturalism doesn’t tell us how to behave, but it warns us away

  19

  from the false complacency associated with the conviction that our morals

  20

  are objectively the best. Our lives are changing in unpredictable ways; we

  21

  need to be able to make judgments with clear eyes and an accurate picture

  22

  of how the world operates. We don’t need an immovable place to stand; we

  23

  need to make our peace with a universe that doesn’t care what we do, and

  24

  take pride in the fact that we care anyway.

  25

  26

  27

  28

  29

  30

  31

  32

  33

  34

  35S

  36N

  4 18

  Big Picture - UK final proofs.indd 418

  20/07/2016 10:02:56

  01

  02

  49

  03

  04

  Listening to the World

  05

  06

  07

  08

  09

  10

  11

  12

  t

  13

  he idea of “Ten Commandments” is a deeply compelling one. It

  14

  combines two impulses that are ingrained in our nature as human

  15

  beings: making lists of ten things, and telling other people how to

  16

  behave.

  17

  The most famous such list is found in the Hebrew Bible. It’s a compila-

  18

  tion of instructions for the Israelite people, handed from God to Moses

  19

  atop Mount Sinai. The commandments are found twice, once in Exodus

  20

  and once in Deuteronomy. In neither case is the list numbered, and the

  21

  wording between the two appearances is slightly different. As a result, there

  22

  is no agreement on what “The Ten Commandments” actually are. Jews,

  23

  Orthodox Christians, Catholics, and different Protestant denominations

  24

  quote slightly different lists. Lutherans, for example, don’t include the tra-

  25

  ditional prohibition against graven images, and split the coveting of thy

  26

  neighbor’s house into a commandment all its own, rather than grouping it

  27

  with the coveting of thy neighbor’s wife and thy neighbor’s servants. What

  28

  matters is that there are ten of them.

  29

  Inevitably, schools of thought outside the traditional religious main-

  30

  stream have borrowed the Ten Commandments idea, and proposed their

 

‹ Prev