Selected Prose of T. S. Eliot
Page 39
literature. It is from the second point of view that my objections
to Milton are made : it is from this point of view that we can go so
far as to say that, although his work realizes superbly one important
element in poetry, he may still be considered as having done damage to the English language from which it has not wholly recovered.
264
from M I LTON I I
. . .
The reproach against Milton, that his technical influence has
been bad, appears to have been made by no one more positively
than by myself. I find myself saying, as recently as 1936, that this
charge against Milton
appears a good deal more serious if we affirm that Milton's poetry
could only be an influence for the worse, upon any poet whatever. It
is more serious, also, if we affirm that Milton's bad influence may be
traced much farther than the eighteenth century, and much farther
than upon bad poets : if we say that it was an influence against which
we still have to struggle.
In writing these sentences I failed to draw a threefold distinction, which now seems to me of some importance. There are three separate assertions implied. The first is, that an influence has been
bad in the past : this is to assert that good poets, in the eighteenth
or nineteenth century, would have written better if they had not
submitted themselves to the influence of Milton. The second assertion is, that the contemporary situation is such that Milton is a master whom we should avoid. The third is, that the influence of
Milton, or of any particular poet, can be always bad, and that we
can predict that wherever it is found at any time in the future,
however remote, it will be a bad influence. Now, the first and third
of these assertions I am no longer prepared to make, because,
detac�ed from the second, they do not appear to me to have any
meamng.
For the first, when we consider one great poet of the past, and
one or more other poets, upon whom we say he has exerted a bad
influence, we must admit that the responsibility, if there be any,
is rather with the poets who were influenced than with the poet
whose work exerted the influence. We can, of course, show that
certain tricks or mannerisms which the imitators display are due
to conscious or unconscious imitation and emulation, but that is
a reproach against their injudicious choice of a model and not
against their model itself. And we can never prove that any
particular poet would have written better poetry if he had escaped
265
APPREC I A T I ONS O F I N D I V IDUAL AUTHORS
1 9 3 0- 1 96 5
•
that influence. Even i f w e ass�rt, what can only b e a matter of
faith, that Keats would have written a very great epic poem if
Milton had not preceded him, is· it sensible to pine for an unwritten masterpiece, in exchange for one which we possess and acknowledge ? And as for the remote future, what can we affirm
about the poetry that will be written then, except that we should
probably be unable to understand or to enjoy it, and that therefore we can hold no opinion as to what 'good' and 'bad' influences will mean in that future ? The only relation in which the question
of influence, good and bad, is significant, is the relation to the
immediate future. With that question I shall engage at the end. I
wish first to mention another reproach against Milton, that represented by the phrase 'dissociation of sensibility'.
I remarked many years ago, in an essay on Dryden, that :
In the seventeenth century a dissociation of sensibility set in, from
which we have never recovered ; and this dissociation, as is natural, was
due to the influence of the two most powerful poets of the century,
Milton and Dryden.
The longer passage from which this sentence is taken is quoted
by Dr. Tillyard in his Milton. Dr. Tillyard makes the following
comment :
Speaking only of what in this passage concerns Milton, I would say
that there is here a mixture of truth and falsehood. Some sort of
dissociation of sensibility in Milton, not necessarily undesirable, has to
be admitted ; but that he was responsible for any such dissociation in
others (at least till this general dissociation had inevitably set in) is
untrue.
I believe that the general affirmation represented by the phrase
'dissociation of sensibility' (one of the two or three phrases of my
coinage - like 'objective correlative' - which have had a success
in the world astonishing to their author) retains some validity ;
but I now incline to agree with Dr. Tillyard that to lay the burden
on the shoulders of Milton and Dryden was a mistake. If such a
dissociation did take place, I suspect that the causes are too complex and too profound to justify our accounting for the change in terms of literary criticism. All we can say is, that something like
this did happen ; that it had something to do with the Civil War ;
that it would even be unwise to say it was caused by the Civil War,
but that it is a consequence of the same causes which brought
about the Civil War ; that we must seek the causes in Europe, not
in England alone ; and for what these causes were, we may dig and
dig until we get to a depth at which words and concepts fail us.
Before proceeding to take up the case against Milton, as it
266
M I LTON I I
stood for poets twenty-five years ago - the second, and only
significant meaning of 'bad influence' - I think it would be best
to consider what permanent strictures of reproof may be drawn :
those censures which, when we make them, we must assume to be
made by enduring laws of taste. The essence of the permanent
censure of Milton is, I believe, to be found in Johnson's essay.
This is not the place in which to examine certain particular and
erroneous judgments of Johnson ; to explain his condemnation of
Comus and Samson as the application of dramatic canons which to
us seem inapplicable ; or to condone his dismissal of the versification of Lycidas by the specialization, rather than the absence, of his sense of rhythm. Johnson's most important censure of Milton
is contained in three paragraphs, which I must ask leave to quote
in full.
Throughout all his greater works [says Johnson] there prevails an
uniform peculiarity of diction, a mode and cast of expression which
bears little resemblance to that of any former writer ; and which is so
far removed from common use, that an unlearned reader, when he first
opens the book, finds himself surprised by a new language.
This novelty has been, by those who can find nothing wrong with
Milton, imputed to his laborious endeavours after words suited to the
grandeur of his ideas. Our latzguage, says Addison, sunk under him. But
the truth is, that both in prose and in verse, he had formed his style by
a perverse and pedantic principle. He was desirous to use English
words with a foreign idiom. This in all his prose is discovered and
condemned ; for there judgment operates freely, neither softened by the
beauty, nor awed by the dignity of his thoughts ; but such is the power
of his poetry, that his call is obeyed without resis
tance, the reader feels
himself in captivity to a higher and nobler mind, and criticism sinks in
admiration.
Milton's style was not modified by his subject ; what is shown with
greater extent in Paradise Lost may be found in Comus. One source of
his peculiarity was his familiarity with the Tuscan poets ; the disposition of his words is, I think, frequently Italian ; perhaps sometimes combined with other tongues. Of him at last, may be said what Jonson
said of Spenser, that he TPT'ote no language, but has formed what Butler
called a Babylonish dialect, in itself harsh and barbarous, but m::de by
exalted genius and extensive learning the vehicle of so much instruction
and so much pleasure, that, like other lovers, we find grace in its
deformity.
This criticism seems to me substantially true : indeed, unless we
accept it, I do not think we are in the way to appreciate the peculiar
greatness of Milton. His style is not a classic style, in that it is not
the elevation of a common style, by the final touch of genius, to
267
APPREC I A T I ONS OF I N D I V I DUAL AUTHORS
1 9 3 0- 1 9 6 5
•
greatness. It is, from the foundation, and in every particular, a
personal style, not based upon common speech, or common prose,
or direct communication of meaning. Of some great poetry one
has difficulty in pronouncing just what it is, what infinitesimal
touch, that has made all the difference from a plain statement
which anyone could make ; the slight transformation which, while
it leaves a plain statement a plain statement, has always the
maximal, never the minimal, alteration of ordinary language.
Every distortion of construction, the foreign idiom, the use of a
word in a foreign way or with the meaning of the foreign word
from which it is derived rather than the accepted meaning in
English, every idiosyncrasy is a particular act of violence which
Milton has been the first to commit. There is no cliche, no poetic
diction in the derogatory sense, but a perpetual sequence of
original acts of lawlessness. Of all modern writers of verse, the
nearest analogy seems to me to be Mallarme, a much smaller poet,
though still a great one. The personalities, the poetic theories of
the two men could not have been more different ; but in respect of
the violence which they could do to language, and justify, there is
a remote similarity. Milton's poetry is poetry at the farthest
possible remove from prose ; his prose seems to me too near to
half-formed poetry to be a good prose.
To say that the work of a poet is at the farthest possible remove
from prose would once have struck me as condemnatory : it now
seems to me simply, when we have to do with a Milton, the precision of its peculiar greatness. As a poet, Milton seems to me probably the greatest of all eccentrics. His work illustrates no
general principles of good writing ; the only principles of writing
that it illustrates are such as are valid only for Milton himself to
observe. There are two kinds of poet who can ordinarily be of use
to other poets. There are those who suggest, to one or another of
their successors, something which they have not done themselves,
or who provoke a different way of doing the same thing : these are
likely to be not the greatest, but smaller, imperfect poets with
whom later poets discover an affinity. And there are the great
poets from whom we can learn negative rules : no poet can teach
another to write well, but some great poets can teach others some
of the things to avoid. They teach us what to avoid, by showing us
what great poetry can do without - how bare it can be. Of these
are Dante and Racine. But if we are ever to make use of Milton
we must do so in quite a different way. Even a small poet can
learn something from the study of Dante, or from the study of
Chaucer : we must perhaps wait for a great poet before we find
one who can profit from the study of Milton.
I repeat that the remoteness of Milton's verse from ordinary
268
M I LTON I I
speech, his invention o f his own poetic language, seems to me one
of the marks of his greatness. Other marks are his sense of structure, both in the general design of Paradise Lost and Samson, and in his syntax ; and finally, and not least, his inerrancy, conscious
or unconscious, in writing so as to make the best display of his
talents, and the best concealment of his weaknesses.
The appropriateness of the subject of Samson is too obvious to
expatiate upon : it was probably the one dramatic story out of
which Milton could have made a masterpiece. But the complete
suitability of Paradise Lost has not, I think, been so often remarked. It was surely an intuitive perception of what he could not do, that arrested Milton's project of an epic on King Arthur. For
one thing, he had little interest in, or understanding of, individual
human beings. In Paradise Lost he was not called upon for any of
that understanding which comes from an affectionate observation
of men and women. But such an interest in human beings was not
required - indeed its absence was a necessary condition - for the
creation of his figures of Adam and Eve. These are not a man and
woman such as any we know : if they were, they would not be
Adam and Eve. They are the original Man and Woman, not types,
but prototypes. They have the general characteristics of men and
women, such that we can recognize, in the temptation and the fall,
the first motions of the faults and virtues, the abjection and the
nobility, of all their descendants. They have ordinary humanity
to the right degree, and yet are not, and should not be, ordinary
mortals. Were they more particularized they would be false, and
if Milton had been more interested in humanity, he could not
have created them. Other critics have remarked upon the exactness, without defect or exaggeration, with which Moloch, Belial, and Mammon, in the second book, speak according to the particular sin which each represents. It would not be suitable that the infernal powers should have, in the human sense, characters,
for a character is always mixed ; but in the hands of an inferior
manipulator, they might easily have been reduced to humours.
The appropriateness of the material of Paradise Lost to the
genius and the limitations of Milton, is still more evident when we
consider the visual imagery. I have already remarked, in a paper
written some years ago, on Milton's weakness of visual observation, a weakness which I think was always present - the effect of his blindness may have been rather to strengthen the compensatory qualities than to increase a fault which was already present.
Mr. Wilson Knight, who has devoted close study to recurrent
imagery in poetry, has called attention to Milton's propensity
towards images of engineering and mechanics ; to me it seems that
Milton is at his best in imagery suggestive of vast size, limitless
269
APPRECI A T I O N S OF I N D I V I DU A L AUTHORS
1 9 3 0- 1 9 6 5
·
space, abysmal depth, and li�t and darkness. No theme and no
setting, other than that which he chose in Paradis
e Lost, could
have given him such scope for t}le kind of imagery in which he
excelled, or made less demand ·upon those powers of visual imagination which were in him defective.
Most of the absurdities and inconsistencies to which Johnson
calls attention, and which, so far as they can justly be isolated in
this way, he properly condemns, will I think appear in a more
correct proportion if we consider them in relation to this general
judgment. I do not think that we should attempt to see very clearly
any scene that Milton depicts : it should be accepted as a shifting
phantasmagory. To complain, because we first find the arch-fiend
'chain'd on the burning lake', and in a minute or two see him
making his way to the shore, is to expect a kind of consistency
which the world to which Milton has introduced us does not
reqmre.
This limitation of visual power, like Milton's limited interest in
human beings, turns out to be not merely a negligible defect, but
a positive virtue, when we visit Adam and Eve in Eden. Just as a
higher degree of characterization of Adam and Eve would have
been unsuitable, so a more vivid picture of the earthly Paradise
would have been less paradisiacal. For a greater definiteness, a
more detailed account of flora and fauna, could only have assimilated Eden to the landscapes of earth with which we are familiar.
As it is, the impression of Eden which we retain, is the most suitable, and is that which Milton was most qualified to give : the impression of light a daylight and a starlight, a light of dawn
-
and of dusk, the light which, remembered by a man in his blindn��s, has a supernatural glory unexperienced by men of normal VISIOn.
We must, then, in reading Paradise Lost, not expect to see
clearly ; our sense of sight must be blurred, so that our hearing
may become more acute. Paradise Lost, like Finnegans Wake (for
I can think of no work which provides a more interesting parallel :
two books by great blind musicians, each writing a language of
his own based upon English) makes this peculiar demand for a
readjustment of the reader's mode of apprehension. The emphasis
is on the sound, not the vision, upon the word, not the idea ; and
in the end it is the unique versification that is the most certain