Book Read Free

Revolution and the Republic

Page 41

by Jeremy Jennings


  It is thus interesting to note that L’Ancien Régime et la Révolution, first published in

  1856, can be read as a sustained comparison between England and France and one

  where England was consistently regarded as the preferred example. In stark contrast

  to the relentless growth and centralization of the French state, Tocqueville argued,

  England was a country where judicial guarantees and local independence had been

  preserved. After the rise of Louis Napoleon and the advent of the Second Empire, in

  other words, England again appeared to be the location of political liberty.

  Nor was Tocqueville to be the only liberal to share in this rekindling of enthusiasm

  for England and the wisdom of its constitutional principles. Michel Chevalier, in a

  review of Walter Bagehot’s The English Constitution, praised the English constitution

  as being ‘among the most beautiful products of our civilization’ and then proceeded

  to offer the standard panegyric in praise of English self-government and liberty.209

  More enthusiastic still was the account provided by Charles de Montalembert, one

  of the leading proponents of liberal Catholicism, in his De l’Avenir politique de

  l’Angleterre,210 a work greatly admired by Tocqueville. Montalembert’s central claim

  was that England, almost alone, seemed able to hold back the twin perils of autocracy

  and anarchy. England, he remarked, had ‘the sole durable, intelligent aristocracy that

  exists in Europe’.211 These comments were all the more remarkable given that at

  this moment England was the subject of sustained criticism from all sides. As a result of

  the military and administrative disasters of the Crimean War, Montalembert acknow-

  ledged, a growing number of people were predicting the collapse of England.212

  Yet the most extended and detailed recommendation of the English model can

  be found in Anatole Prévost-Paradol’s La France nouvelle, first published in 1868.

  The title alone gave some indication of Prévost-Paradol’s purpose. His subject was

  ‘the political and administrative reform of France’. To secure that end he sketched

  out a system of government that, in its adumbration of all the essential elements

  of the English constitution, represented the culmination of liberal admiration of

  England. Recommended to his French readers were the separation of powers,

  freedom of the press, the jury system, religious toleration, the preservation of

  local liberties and self-government, a two-chamber system (one hereditary, one

  popular), a system of election that would protect minorities as well as recognize

  208 See Aurelian Craiutu and Jeremy Jennings (eds.), Tocqueville on America after 1840: Letters and

  Other Writings (Cambridge, 2009), 183.

  209 ‘La Constitution de l’Angleterre’, Revue des Deux Mondes, 72 (1867), 529–55.

  210 Charles de Montalembert, De l’Avenir politique de l’Angleterre (1860).

  211 Ibid. 97.

  212 See Charles de Rémusat, ‘La Réforme administrative en Angleterre’, Revue des Deux Mondes,

  12 (1855), 241–84.

  Commerce, Usurpation, and Democracy

  191

  talent and ability, ministerial responsibility and cabinet government, and finally a

  constitutional monarch or head of state armed with the power of dissolution. All of

  these were wheeled out one after the other by way of example and contrasted with

  France’s ‘inexperience of parliamentary practices and lack of familiarity with free

  institutions’. But why did Prévost-Paradol imagine that it was necessary to con-

  template such extensive borrowing?

  The answer was contained in the opening discussion of the nature of democracy.

  If it was true, Prévost-Paradol argued, that all societies were moving towards

  democracy, sooner or later they would aspire to have a democratic political system.

  The natural tendency of all such democratic government was to become corrupt

  and to dissolve into anarchy. The disorder within the State would then become

  such that, out of this intolerable situation, would arise ‘democratic despotism’.

  This, in turn, would justify its existence on the grounds that it could ‘assure the

  maintenance of public order and the salvation of society’. Its goal would become

  that of satisfying the demands of the ‘multitude’ for ‘well-being’ and this would be

  attained by sacrificing individual liberties. ‘Thus charged’, Prévost-Paradol wrote,

  with an unlimited mandate and invested, through the laws, with an immense power over

  men and by the popular imagination with an immense power over things, with the aim

  of ensuring the general happiness democratic despotism advances with an irresistible

  force and an insolent pomp, until the inevitable day when, stunned by its own success

  and seized by a form of drunkenness, it comes up against some pathetic obstacle and

  collapses into a form of anarchy worse than that which served as its cradle.213

  With such unremitting pessimism did one of France’s leading liberals contemplate

  the advent of democracy over thirty years after the publication of the first volume of

  De la Démocratie en Amérique.

  Even in the difficult political climate of the 1860s the voice of liberalism could

  still be heard (and often with great vigour). A work such as Odilon Barrot’s De la

  Centralisation et de ses effets, published in 1861, continued to voice traditional

  liberal concerns about an overmighty state and did so by making explicit reference

  to the ideas of Montesquieu. Similar claims against administrative centralization

  were made by Jules Simon, through an immensely sophisticated argument ground-

  ed upon philosophical first principles and a close analysis of French history. Simon’s

  ambition was to restate the conditions and guarantees of political liberty. Intrigu-

  ingly, Simon contended that the Revolution of 1789 had ‘slipped’ rapidly down the

  slope from ‘wise liberty to excessive liberty’, leading to anarchy and despotism.214

  Most impressive of all was Édouard Laboulaye.215 Not only did he edit and

  republish Constant’s major political writings,216 but he reworked the latter’s

  213 Prévost-Paradol, La France nouvelle (1869), 35–6.

  214 Jules Simon, La Liberté (1859). Simon’s criticisms of centralization drew upon a reading

  of Tocqueville.

  215 See Walter D. Gray, Interpreting American Democracy in France: The Career of Edouard

  Laboulaye, 1811–1883 (Newark, NJ, 1994).

  216 Cours de politique constitutionnelle ou collection des ouvrages publiés sur le gouvernement représentatif

  par Benjamin Constant avec une introduction et note par M. Edouard Laboulaye, 2 vols. (1861).

  192

  Commerce, Usurpation, and Democracy

  distinction between ancient and modern liberty as part of a self-conscious liberal

  tradition that ran from the monarchiens to Tocqueville.217 In the same year that he

  published L’Etat et ses limites, he also published Le Parti liberal, son programme, son

  avenir, and in so doing set out a liberal agenda for a ‘new generation’ freed from the

  ‘illusions and disappointments’ of the past. His text, he announced, was a

  ‘programme for modern democracy’. Accordingly, Laboulaye defended an exten-

  sive array of what he termed ‘social liberties’, beginning with religious liberty (he

 
; advocated the separation of Church and State), liberty of education, and liberty of

  association, combined with the traditional liberal advocacy of municipal liberty.

  With regard to political liberties, Laboulaye recommended not only freedom of the

  press and an independent judiciary but also ‘national representation’ and ‘an

  extended electoral suffrage’. In the aftermath of the elections of 1863, in which

  liberal opinion appeared to be making advances, it seemed to Laboulaye that it was

  in this direction that France was moving.

  V

  If Prévost-Paradol’s La France nouvelle remains known today it is for two reasons.

  The first is that its author, having thrown in his lot with the liberal Empire of Émile

  Ollivier, committed suicide upon his arrival in New York when he heard of the

  imminent outbreak of the Franco-Prussian war. The second is because the book

  contained the following memorable phrase: ‘The French Revolution established

  a society: it still seeks a government.’218 This, in a very real sense, had been the

  refrain of all liberals throughout the nineteenth century. They had sought to bring

  the political turmoil of the Revolution to an end and to build a regime based upon

  order, property, and the recognition of individual liberties. They were repeatedly

  thwarted in these ends, in part due to their own political ineptitude, but also by the

  combined forces of Bonapartism, republicanism, and monarchical reaction. As

  Pierre Rosanvallon has commented, ‘[t]he central question in France has always

  been that of knowing who is the holder of power rather than that of specifying what

  form this power should take’.219 If this is true, then the liberals were arguably

  asking the wrong questions and providing answers that few people wished to hear.

  Rosanvallon similarly speaks of ‘the want of moderation which characterizes

  a culture in which the sense of compromise and of concession is weak’.220 Again,

  the liberal enthusiasm for a juste milieu, for constructing a political balance that

  would embrace all the social forces that made up the new France, held little appeal

  in such an environment. A harsher response is to suggest, as Sudhir Hazareesingh

  has done, that the political project of liberalism was ‘inadequately attuned to the

  217 Edouard Laboulaye, ‘La Liberté antique et la Liberté moderne’ and ‘Alexis de Tocqueville’ in

  L’Etat et ses limites (1863), 103–201.

  218 Prévost-Paradol, La France nouvelle, 296.

  219 Rosanvallon, La Monarchie impossible (1994), 170.

  220 Ibid. 179.

  Commerce, Usurpation, and Democracy

  193

  imperatives of its time’. On this account, the rising democratic demands associated

  with radical republicanism ‘triggered a number of recurring tensions among differ-

  ent liberal goals and principles’. Appeals to consensus failed to convince a public

  opinion that was increasingly polarized.221 More tellingly still, Hazareesingh’s

  contention is that the liberal conception of citizenship was ‘riddled with contra-

  dictions’. The advocacy of communal liberties and autonomous citizens looked

  flimsy and insubstantial when placed by the side of ‘an entrenched suspicion of

  universal suffrage, a sense of confidence in the natural superiority of bourgeois rule,

  and a defence of traditional social institutions’.222

  This analysis undoubtedly contains a grain of truth. As we have seen, in the

  nineteenth century liberalism was not democratic. But nor, for that matter, was

  democracy liberal. And this should not be forgotten. To their immense credit, the

  French liberals, probably before anyone else, realized that democracy could spawn

  an entirely new type of despotism. In its mild form, it could take the shape of

  Tocqueville’s tyranny of the majority; less benignly, it could appear as the Bona-

  partist usurpation described by Constant or the ‘democratic despotism’ of the

  Second Empire described by Prévost-Paradol. In either shape, the liberals were

  surely right to discern the danger, and right too to seek to find ways to alleviate it.

  The irony is that, for all their political failure to carry the electorate with them, it

  can plausibly be argued that liberal opinion had a deep impact upon the formation

  of the Third Republic in its early years. This claim would not receive universal

  assent. However, it can be given substance in two ways. The first is to follow Pierre

  Rosanvallon and to acknowledge that the pères fondateurs of the Third Republic

  were deeply imbued with the liberal suspicion of a wayward universal suffrage.

  A ‘democratic elitism’, Rosanvallon claims, was ‘one of the central elements of

  their political vision’. He quotes Jules Grévy, for example, to the effect that the

  purpose of representative government was ‘to substitute the ignorance of the

  greatest number by the enlightenment of the elite of our citizens’. The castigation

  of ‘parliamentary anarchy’ by Grévy and many others, Rosanvallon argues, reflected

  the ‘secret’ desire to see a parliamentary assembly peopled with only ‘wise men’.

  Most tellingly of all, Rosanvallon cites Jules Ferry in order to show that his goal was

  ‘to place the Republic above universal suffrage’, to protect it from the passions of

  society.223

  Second, there was little in the actual institutional arrangements of the Third

  Republic that the liberals would have found uncongenial. Certainly this would have

  been the view of many radical republicans, who (as we have seen) felt deeply

  betrayed by the compromises entailed in the outcome. But we can surmise that a

  good few liberals saw the positive benefits of the new constitutional arrangements.

  For example, this would be the conclusion reached from reading Vues sur le

  gouvernement de la France, by Alfred, Duc de Broglie. Broglie’s analysis reworked

  221 Hazareesingh, From Subject to Citizen: The Second Empire and the Emergence of Modern French

  Democracy (Princeton, NJ, 1998), 229.

  222 Ibid. 230.

  223 Rosanvallon, La Démocratie inachévée (2000), 235–41.

  194

  Commerce, Usurpation, and Democracy

  the standard account of how the destructive tendencies of republican democracy

  had led to Bonapartist dictatorship and the loss of liberty, but it concluded with the

  argument that only two types of government were now possible for France: a

  republic informed by constitutional monarchy or a constitutional monarchy in-

  formed by the republic. ‘Every other Republic’, he wrote, ‘is the Convention; every

  other monarchy is the Empire.’224 A similar argument was advanced by the young

  liberal Ernest Duvergier de Hauranne in his call for the acceptance of ‘a conserva-

  tive republic’. Accepting that a republic was inevitable, he argued that the ‘moder-

  ate republicans’ and ‘conservative liberals’ wanted practically the same thing and

  that, in the institutions of the Third Republic, France now had a system of

  representative government that combined liberty with order.225

  Yet, all was clearly not well in the liberal garden. This chapter began with an

  invocation of the praise lavished upon England as the country of commerce and

  liberty. The liberals, most notably Constant, developed this theme in order t
o

  suggest that a new type of liberty was appropriate to the modern age. Whatever

  their complexion, all liberals in France accepted some version of this argument. To

  a greater or lesser degree, they were all prone to Anglophilia. But, with few

  exceptions, they seemed particularly blind to the fact that it was the changes

  wrought upon society by the advance of commerce that were to be deeply

  problematic and that in these circumstances the constitutional palliatives which

  they were recommending were likely to have little effect or appeal. If, to the evident

  dismay of the liberals, the workers and the peasantry persisted in wanting ‘well-

  being’ rather than ‘liberty’, this had much to do with the fact that they were hungry

  and poorly housed and felt themselves to be exploited. Faced with these demands,

  as was revealed by their response to the labour unrest of 1848, the liberals showed

  no desire to give up their free-market assumptions. Adolphe Blanqui, for example,

  insisted that the government should not supply the workers with work, should not

  help them when they were ill, nor provide for their security in old age. Regulations

  on minimum wages and maximum hours were deemed to be excessive interference

  in the workings of the market and thus detrimental to the interests of the

  workers themselves.226 The same message received its most forceful and articulate

  expression in the writings of Frédéric Bastiat.227

  By way of conclusion, therefore, we might return our attention to those writers

  who were prepared to challenge not just the virtues of commerce but also the

  paradigmatic status of English society and government. As we saw in our earlier

  discussion of Eugène Buret and Flora Tristan, there were many cases of this but

  undoubtedly one of the most sustained examples was De la décadence de l’Angleterre,

  224 (1870), p. lxxii.

  225 Ernest Duvergier de Hauranne, La République conservatrice (1873). Duvergier de Hauranne had

  clearly been influenced (like Tocqueville before him) by his visit to America: see Huit Mois en Amérique

  (1866).

  226 Adolphe Blanqui, Des Classes ouvrières en France pendant l’année 1848 (1849). See also Michel

  Chevalier, Question des travailleurs (1848).

  227 In addition to the Œuvres complètes de Frédéric Bastiat, 6 vols. (1862), see two republications of

 

‹ Prev