Book Read Free

Revolution and the Republic

Page 42

by Jeremy Jennings


  Bastiat’s work: Sophismes économiques (2005) and Pamphlets (2009).

  Commerce, Usurpation, and Democracy

  195

  first published in 1850, and written by the radical writer and parliamentary deputy

  Alexandre Ledru-Rollin.228 Turning his back on the ‘exaggerations of anglomania’,

  Ledru-Rollin asserted that England was one enormous aristocracy, ‘the aristocracy

  of the crown, the aristocracy of land, the aristocracy of business’, and that England’s

  famous liberties gave the people nothing. All aspects of English society came in for

  this treatment, but by far the greater part of Ledru-Rollin’s text was taken up with

  an account of the conditions of the working class. In a series of sketches of the lives

  of the various occupational groups, he painted a heart-felt picture of the poverty

  and degradation resulting from the relentless competition associated with the

  industrial system. Behind the official prosperity, he argued, lay a universal misery

  and imminent bankruptcy. England, in sum, was a country that had been destroyed

  and enslaved by the greed of its aristocratic classes. With patriotic fervour, he thus

  announced that England’s ‘half principles of civil, commercial, political and reli-

  gious liberty’ had to be rejected by France, the ‘daughter of Rousseau’, and that

  such a rejection would amount to nothing less than the destruction of England

  itself. The two nations, he proclaimed, were ‘going in diametrically opposed

  directions’. France was rushing towards ‘the future of equality’ whilst England

  fortified itself ‘more than ever in the privileges of the past’. France, he therefore

  proclaimed, should stay true to her particular genius and call for ‘social justice on

  earth, the justice of brothers’.229

  That these were widely held sentiments can be shown by referring to the Grand

  Dictionnaire Universel of 1867. The so-called Dictionnaire Larousse had a substan-

  tial entry on England, running to fifteen pages. It began with a largely factual

  account of England’s geography, history, and culture, but at the end Larousse took

  the liberty of adding an imaginary and intriguing discussion between the two

  archetypal figures of France and England, Jacques Bonhomme and John Bull. To

  aid his readers, Larousse kindly explained the context in which this discussion was

  taking place.

  ‘Two entirely opposed currents of opinion about England are evident in France’,

  Larousse wrote: ‘One is very sympathetic to the laws and the constitution of

  England; the other, which has its source in long-standing national enmity, sees in

  the Englishman only a rival, an enemy that has to be fought to the bitter end.’

  Jacques Bonhomme, Larousse explained, ‘is afflicted with an incurable anglopho-

  bia’. Thus, if he had Jacques Bonhomme accept that England possessed a certain

  amount of power and material wealth, John Bull was quickly informed that the

  English were ‘one of the most wretched people on earth; despite your hard work

  you languish in poverty and abjection. . . . Your women throw themselves in their

  thousands into prostitution and your men are stupefied by hard liquor.’ In no other

  country was the struggle for life so hard and defeat so tragic. The causes of this

  miserable existence were well-known. England’s government was a ‘veritable oli-

  garchy’ and a prey to a ‘devouring aristocracy’. In the name of a respect for the law,

  injustice and arbitrary government were inflicted upon the poor. Liberty existed

  228 2 vols. (1850).

  229 Ibid. ii. 272.

  196

  Commerce, Usurpation, and Democracy

  only for the upper classes. In sum, English civilization had remained impervious to

  demands for the moral and physical emancipation of the lower classes. ‘The France

  of 1793’, Jacques Bonhomme concluded, ‘denounced your nation to the world as

  the modern Carthage and the enemy of humanity. The illusions of Montesquieu,

  of the philosophes and of the constitutional school vanished at that point. From

  cruel experience we had come to appreciate the lack of sincerity to be found in your

  liberalism.’ A very good case could be made for arguing that, over the long term, the

  rhetorical force of these sentiments was to have far more appeal than liberal calls to

  commerce, moderation, and individual liberty.

  5

  Universalism, the Nation, and Defeat

  I

  Prévost-Paradol concluded La France nouvelle with an essay on geopolitics.1 None

  of the maladies afflicting France, he ventured, were necessarily fatal but it would

  take a near superhuman effort for France to retain the position of eminence she had

  occupied over recent centuries. The context for this remark was Prussia’s crushing

  victory over Austria at the battle of Sadowa in 1866 and France’s failure to respond

  to Prussia’s imposition of its hegemony over the other members of the German

  confederation.

  Two aspects of Prévost-Paradol’s argument stand out. The first was the

  contention that France had been mistaken in building her foreign policy around

  the principle of nationalities. This principle, Prévost-Paradol explained, laid

  down ‘identity of race and language and the consent of the population’ as

  the conditions necessary to legitimize the annexation of a territory.2 Neither,

  he argued, could serve France’s interests, but they could allow Prussia to forge

  the union of a single state composed of 51 million inhabitants. In the unlikely

  event of success against Prussia, he therefore suggested, it would be best for

  France to put this ‘famous principle’ to one side and to base her claims simply

  upon the rights of the victor. Next, Prévost-Paradol saw all too plainly what

  the outcome of defeat by Prussia would be. France, he surmised, would not be

  removed from the map—a general attachment to the idea of a balance of

  power in Europe would ensure this—nor would she necessarily lose Alsace

  and Lorraine, but she would lose ‘the means of opposing this dismemberment

  on the day that our triumphant rival would judge it to be practicable and

  useful to its interests, and this day would not be long in coming’.3 It was not

  impossible, Prévost-Paradol wrote, that war would be avoided, but, he avowed,

  France and Prussia had the look of two steam trains heading at full speed

  towards each other. The image was to prove to be all too accurate.

  This was only part of the gloomy scenario facing France. Beyond Europe’s

  borders, Prévost-Paradol continued, ‘[t]wo rival powers, but which from the

  point of view of race, language, manners and laws amount to one power, England

  1 Prévost-Paradol, La France nouvelle (1869).

  2 Ibid. 380.

  3 Ibid. 383.

  198

  Universalism, the Nation, and Defeat

  and the United States, dominate the remainder of the planet’.4 Here once more

  France’ recent history had been one of woeful decline and ineptitude and it was this

  that led Prévost-Paradol to predict that the dominance of the ‘Anglo-Saxon race’

  would only grow in the future, leaving the European powers (including a united

  Germany) with a few unimportant colonial outposts. From this Prévost-Paradol

 
reached two important conclusions. If France were to survive in anything like a

  meaningful form ‘the number of French people must increase sufficiently rapidly in

  order to maintain a level of equilibrium between our power and that of the other

  great nations on the earth’.5 Next, France had to make the most of ‘the supreme

  opportunity’ provided by Algeria. There, he argued, was a colony that was fertile,

  not too far away from ‘la mère patrie’ and easy to defend. In addition, from this base

  colonization could be extended into Morocco and Tunisia so as to construct ‘a

  Mediterranean Empire’ appropriate to France’s pride and stature. Only two ob-

  stacles, Prévost-Paradol believed, stood in the way of this plan: France’s continuing

  uncertainty about what type of regime to construct in Algeria, and ‘the Arab

  people’. ‘It is time’, Prévost-Paradol responded unambiguously, ‘to establish

  laws in Africa conceived with regard to the extension of French colonization . . . this

  is French territory which as soon as possible must be peopled, possessed, and

  cultivated by the French’.6

  Within two years of these lines being written, France’s armies had been routed

  by those of Prussia and the eastern provinces of Alsace and Lorraine had been lost.

  Later, and by way of compensation for her national humiliation, France duly set

  out to construct her Mediterranean Empire, a strategy that was to have immense

  long-term costs and consequences. After the Franco-Prussian war there could be

  no denying the stark realities that Prévost-Paradol had only been able to guess at,

  and in these troubled circumstances, as Prévost-Paradol had already recommended,

  the validity and utility of the principle of nationalities had to be reconsidered. Just

  as striking was the pessimistic tone struck by Prévost-Paradol. Where once, he

  suggested, the question would have been whether France could hold her own

  against the combined forces of the European states, it now seemed doubtful that

  she could even stand up to Prussia alone. The ‘glorious name of old France’ seemed

  but a bitter memory.

  The contrast with the mood of the previous century could not have been more

  marked. As Colin Jones has written, ‘[i]n many senses, the eighteenth century was

  France’s century’.7 The country bounced back from the gruelling wars that had

  characterized the final years of Louis XIV’s reign and was able ‘to imprint its influence

  on every aspect of eighteenth-century European life’. France had the largest popula-

  tion of any of the great powers and experienced long-term economic growth and

  improving living standards. Paris remained at the epicentre of the intellectual world

  and the eighteenth century was an age when Europe spoke French.8 It was not only

  the language of international diplomacy but also the language of civilization, of the

  4 Prévost-Paradol, La France nouvelle (1869), 397.

  5 Ibid. 413.

  6 Ibid. 418.

  7 The Great Nation: France from Louis XV to Napoleon (London: 2003), p. xiii.

  8 Marc Fumaroli, Quand l’Europe parlait Français (2001).

  Universalism, the Nation, and Defeat

  199

  arts, and of the republic of letters. To speak French, in this sense, was to be a party

  to the aspirations of humanity as a whole. As Jones himself acknowledges, this did

  not mean that France was a country without weaknesses. The monarchical system

  did not adapt and gradually imploded, before going bankrupt. There were signifi-

  cant losses of overseas territory, especially after the Seven Years War, when France

  was ignominiously booted out of both India and North America by the British.

  However, revenge was swiftly exacted through French support of the American

  colonists. Most importantly, despite the upheaval and turmoil produced by the

  Revolution, at the end of the century France had succeeded in greatly extending her

  borders. In short, what in retrospect looked like Britain’s inevitable rise to become

  the world’s dominant power in the nineteenth century did not look quite so certain

  from the vantage point of the windmill placed on the top of the hill at Valmy at the

  moment when France’s revolutionary army put to rout their Prussian opponents on

  12 September 1792.

  There could be no better description of the manner in which France was

  constructed as a territory than that provided by Daniel Nordman.9 His is an

  account that recognizes the importance of properly understanding the historic

  meaning of such words as ‘frontier’ and ‘limit’ as a necessary prelude to grasping

  the intricate processes through which France progressively extended her borders

  and removed the foreign enclaves that existed within them. It was largely during the

  reign of Louis XIV, and specifically after the Treaty of Munster in 1648, that

  France’s territory became fixed. Sovereignty over Alsace was confirmed by treaty in

  1648 and again by the treaty of Ryswick in 1697 (thereby establishing the Rhine as

  the frontier between France and the Holy Roman Empire), over Artois and

  Roussillon through the Treaty of the Pyrenees in 1659, over the Franche-Comté

  in 1678, and over Strasbourg in 1681. These extensions to French territory were

  usually the outcome of successful military campaigns. The pattern of acquisition

  changed significantly in the eighteenth century, when the most noteworthy addi-

  tions were Lorraine in 1766 and Corsica in 1768. Through painstakingly detailed

  investigation, servants of the monarchy sought to establish sovereign claim upon

  often quite small areas of territory in cases where sovereignty was either indetermi-

  nate or contested. Relying usually upon either legal or historic evidence, the

  enterprise was carried out in a spirit of conciliation and exchange. Thus, despite

  politically useful myths to the contrary, the borders of France were relatively well

  defined and beyond dispute when the Revolution got under way in 1789.

  Two points stand out from this analysis. The first is that, although there was a

  long-standing sense of the physical limits of France—a sense that at its most

  rudimentary rested upon a classical understanding of the territory of the Gauls as

  covering that of present-day France, Belgium, and northern Italy—the actual

  concept of ‘natural frontiers’ did not make its appearance until the early nineteenth

  century. Just as significantly, the concept of ‘linguistic frontier’ did not manifest

  itself until much later, probably around the time of the Second Empire. Indeed, the

  9 Frontières de France: De l’espace au territoire XVIe–XIXe siècle (1998).

  200

  Universalism, the Nation, and Defeat

  language of the inhabitants was virtually absent from earlier territorial considera-

  tions, and did not figure significantly during the period of the Revolution. Nor

  indeed could it, as linguistic maps of Europe were at best sketchy and of little

  practical, political use. So too it was only during the period of the First Empire that

  systematic efforts were made to provide a linguistic map of France. The fact was,

  however, that from the beginning of the nineteenth century language became

  increasingly associated with nationality.

  As Claude Nicolet has remarked, in a French cont
ext the word ‘Nation’ must be

  placed amongst the category of ‘mots voyageurs’, words central to political dis-

  course whose sense has changed significantly with passage of time.10 In the

  eighteenth century it had at best an indeterminate meaning. Prior to the Revolution

  of 1789 a person possessed not French nationality but ‘the quality of being French’

  and this was determined not by place of birth but by the bond of parentage.11 Thus

  Mirabeau, for example, could speak of ‘la nation provençale’, whilst Robespierre in

  Arras could publish an appeal to ‘la nation artésienne’, thereby maintaining its use

  as a term to describe a collection of individuals held together by a set of common

  interests. Voltaire and Montesquieu used the term in a purely descriptive, sociolog-

  ical fashion, as denoting a set of people held together by shared experiences and

  customs; whilst Rousseau, once again ahead of the game, could speak of all peoples

  as possessing ‘a national character’.12 For Rousseau, the existence of the nation

  preceded that of the State but it would be through the State that the sense of being a

  member of the nation would be strengthened and put to good use.13

  It was outside the confines of discussions among the philosophes that the word

  came to take definitive shape. There is much that could, and arguably should, be

  said about the general manner in which over time the nation replaced God as the

  source of all legitimate authority. With God, although not yet dead, now deemed to

  be absent from human affairs, there was a felt-need for a new organizational

  principle capable of generating loyalty among individual members of the commu-

  nity and for some this dubious role fell to the nation. So much we will take as given

  by way of general background to the emergence of nationalism as an ideology,

  preferring rather to focus upon the specific context in which the word ‘nation’ came

  to prominence in eighteenth-century France.

  The first thing to note is that the monarchy itself played an important role in

  fostering national sentiment. There has been a long-established view that prior to

  the French Revolution wars did not arouse strong national emotions. However,

  David Bell has shown that the literature of the Seven Years War, far from portraying

 

‹ Prev